YOU ARE DOWNLOADING DOCUMENT

Please tick the box to continue:

Transcript
Page 1: The Cause of Freedom

1

The Cause of Freedom

MA Dissertation: Cultural Studies 2012-3

Adviser: Tom Bunyard

3326254801

Page 2: The Cause of Freedom

2

Acknowledgements:

I would like to thank my friends and family for all their moral support,

and my advisor for the incredible amount of patience and care he gave to me.

Page 3: The Cause of Freedom

3

1. The Two Formulas of Freedom

Millions huddled around glowing screens to listen to

President Barack Obama's inauguration speech, the

culmination of a process that is in itself an instantiation

of the peoples' freedom, their freedom of choice. After

some brief exchanges of smiles and applause, Obama and the

crowd before him settled into a spirit of solemnity. With a

gaze cast far off into the distance, as if he was genuinely

envisioning the distant past and tracing its trajectory

forward upon each glance returned to the audience, he began

his speech with a stentorious voice:

"Each time we gather to inaugurate a President we bear

witness to the enduring strength of our Constitution. We

Page 4: The Cause of Freedom

4

affirm the promise of our democracy. What makes us

exceptional—what makes us American—is our allegiance to an

idea articulated in a declaration made more than two

centuries ago: 'We hold these truths to be self-evident,

that all men are created equal; that they are endowed by

their Creator with certain unalienable rights; that among

these are life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness.'

Today we continue a never-ending journey to bridge the

meaning of those words with the realities of our time. For

history tells us that while these truths may be self-

evident, they've never been self-executing; that while

freedom is a gift from God, it must be secured by His people

here on Earth"

From here it's all agenda details. It is this last

bromidic sentence given here that concerns us. It blazons a

far-reaching departure from the ontological premise of

liberalism predicated on the subject's "self-evident", viz.

pre-given, freedom. Strictly speaking, it displays a

Foucauldian discernment of liberalism which applies

governmental practices to produce a free subject by

actualising "conditions of freedom" (Foucault 1979: 63):

freedom is ontologically contingent and hence "must be

secured" by the people and their government (Odysseos 750).

Nikolas Rose's book Powers of Freedom, written in 2004,

thoroughly analyses Foucault's notion of freedom as not only

Page 5: The Cause of Freedom

5

produced by a liberal form of government, but also as a

necessary resource for its operation. Thus while freedom

does serve as an ideal, as a "weapon in 'saying no to power'

", it is also a mode of organisation and regulation — "a

certain way of administering a population that depends upon

the capacities of free individuals" (Rose 1999: 64).

Typically, freedom in liberal politics "is structured by the

opposition between freedom and government"; in other words

the liberal ideology views the maximisation of individual

liberty and the power of the state as constituting an

inverse relationship (Rose 1999: 62). Francis Fukuyama

describes the dynamic of this relationship as being

determined by the individual's capacity to self-govern: if

they fail to discipline themselves in a manner conducive to

the harmonious co-existence with others and their

environment, then they will require a stronger and more

coercive state to maintain order (Fukuyama 1996: 357-8).

Thus, as Rose later explicates, freedom as an ideal and

freedom as a mode of organisation and regulation can also be

thought of as freedom as a formulae of resistance and

freedom as a formulae of power, respectively. As Fukuyama's

description of the relationship between governors and

governed shows, freedom as the formulae of power does not

function solely as hierarchical domination; it is not a

relationship of absolute control. Additionally, power is

not a "thing" that one can posses, lack, or can be directly

Page 6: The Cause of Freedom

6

pointed to. It is internal, not external, to relationships

— agency is always involved to a certain degree (Foucault

1978). Put differently, liberalism utilizes freedom as an

ethos of government: one governs others via the government

of the self 1 and, in effect, brings them together in a

bilateral continuity 2. Foucault explains the government of

the self as an ethical self-understanding that distinctively

operates via "technologies of the self". For example,

neoliberal forms of government coercively deploy practices

of self-government, under the guise of economic necessity,

to make individuals more responsible. By taking the least

amount of responsibility for all citizens and non-citizens

as possible, many serious problems with a social bearing —

illness, unemployment, poverty, etc —are unilaterally

shifted from the government to individuals so that they

become issues of "self-care" (Lemke 2001:12). Philip

Mirowski, a historian of economic thought, brilliantly

encapsulated how such policies are duplicitously posed as

liberating:

1 the government of the self contains practices that, as Wendy Brown states, "exceed express state action and orchestrate the subject's conduct toward himself or herself" (Brown 2005)2 Foucault deduces from one of the earliest texts on governmentality — La Mothe Le Vaver — that there is a continuity of power that flows in both upward and downward directions: if a person is to govern well, he must "first learn how to govern himself". When he governs himself well,his subjects will behave as they should (Foucault 1994: 206-7).

Page 7: The Cause of Freedom

7

"Hayek hit upon the brilliant notion of developing the 'double truth' doctrine of neoliberalism — namely, an elite would be tutored to understand the deliciously transgressiveSchmittian necessity of repressing democracy 3, while the masses would be regaled with ripping tales of 'rolling back the nanny state' and being set 'free to choose'..." (Mirowski 2009: 444)

This extra layer of truth, that gives governmental and self-

governmental practices rhetorically persuasive meaning, is

ideology.

1.2 The Vehicle of the Formulae: Ideology

3 Schmitt's disdain for democracy specifically targeted liberal democracy, as he believed the principles of liberalism — mainly the concept of individual freedom, which imports pluralism — to be heterogeneous, and therefore incompatible, with the modern democratic logic of group identity and equivalence (Mouffe 1993: 133). His view ofthe liberal relation to truth was one where the arrival of a truth, uponwhich a decision can be founded, is always deferred as a result of the lack of collective identity encouraged by the liberal notion of individual freedom. The underlying assumption in liberalism is that endless competition of ideas/opinion will effortlessly produce harmony (Schmitt 34). Conversely, for Schmitt the logic of democracy infers an identity between the "government and governed", which is "perfectly compatible with "Bolshevism and Fascism are, like all dictatorships, certainly antiliberal but not necessarily antidemocratic" (Schmitt 16). A strong fear of totalitarianism runs throughout Hayek's texts; and he, like Schmitt, has pointed out the danger facing the generally accepted types of democracies of becoming totalitarian during the mid 20th century. Somewhat ironically, Hayek was in support of liberal dictatorships and told an interviewer for El Mercurio: "Personally I prefer a liberal dictator to democratic government lacking liberalism (El Mercurio 1981)." Since Hayek pioneered much of neoliberal thought, it is not surprising that there is a shared antidemocratic stance.

Page 8: The Cause of Freedom

8

What Foucault, and consequently Rose, are too quick to

dismiss is the question of how technologies of the self

intelligibly emerge and reproduce themselves. That is, by

performing a certain set of actions, one also assigns a

specific meaning or belief to them: the logic of which

Althusser sets forth, borrowing from Pascal; "pray, kneel

down, and you shall believe, faith will arrive by itself"

(Althusser 2012: 8). Contrary to Foucault's disregard of

ideology as being nothing more than a relative effect of a

material infrastructure 4, I argue that they have reciprocal

material import. Ideologies are internally embedded in

institutions and co-produce relations of power; they provide

people with "rules of practical conduct and moral

behaviour", and is the equivalent to a 'religion understood

in the secular sense of a unity of faith between a

conception of the world and a corresponding norm of conduct'

" 5. In this way, they too are a mode of organising and

regulating individuals in society and enable both individual

and collective action in advancing goals or making decisions6. Of course, this is not to say that ideologies positively

4 see (Barret 1992: 123). Not to mention Zizek's disparagment of Foucault for failing to bridge how his mechanisms of "micro power" in Discipline and Punish connect to the "spectre of Power"; and, as a result, isforced to resort to drawing a confused schematisation of overtly complexarrangements of power and its mechanisms (Zizek 9). 5 the single quotation marks contained within the quotation are from Antonio Gramsci's prison notebooks, see (Simon 1991: 65). 6 A recent study showed U.S. Supreme Court Justices' votes correlated 0.80 to their ideological values when using a system of measures that precluded their actual voting record, see Cover and Segal. On the

Page 9: The Cause of Freedom

9

cause a certain behaviour or the reverse of this proposition7; but, as Gordon Wood notes, while ideas may not cause

behaviour in a way that economic or psychological factors

allegedly do, they are always present — "we do not behave

without them" (Wood 629). Our world and actions are made

intelligible through the meanings we assign to them, making

them easier to produce and reproduce. These meanings

concatenate to produce other significations: they

"constitute our ideas, our beliefs, our ideology, our

culture" (Wood 631). Likewise, our language and cultural

conventions circumscribe the meanings we create, to which

Wood adds:

"It is in this sense that culture or ideology creates behaviour. It does so by forcing us to describe our behaviour in its terms" (Wood 631).

When signifiers are subsumed into an ideology they are

given different connotations and values. Within liberalism

freedom is the superlative value. Moreover, the dual

operation of freedom is characteristic of liberalism 8; but,

organising and regulating functions of ideologies, see also Freeden pg 14.7 not to mention that proving an ideology caused a specific behaviour would be practically impossible. 8 It is clear that Rose's two conceptions of freedom — as an ideal and as power — is formulated after the analysis of liberalism that Foucault made in his lecture series The Birth of Biopolitics: "Liberalism is also a tool for the criticism of reality, from a previous governmentality from whichone is trying to get free. Thus liberalism can be used as a regulative schema of governmental practice and as a means to radically oppose them

Page 10: The Cause of Freedom

10

as has been suggested beforehand, both function through an

ideology. For better or for worse, an ideology postulates a

particular world view, which in turn presupposes a certain

ordering of the world, including the propriety of certain

social structures. Althusser theorises this is how regimes

manage subjects to preserve their power: an ideology

presents a non-epistemological explanation of how the world

has to be and is, and along its lines a subject finds his

position in that order as necessary and natural. Freedom

inscribed in an ideology, then, is used as an ideal to

justify almost any governmental action or inaction; it

becomes an unconditional and objective good that must, at

any cost, be "secured". In defiance of liberalism's

conditional freedom, Sartre posits that it is intrinsically

part our being as our transcendence that surpasses all that

is and necessary: to treat it as an external effect coming

from the realisation of certain conditions is to be in a

state of bad faith. Serious problems arise when ideology's

defining quality of belief is converted into a finalising

rationalisation of certain natural or social orders and

ceases to be perceived as an ideology. Being able to

identify what meanings in our immediate experience are

ideological make critiques thinkable and new possibilities

imaginable. When freedom as a "weapon to say no to power"

and freedom as a "formulae of power" converge into common

(Foucault 1979: 320).

Page 11: The Cause of Freedom

11

sense, it becomes nearly impossible to perceive power

relations.

2. A Genealogy of the Liberal Value of Freedom

Freedom has a particularly predominant place in the

psyche of Americans, such that it is unquestionably felt to

be common sense a la Gramsci, as noted by David Harvey.

America's liberal democratic institutional foundations

indicate that a heightened, reverential feeling towards

liberty is far from being an inconsequential outcome of this

heritage. However, while the popular devotion to this ideal

has been more or less consistent, its meaning and the

material manifestations in its name have been otherwise.

Liberal intellectuals have adroitly taken up the cause of

freedom; and, their interpretations have been engineered and

employed to buttressed state apparatuses, extracting consent

to be ruled through the alluring medium of ideology. While

Althusser's theory of ideology contributes an effective

description of how ideology rationalises a modality of

governing and a corresponding subjectivity, he generally

deemphasizes the determinative role of the intellectual in

Page 12: The Cause of Freedom

12

not only developing ideologies 9, but in making them into

"compelling interpretations of actual lived experience"

(Morgan 2013). When an ideology achieves popular consent,

it becomes a hegemonic ideology. The means of hegemony are

not ones of unalloyed structural force, but of gaining a

position of intellectual and moral leadership:

"A social group can, indeed must, already exercise 'leadership' before winning governmental power (this is indeed one of the political conditions for the winning of such power); it subsequently becomes dominant when it exercises power, but even if it holds it firmly in its grasp, it must continue to 'lead' as well" (Gramsci 1971 p 57-8).

One way to untie the Gordian knot of common sense

binding the two formulae of freedom together is to examine

the intellectual ideations of freedom against their

relatively coeval political practices, and other historical

socio-economic contingencies. This is approximately what

Foucault's genealogical method focuses on, and will lead us

to an account of freedom within the context of neoliberalism

— what I argue is still the ideological lens through which 9 An amusing anecdote, while it is one that digresses from our American context, recorded by John Ranelagh in his book Thatcher's People: An Insider's Account of the Politics, Power, and Personalities exhibits this point. During a Conservative Party policy meeting, a member was arguing for a "middle way" as the most practical one for the party when Thatcher, obviously frustrated by his position, ripped out a copy of Friedrich von Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty out of her briefcase, interrupted his speech by holding it up and declaring, "This is what we believe", then concluded her point by slamming it down on the table (Ranelagh 1991).

Page 13: The Cause of Freedom

13

America understands freedom presently. Furthermore, the

neoliberal ideology is one that "borrows ideas from the past

and then reinterprets them on a new ideological terrain"

(Turner 7). However, the appropriation, recombination, and

reinterpretation instantiated in neoliberal ideology is not

unique to it alone, as most ideologies can be said to have

sprung from an amalgam of past archetypes. Henceforth, I

will survey the quintessential thinkers of liberalism who

have markedly influenced its American version — elucidating

a basic schematic of their thought in relation to the core

concept of freedom — to illuminate freedom in its current

neoliberal form. Close attention will be paid to how the

interrelation between the two formulae of freedom gave rise

to its present form; as the thinkers explored have arrived

at their formulations in reaction to certain regimes power,

which are eventually embraced by new institutions of power.

During the course of our genealogy, thematic preconditions

for freedom in a liberal society will emerge — property

rights, the rule of law, democracy, homo oeconomicus, and

homo juridicus — that unify the liberal model in general.

However, the emphasis given to each varies within the four

ideologies addressed, which are: Lockean liberalism,

classical liberalism, liberal progressivism, and

neoliberalism. After these investigations I will be in a

position to advance toward a three-pronged critique of

liberal ideology with special attention given to its

Page 14: The Cause of Freedom

14

neoliberal configuration. My critique will not proceed from

weighing its theory against its practice — as many critics

of neoliberalism have done, most outstandingly David

Harvey's A Brief History of Neoliberalism — but as a contestation of

its instrumentalisation of freedom by contrasting it with

Sartre's ontology of freedom.

2.2 Locke's "Beasts of Prey" and the Sword of Law

The Law of Nature and Lockean Liberalism

“That these are our grievances which we have thus laid before his majesty, with that freedom of language and sentiment which becomes a free people claiming their rights as derived from the laws of nature, and not as the gift of their chief magistrate.” 

— Thomas Jefferson

Unfortunately, beginning with hackneyed historical

espousals are unavoidable, if one is to give a luminous

narrative of the development of the liberal value of freedom

up to its present form. I have already indicated that the

notion of freedom is particularly embedded in America. It

is possible to speculate endlessly as to why this is so, but

a choice reason would be that feudalism never took hold 10.

America was a tabula rasa (from the colonists' point of view) 10 The feudal structuring of society — with its rigid aristocratic and clerical hierarchies — is extremely antithetical to liberal notions of individual freedom.

Page 15: The Cause of Freedom

15

where one could escape feudal power structures (McGown 2007:

99). In place of the Church and the monarchical hierarchy,

liberalism itself was the supreme authoritative doctrine in

America 11; "it was the political equivalent of a civic

religion" (Turner 2008: 31). Liberalism, in the widest

sense of the term, can be defined as "the self-limitation of

governmental reason"; the central aims of which is the

promotion of individual freedom (Foucault 1978: 20) (McGown

2007: 24). To be sure, the ambiguity ingrained in its

idealism left one with room to expand its practical

potential beyond one's current situation, unmasking

illusions imposing the needfulness of oppressive measures.

Before the conflict between the British Empire and its

colonies piqued, the denizens of the latter petitioned their

grievances within the confines of the British constitution,

invoking "their rights as British subjects" (Foner 13). As

imperialist oppression progressed, colonists began to

perceive the whole system as corrupt and saw the need to

build for themselves a new foundation for the protection of

their freedom. Ironically, their ideas were built upon

prominent British philosophers, mostly from the work of John

Locke (McGowan 2007: 23). John Locke wrote the Two Treatises of11 Needless to say, the Puritan settlers also brought with them spiritual and moral imperatives that conceptualised freedom in a Stoic manner, viz. as being actualised by self-restraint. Though it did not last long — Eric Foner places the date at 1750 — and was soon after followed by a Anglo-American Protestant reading poised against "tyranny and popery", which was conveniently aligned with the liberal notion of freedom (Foner 5).

Page 16: The Cause of Freedom

16

Government before the Glorious Revolution of 1688 12, and its

content gives a reasoned, philosophical basis for

revolutionary action; therefore, it was a salient

inspiration for the American Revolution (Turner 2008: 33).

The First Treatise of Government is a polemical critique of

the Divine Right of Kings against Sir Robert Filmer's

argument for divine and absolute monarchy premised on

Filmer's belief that man is not "naturally free" — using a

hermeneutical reading of the Bible to metaphorically to

fortify this claim. Whilst this subsidizes the assertion

that Locke was authentically writing for revolutionary

change, it did not furnish a detailed account of his concept

of freedom nor its enabling framework (MacPherson 1980:

viii).

It is within his Second Treatise of Government where he

resolutely advances a conception of freedom deduced from his

theories on the state of war, state of nature, and civil society. These

various states are ordered to relatively correspond to the

events surrounding the American Revolution; and concurrently

freedom moves from a negative form of freedom to a loosely

positive one (when founding a new government), returning to

the former upon the foundation of new polity. As the British

12 The first of John Locke's Two Treatises of Government was believed to be written several years before the Glorious Revolution of 1688, with suspicions that the second wasn't written wholly after the revolution. It may be surmised, then, that the historical context did not so much imply that the Two Treatises were justifications of the revolution but a call for one (Locke 1988: 47).

Page 17: The Cause of Freedom

17

Empire escalated legislative coercion to force submission,

the atmosphere grew tempestuous and Locke's condemnations of

tyranny briskly and passionately circulated among the

patriots:

"Whensoever therefore the legislative shall transgress this fundamental rule of society; and either by ambition, fear, folly or corruption, endeavour to grasp themselves, or put into the hands of any other, an absolute power over the lives, liberties, and estates of the people; by this breach of trust they forfeit the power"

Upon this breach the people enter into a state of war, the

people have the right to use force to fight such tyranny, as

is made dramatically vivid in the following passage:

"..one may destroy a man who makes war upon him, or has discovered an enmity to his being, for the same reason that he may kill a wolf or a lion; because such men are not underthe ties of the commonlaw of reason, have no other rule, butthat of force and violence, and so may be treated as beasts of prey" (Locke 1980: II § 16).

While Locke believed the human psyche was innately

prone to the warlike vicissitudes of pain and pleasure 13,

man could, by his intellect, discover the Law of Nature, which

13 Locke's explanation of human motivation, or human nature, is scrupulously rendered in his Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Synoptically put, he denies the existence of innate moral laws and instead, in a Hobbesian fashion, states that man's innate inclinations are in his appetites — "a desire of happiness and an aversion to misery"(Locke 1690: 1.2).

Page 18: The Cause of Freedom

18

is the Law of Reason (Locke 1988: 95). It is reason which

gives man the positive freedom to form societies and create

polities. Locke stipulates, however, that man's freedom,

bestowed upon him by the light of reason, cannot be

exercised until one has reached a level of maturity — of

which children lacked and "savages" were permanently

incapable of reaching (Klausen 760) (Locke 1980: II § 61).

Thus the settlers had no obligations to their ancestral

polity, i.e. imperial Britain, nor to the Native Americans

who inhabited the land in which they wished to establish a

new polity. For Locke the state of nature was more than a

mentally simulated metaphysical space but America herself —

where there was "room enough" to create a new polity, and,

therefore, shrewdly justified the white man's territorial

expansion 14.

As mentioned briefly in the preceding paragraph, the

Law of Reason also serves to ideologically regulate and

organise people under laws that are in adherence to the

liberal inflection of the raison d'Etat — "the self-

limitation of government". Locke was unambiguous about the

fact that freedom could only really be enjoyed with the

protection of law with which disputes could be 'peacefully'

14 In Locke's view the Native Americans did not have legitimate polities: "in many parts of America there was no government at all"; thus, from the settler's point of view, America was a blank slate whereupon they could establish a new sovereign (Locke 1980: § 102). Seealso (Klausen 760)

Page 19: The Cause of Freedom

19

settled by a third party 15. Locke has already implied that

freedom is not licentious abandonment to one's innate

desires. A dependable and veritable freedom is being able

to "dispose and order as he lists, his persons, actions, and

possessions", this could not exist "where there is no law"

(Locke 1980: II § 57). Only the limiting framework of the

law is an effectual prophylactic against the formation

tyrannical governments or individual paroxysms; therefore,

it is best to give up the executive freedom one has in the

state of nature and live in accordance with the rule of law.

Within a society, which for Locke is defined by consenting

to and living by the mediating authority of the law, one is

ensured a negative freedom from the arbitrary will of others.

Prioritising the common good — such that individual

interests are transcended (limited) in its name — was keenly

in line with the republicanism of Thomas Jefferson and James

Madison (McGowan 14). The concentration of power was

preventively battled on all fronts, and the Bill of Rights

reflected the republican imperative to control the tyranny

of the majority by enumerating unalienable rights. John

McGowan, an American distinguished professor of the

15 While this seems to be parallel to Hobbe's argument for the creation of the state, there is a subtle difference in Locke. Locke, unlike Hobbes, did not identify the State of Nature with a State of War. He believed that overall, men in the state of nature recognised the Law of Nature, and, therefore, morally conducted themselves accordingly, i.e. took it upon themselves not to harm others' "life, liberty, or possessions" (Locke 1980: II § 8). Nonetheless, he did estimate that the State of Nature could degenerate into State of War.

Page 20: The Cause of Freedom

20

Humanities, enthusiastically defends the wisdom of the

Constitutions' most well-known drafters in creating a

public/private sphere with private property rights. He

argue that since citizens are able to derive their

livelihood by means other than the state, they could better

stand up to the state (McGowan 27). The rule of law's main

objective is to protect property rights, including

individuals — "every man has property in his own person"

(Locke 1980: II § 27).

Lockean liberalism and the republicanism of the

founding fathers ideologically functioned to not only incite

revolution and erect a new government charged with producing

freedom, it also supplied the rationale for unbound

capitalist accumulation as well as an inchoate subjectivity

hinging on self-interest. Political scientist C.B.

MacPherson delineated three limitations on the accumulation

of property in Locke's Second Treatise:

"First, a man may appropriate as much as leaves 'enough, andas good' for others...[insomuch as] each man has a right to his preservation and hence to appropriating the necessities of his life. Secondly, as much as any one can make use of to any advantage of life before it spoils...Thirdly, the rightful appropriation appears to be limited to the amount aman can procure with his own labour" (MacPherson 201)

Since the first premise entitles each man the right to

secure his life, there is no need to garner the consent of

Page 21: The Cause of Freedom

21

others; the bounty of the earth was given to mankind in

common and by the necessity of life man must be able to

appropriate them. Thereby the European yeomen could justify

intruding upon Native American lands. Historically we know

that this is not a wholly satisfactory validation, because

it was often the case that the Europeans took more than was

necessary to protect their lives and could acquire single-

handedly by their own labour, breaking the third limitation.

Money, Locke admitted in sections 36 and 50 of the Second

Treatise, could store value, and, as MacPherson aptly notes,

it transcends the spoilage limitation 16. He also concedes

that the limitation of "enough, and as good" may be

circumvented, insofar as Locke reckoned an enclosed piece of

land can yield "ten times more than those which are yielded

by an acre of land of equal richness lying waste in common"

(Locke 1980: II § 37). From this observation, Locke

concluded that even if "enough and as good" is not left to

others in an equivalent form, e.g. land, "enough and as

good" is left in the form of commodities (Locke 1980: II §

16 Locke's original limitations do not invalidate money, because consentto the use of money is "tacit":

"...it is plain, that Men have agreed to disproportionate and unequal Possession of the Earth, they having by tacit and voluntary consent found out a way, how a man may fairly possess more land than he himself can use the product of, by receiving in exchange for the overplus, Gold and Silver, which may be hoarded up without injury to anyone" (Locke 1980: II § 50).

see also (MacPherson 208)

Page 22: The Cause of Freedom

22

37). He even goes so far as to say that by taking land and

making it more productive, one is making a greater

contribution to society due to the surplus created. What's

more is that once the great American tabla rasa has been

covered in proprietary demarcations, it wasn't problematic

to permit the alienation of the landless wage worker's or

slave's labour: "the turfs my servant has cut...become my

property", since the turfs were removed from the common

state they were in by "my" labour originally (Locke 1980:

xvii).

Why did Locke allow for so many contradictions in his

theory of property? While one should always point out

personal reasons with caution, his logical contortions do

bend easily and favorably with his mercantilist background;

he desired the rapid accumulation of gold not only for its

own sake but to "drive trade" (MacPherson 205). MacPherson

also avers that it gives a moral foundation for bourgeois

appropriation by positing that man completely owns his

'labour' — owing none of its fruits to anyone besides whom

he so chooses — and, in so doing, also gives an affirmative

moral basis for a capitalist market society (MacPherson

221).

From Locke's Two Treatises the aim of freedom is secured

through three elements: one is property, and the other two

are the subjectivities of homo oeconomicus and homo

juridicus. Both of these subjectivities are not explicitly

Page 23: The Cause of Freedom

23

articulated within his work, but their schematic content

recognisably surfaces. Homo juridicus is the "man of right"17 who in exchange for the security of his property, gives

up his "equality, liberty, and executive power" that he had

in the state of nature (Locke 1980: II § 131). Homo

oeconomicus is much more embryonic in Locke, but his

individualism morally condones the self-interested

accumulation of wealth 18.

That said, Locke's idea of man being the owner of

himself was expanded to include his expressions, giving a

deeper political dimension to the concept of freedom.

During the Constitutional Convention of 1787, Madison

proclaimed, "a man has property in his opinions and the free

communication of them" (Foner 17). Madison would continue

to adopt the language of property rights to encompass the

immaterial, insisting that a citizen also had "property" in

his rights; and this idea, Eric Foner argues, leads to the

logical conclusion that all should be able to participate in

government (Foner 17). At the time, this was only the case

for propertied, white free men 19. On the other hand, the

17 see (Foucault 1978: 283)18 Locke rather vaguely acknowledged the justness in providing basic food to prevent one's fellow from "extreme want" — i.e. from starvation — but nothing more. There is also the further restriction to this limited charity that the person in need must absolutely have no other means to his subsistence (Locke 1764: I § 42). 19 One's political freedom depended on one's self-sufficiency; the reason being was that man only has the virtue to overcome his "private passions" if he needn't worry about the trivialities of life (Foner 8-9).

Page 24: The Cause of Freedom

24

ideas of "liberty" and "equality" contained in these

statements and reflected in the Declaration of Independence

— the United States Constitution omits the latter and

sustains the former — counterposed their idealism with

extant social realities. The clarity of the contrast

created between them likely made future challenges to

disparities conceivable 20.

2.3 Vice Makes Paradise

The Scottish Enlightenment and Classical Liberalism

"Thus Vice nurs'd Ingenuity,Which join'd with Time and Industry...Vice is beneficial found,When it's by Justice lopt and bound"

— Bernard Mandeville The Fable of the Bees

Ever weary of the possibility of tyranny — which,

according to the influential intellectuals at the time, came

in a variety of forms, even democratic ones — the radical

20 The constitution encapsulated the intellectual revolution within the American Revolution. Thomas Paine, an English-American who helped foment the revolution through the distribution of the popular pamphlet "Common Sense", stated that power structures both at home and abroad were to be challenged, because "We see with other eyes; we hear with other ears; and we think with other thoughts, than those we formerly used" (Paine )

Page 25: The Cause of Freedom

25

ideas of Charles de Montesquieu and David Hume had major

impact in the constitutional debates. Generally speaking,

their work forms a choral decree calling for commerce to be

respected as a separate sphere autonomous from government

control, expanding upon Locke's possessive individualism.

In addition to the rule of law, a civil society freed from

political and social obligations was advised as a way to

bring about the 'common good' without 'despotic' dirigisme

that disrespected individual freedom. Montesquieu noted how

once the nobility was able to participate in commerce, a

monarchy's strikingly unequal ranking system was

destabilised to the point where its classification as

monarchical became merely nominal (Joseph Smith 9).

In a gesture that philosophically broadened the meaning

of society, Scottish philosopher Adam Ferguson considered it

to be a historical-natural constant, as man's survival

necessitates that he live in society (Foucault 1978: 299).

In order to maintain the natural, spontaneous synthetisation

of individuals and free association that occurred in civil

society, the state's institutional frameworks had to prevent

the formation of coercive factions; Madison argued for this

in Federalist No. 10 and it appeared in the U.S.

constitution by dividing the legislative branch into the

Senate and House 21. Such a system ensured that the 21 Federalist No. 10 laid out a solution to the problem of factions (Madison 1787). Montesquieu agreed that the fragmentation of powers through checks and balances warded off tyranny, but believed that

Page 26: The Cause of Freedom

26

opinions of the majority (which was composed, in the

founders' view, of mostly poor people) would be 'refined'

through representatives removed from their most proximal

constituencies; 'refined' euphemistically referred to the

larger goal of thwarting class conflict, or at least ensure

that it wouldn't work its way into policy (Diggins 51).

Madison warned that if such institutional measures were not

taken, the body politic would be inflicted with the "rage

for paper money, for an abolition of debts, for an equal

division of property, or for any other improper or wicked

project" (Madison 1787).

Montesquieu's advocacy for free commerce rested upon

his assumption that it fostered one's "love of equality" and

a spirit "frugality" — as opposed to one "enervated by

pleasure" — but thought this relationship could only be

produced within a confederation of small republics. David

Hume's rationale, then, is more in line with the American

political system finalised in the Constitution (Joseph Smith

9). One's virtuous conduct in the market was not the cause

of its efficacy and democratising potential, Hume opined.

Pure pursuit of self-interested pleasures begets "self-

improvement", a "productive citizenry", and a more powerful

state 22. The people's aspirations to luxury and wealth

freedom was sustained better at a more local, republic level. He therefore opposed the centralisation of power in a legislative hierarchy(Joseph Smith 6).22 see (Tuner 2008: 34). Like most philosophical arguments, Hume made this argument from broad generalisations. In his case, they were from

Page 27: The Cause of Freedom

27

incentivises "husbandmen to work harder" 23, thus creating

more commodities and wealth, and set into motion an endless

cycle that infinitely amplifies the drive for consumption

and production.

Without an aristocracy to extol the superiority of the

virtues over the degrading act of "working for profit" 24 or

an organised working class to "uphold the ideals of

socialism" 25, the accouchement of classical liberalism was

particularly robust and omnipotent in post-revolutionary

America. Classical liberalism's pivotal notions of laissez-

faire and homo oeconomicus operated in unison within civil

society. To the thinkers of the Scottish Enlightenment,

economic necessity was a more tenacious social cement than

Locke's imperative of moral duty. The former bond was also

empirically irreversible: man could transition from a

natural state of subsistence hunting to civil society, but

not back due to the former state because it required "ten

times the quantity of land" (Christian 369). Overall, then,

the economic bond is stronger, and therefore better, than

the historico-economic aspects of feudalism. To offer a slight criticism, it seems that he has forgotten the existence of independent peasant proprietors in feudal societies when drew up this proposition. He made the sweeping judgement that within simpler societies the dependency of serfdom and lack of trade perpetuated servility among other miseries, precluding the contradiction of the exception of the free peasantry. see (Joseph Smith 10)23 see (Joseph Smith 11)24 see (Wood 640) 25 see (Turner 34)

Page 28: The Cause of Freedom

28

the governmental one 26. He vindicated that: "sovereigns

must take mankind as they find them, and cannot pretend to

introduce any violent change in their principles and ways of

thinking...[the] best policy [is] to comply with the common

bent of mankind" (Hume 1985: 260). What was the proclivity

of mankind in Hume's opinion? Well, in more complex

societies it is self-interest, which he concluded from two

essential findings in his analysis of human nature: man's

nature is common due to similarities in physical

constitution and moral evaluations are made by "taste" over

moral. Hume pointedly chose to use the word "taste" for its

connection to human "sentiments of pleasure and pain" which

he thought were the prime movers of man's actions (Church

173). In contrast to Locke, Hume did not think one could or

should orient their estimations beyond the "painful or non-

painful nature of the thing" — the avoidance of pain is the

irreducible, non-transferable factors of every decision 27.

Thusly, while a sovereign may have good, albeit

paternalistic, intentions in limiting the exports of wheat —

26 Hume believed the government should only intervene when necessary andonly in "as calculable a manner as possible", as was made obvious by ones of Hume's essay titles "That Politics May be Reduced to a Science" — an uncanny foreshadowing of the totalising, calculating governmental rationality in neoliberalism (Werner 444). 27 see (Foucault 1978: 272). Besides, even if one were to behave in an altruistic way, this would not entail a sacrifice of one's interest for the other per se, because, Hume would argue, such a decision is reducible to the fact this other's suffering is more painful than whatever sacrifices one would have to make in order to aid their situation (Hume 1998: 293).

Page 29: The Cause of Freedom

29

say, out of the concern of possible shortages — it would be

more beneficial to both the nation experiencing dearth and

the one with a surplus to transact with each other (Foucault

1978: 294). John Maynard Keynes calls this the

harmonisation of "individualism and socialism", writing that

the "political philosopher could retire in favour of the

business man" (Keynes 1926).

Keynes undoubtedly had Adam Smith's "invisible hand" in

mind when making this animadversion, as it exemplarily

symbolised this miraculous, mutually beneficial alignment of

interests. Invisible is a key word with a double

connotation: firstly, it confers the fact that no agent can

know, and therefore cannot possibly pursue, the common good;

the second relates to the first since if no one can know,

neither can the state, being a mere instrument of men. For

this reason, any sort of economic planning is futile.

Friederich von Hayek, one of the main figures to develop the

neoliberal corpus, praised his British and Scottish

Empiricism influences:

"no human mind can comprehend all the knowledge which guidesa society and [there is] a consequent need for an impersonalmechanism, not dependent on individual human judgements, which will co-ordinate the individual efforts" (Hayek 1960: 4).

Page 30: The Cause of Freedom

30

Hayek found there to be "traditions of freedom" in the

work of these two 18th century philosophers: they attribute

a lack of coercion and spontaneity as fundamental qualities

comprising the true essence of freedom, both of which

greatly factored into Hayek's own definition of freedom 28.

In effect, this is a laconic description of the principle of

laissez-faire — embodied in the metaphor of the invisible

hand — acting in conjunction with the rule of law. Contra

to the vulgar version of laissez-faire, it was never meant

to be understood or practiced as an absolute. The Scottish

economic theorists did give some credence to institutions:

"They knew better than most of their later critics that it was not some sort of magic but the evolution of 'well-constructed institutions', where the 'rules and principles of contending interests and compromised advantages' would bereconciled, that had successfully channelled individual efforts to socially beneficial aims. In fact, their argument was never anti-state as such, or anarchistic, whichis the logical outcome of the rationalistic laissez-faire doctrine; it was an argument that accounted for the proper functions of the state and for the limits of state action" (Hayek 1960: 60).

28 Hayek came to this conclusion by comparing the colonial approaches of the French and the English where the success of the latter was due to"slow, half-conscious growth". According to his analysis, the French tradition located freedom in deliberateness and enforced planning, and their fortunes suffered as a result (Hayek 1960: 56). Political economyevidently had a huge effect on the meaning of freedom, in that the valueof its interpretation depended on how well it worked ideologically to produce wealth.

Page 31: The Cause of Freedom

31

Ergo, the relevance of the Rule of Law does not

diminish under the principle of laissez-faire. But the

relationship between governor and governed does noticeably

change; an altered type of freedom surfaces and with it a

new subjectivity. Gordon S. Wood cites American historians

Steven Hahn and Jonathan Prude's book The Countryside in the Age of

Capitalist Transformation and highlights their point that farmers

everywhere were industriously working the land, putting

their children and wives to work (even having them younger

and in greater number to increase their workforce), and

trading their surpluses for an ever-expanding variety of

consumer goods. Their "desire to consume above all became

the motor for their growing industriousness...[which]

contributed further to the rapid commercialization of

American life", she notes (Wood 638).

From these accounts it seems that the subject of right

(homo juridicus) underscored in Lockean liberalism takes a

back seat to the subject of interest (homo oeconomicus).

Perhaps the best way to assess the plausibility of this

transition is to ask, who was best served by this specific

articulation of freedom? Well, Tuner makes the following

summary that gives us a good enough idea — while also

abridging other transformations that we will unfortunately

have to neglect due to space limitations and so that we may

give attention to more pertinent developments:

Page 32: The Cause of Freedom

32

"In the early days of classical liberalism...laissez-faire became a reform ideology associated with the rising class oftradesmen and entrepreneurs...In the Jacksonian era, it was used 'to open the area of freedom by restricting the area ofprivilege'. In the late nineteenth century, 'it became the conservative weapon against the new generation of social reformers' " (Turner 35)

Economic freedom is thoroughly made the crucial freedom

during the late 18th and the 19th century, but it was

accompanied by increased equality under the law. The

demolishing of property restrictions on voting rights began

to erode in 1792 and only two requirements remained by the

late 1950s 29. In 1868 the Equal Protection Clause (the

14th amendment) further abraded asymmetrical legal

privileges by ensuring equal protection and impartial

judgment by the law (Cornell).

2.4 Freedom in Law Vs. Freedom in Fact

Freedom from Want and Liberal Progressivism

“An epoch which had gilded individual liberty so that if a man had money he was free in law and fact, and if he had not money he was free in law and not in fact.” 

— John Galsworthy The Forsyte Saga

29 restrictions still applied to "foreign-born residents of Rhode Island", African Americans, and women (Keyssar 29)

Page 33: The Cause of Freedom

33

At the beginning of the 20th century, the effects of a

permissive and rapacious individual self-interest myopically

focused on exercising a bludgeoning economic liberty were

palpable everywhere. The top ten percent of earners took

home almost half of the nation's wealth 30 — 43.6 percent to

be precise and in the 2000s 44.3 percent — and any proposals

to redistribute the wealth so as to relieve the misery of

the working poor, including children, were denounced at

first. William G. Sumner, the famous Social Darwinist who

founded the Sociology Department at Yale, voiced the

sentiments of robber barons and others of great affluence

when he cavilled that "every effort to realise equality

necessitates a sacrifice of liberty" in his popular little

book What the Social Classes Owe Each Other published in 1883 (Sumner

16).

Underneath the thin layer of lustrous, licentious

freedom practised by the few there was a compounding misery

that intermittently burst through in undeniable tragedies,

leading to a questioning of the rugged individual freedom at

the heart of classical liberalism and its effects upon

society 31. A growing social consciousness began to fight 30 see (Krugman 31) 31 Workers faced countless bursts of violence from the unchecked economic "freedom" of the capitalist class. There was the Monongah Mining Disaster that killed more than 350 men and children in 1907 ?; the egregious Triangle Shirtwaist Factory fire in 1911 that claimed the lives of 146 garment workers, mostly immigrant women, whose deaths couldhave been entirely prevented had the managers not made a practice out of

Page 34: The Cause of Freedom

34

the regime of classical liberalism on all fronts, both its

ideology and the practices that wore it. In 1888 The Ethics of

Democracy by John Dewey, an American philosopher, was

published and called for a "greater freedom in fact". It

was one of his earliest works, but it already contained most

of his progressive reinterpretations of classical

liberalism's fundamental concepts — principally its

atomistic view of the individual that resulted in a negative

version of freedom — by developing his idea of the "social

organism" (Dewey 231). This metaphor works on three levels.

First, it meant that the well being of the individual was

dependent upon the well-being of the whole. Second,

democracy was not simply an aggregate of individual

interests expressed in each vote but "a manifestation of

some tendency of the social organism through a member of

that organism"; that is, citing some of the findings of

Governor Tilden, the reason the majority often only wins

within a small margin is that each individual, and thus the

whole social organism, is deliberative and in regular

communication with others (Dewey 234-5). Or, put in a

different way, the majority position is only achieved

through the process of tentative deliberation, and

compromises must be made in order to reach a decision.

Thirdly, freedom is — in opposition to Lockean liberalism

locking their workers in to prevent theft and unauthorised breaks ?; thelynching of a disabled union organiser, Frank Little, in 1917 ?; and I am only naming a few of the more publicised cases here.

Page 35: The Cause of Freedom

35

and classical liberalism — positive. Freedom is not brought

about just by the removal of external obstacles and

constraints, as is the case with negative liberty; it is

also the ability to participate in the construction of an

ethical social order per the recognition that men are

"organically related to one another" (Dewey 232). Dewey's

"social organism" makes a sophisticated case for equality —

the elemental concept of democratic freedom.

Even though an ideological paradigm shift with real

thwart was already well underway, most scholars agree that

the Great Depression was the definitive signifier that the

antecedent liberal era was coming to a close (Tuner 41).

Economic catastrophe hit nearly every family, giving Dewey's

notion of the "social organism" — primarily the aspect that

well-being of the individual and of the whole mutually

affect one another — a resounding truth. Important reforms

have already been made prior to Roosevelt's New Deal 32, but

the most ambitious expansion of government action and

positive freedom can be comprehensively attributed to his

administration. He added two new freedoms — freedom from

want and freedom from fear — that he considered to have as

much importance as the other two freedoms he listed in his

famous Four Freedoms Speech: "freedom of speech" and "freedom

32 To give just one example, after immense union pressure, the Adamson Act of 1916 mandated the eight-hour work day for railroad workers and was upheld in Wilson Vs. New (see Wilson V. New 242 U.S. 332 1917 Justia: the US Supreme Court Center)

Page 36: The Cause of Freedom

36

of religion". Freedom from want translated into a right to

an adequate standard of living, and "freedom from fear"

translated into a world-wide call for the reduction of

armaments (Roosevelt). Both necessitated government

intervention — exceedingly so in light of their historical

context — and to properly do so it needed to recruit

economic theories outside of classical economic liberalism's

model.

For the key economists who helped shape governmental

policy during the New Deal era, the problem with laissez-

faire was not so much an ethical or moral one but a

pragmatic one: classical economic liberalism, frankly, just

didn't work anymore (Turner 50). Rescuing capitalism from

its dire state mandated collective action, calling for the

dissolution of the state/society dichotomy and the invention

of demand-side economics. Keynesian economics, eponymously

named after its founder, suggested that severe downturns in

the business cycle could be adjusted for with fiscal policy

and intensive public investment to create jobs. His advice

was wholly taken by Roosevelt's administration (Jones 139).

The creation of the Bretton Woods International Monetary

System 33 was partially led by Keynes, and a profusion of

work programs were enacted in accordance with his theories.

33 Bretton Woods worked to manage world economies during times of peace by fixing the exchange rate via tying it to the U.S. dollar. It was abandoned in 1971 by Richard Nixon — henceforth the nation's currency became free-floating (Harvey 2007: 12)

Page 37: The Cause of Freedom

37

Still, Keynes did step outside of purely pragmatic

concerns to advance criticisms against the philosophical

claims upon which the notions of natural liberty and

laissez-faire had been founded:

"Let us clear from the ground the metaphysical or general principles upon which, from time to time, laissez-faire has beenfounded. It is not true that individuals possess a prescriptive 'natural liberty' in their economic activities.There is no 'compact' conferring perpetual rights on those who Have or on those who Acquire. The world is not so governed from above that private and social interest always coincide. It is not so managed here below that in practice they coincide. It is not a correct deduction from the principles of economics that enlightened self-interest always operates in the public interest. Nor is it true that self-interest generally is enlightened; more often individuals acting separately to promote their own ends are too ignorant or too weak to attain even these. Experience does not show that individuals, when they make up a social unit, are always less clear-sighted than when they act separately" (Keynes 1926).

Karl Polanyi, who was an eminent economic historian, added

to this perspective, writing that the government

interventions taking place during the New Deal meant that

the economy was simply being put back in its traditional

place; in his assessment the economy was always politically

and socially administered. Upon the nearly ubiquitous

rejection of classical liberalism, progressive liberalism

came to be associated with the welfare state and is the

Page 38: The Cause of Freedom

38

common definition of liberalism in the American political

lexicon today.

With such a lucid apperception of the complete

artificiality — viz. the constructivism of all economic,

social, and political apparatuses — there were no barriers

to designing and administering programs to build an ideal

citizenry that would be maximally conducive for the

realisation of liberal progressivism's aims. Statistical

devices originally utilized for the investigation of

macroeconomic phenomena — such as researching the

relationship between national wealth and population size,

taxation issues, etc., — were used to thoroughly penetrate

the microeconomic in order to efficiently deliver welfare

services (Rose 113). As the sociologist Nikolas Rose aptly

put it, the "social organism" was to be "gridded by

regulatory codes demanding, for example, the registration

and recording of births, marriages, illnesses, numbers and

causes of death, types of crime, and their geographical

location", etc. (Rose 113). Numbers empowered experts to

distinguish and classify a desirable level of normativity

and vet over what degrees of deviation were socially

detrimental. Those who fell into the latter category were

to become the target for intervention by philanthropists,

social workers, teachers, police, doctors, etc. Dewey's

"social organism", whose health depends on the health of

each part, corresponds to the rationale behind new

Page 39: The Cause of Freedom

39

government objectives. Liberal progressivism reconciled

freedom and control by underscoring a democratic type of

freedom — the prerequisite of which is a foundation of

equality. Daniel Stedman Jones, a historian and barrister,

indicates that there is an odd logical congruence between

the New Deal idea that "political freedom was inadequate

without some economic security" and the "hollow" point made

many neoliberals that there cannot be any sort of political

freedom without economic freedom — a logic that can be

traced back to ancient Greece but is also in found in our

discussion of Lockean liberalism and classical liberalism34. And once again, albeit differently, individualism is

conciliated with collectivism; because practices of social

control through standards of hygiene, schooling, child-

rearing, etc are internalized by the individual and

exercised as forms of "self-control" 35.

2.5 Hayek's Freedom Fighters

The Phylogenesis of the Mont Pelerin Society to American Neoliberalism

34 Jones calls the neoliberal vindication of economic freedom "hollow" because "it was beyond so many people's reach" (Jones 333).35 Rose gives examples of how governmetalising social responsibilities was reflected in individual conduct, especially within the working family: proper hygienic practices were disseminated through public schools, the "female condition" was psychiatrised, and officials such ashealth visitors morally reprimanded those who did not internalise properprocedures (Rose 121-8).

Page 40: The Cause of Freedom

40

"It may seem odd now, but I hesitated a while before deciding to call my book Human Capital...In the early days, many people were criticizing this term and the underlying analysis because they believed it treated people like slaves or machines. My, how the world has changed!"

— Gary S. Becker Human Capital

"Even the striving for equality by means of a directed economy can result only in an officially enforced inequality – an authoritarian determination of the status of each individual in the new hierarchical order."

— F. A. Hayek The Road to Serfdom

Growing alongside liberal progressivism was the

incipience of a reactionary ideology, which came to be known

as neoliberalism. Ludwig von Mises directly attacked what

he imagined to be a dangerous and vast augmentation of state

bureaucracy. Both his essay Bureaucracy and Hayek's extremely

popular The Road to Serfdom — published contemporaneously in

1944 — expressed deep-seated fears of totalitarianism that

they believed was congenital to government planning; the

most harrowing case they cited was National Socialism 36.

Mises was more optimistic about America's ability to fend

off its more nefarious aspects because America was born free

from the constraints of "industrial codes or guilds";

rather, her spirit is substantiated in the venturous pioneer

(Mises 2007: 76). Even so, he saw the indelible emblem of

36 The similarity between the texts is far from coincidental. Hayek came to admire Mises upon their very first meeting and placed himself under his tutelage (Magrit von Mises 1976: 189)

Page 41: The Cause of Freedom

41

Obrigkeirt (authority) written on all bureaucratic structures;

they all equally sought to usurp everyone's freedom through

the paternalistic management of more and more individual

affairs (Jones 271). Its even worse, not only do

bureaucrats — even with the best of intentions — corrode

one's freedom with compulsory programs and taxes, he adds

that they are also too absolutely enslaved by "rules and

regulations" to be able to find the best possible solution.

Yet, in a stroke of blatant inconsistency, Mises opines, in

their zealous efforts to serve the public, they use morally

and legally questionable techniques such as "pork barrel

spending" 37 and exploit loopholes in the law to make sure

no "scoundrel" escapes their grasp (Mises 2007: 62). For

Mises, competitiveness in the public sector by parties and

organisations lead to corrupt practices, bringing him to the

conclusion that democracy could only work in the private

sector, i.e. the market.

It isn't, however, the exclusive fault of the

individual bureaucrats; their 'ruthless' drive to enlarge

the jurisdiction of their authority was a symptom of an even

greater political thrust for expansion and a disregard for

the rule of law (Mises 2007: 7). The Rule of Law — heeds

Hayek, in unity with Mises — cannot survive in a planned 37 see (Jones 272). "Pork barrel spending" describes the somewhat furtive act of a congressional representative inserting funding for a project exclusively beneficial to their specific constituency — and thereby bolstering their own career — into a bill as a condition for their backing of a bill (Jones 1539).

Page 42: The Cause of Freedom

42

society 38; but, Hayek adds, this does not mean the exercise

of government power will not be legal:

"It means the use of government's coercive powers will no longer be limited to pre-determined rules. The law can, andto make a central direction of economic activity possible must, legalize what to all intents and purposes remains arbitrary action. If the law says that such a board or authority may do what it pleases, anything that board or authority does is legal — but its actions are certainly not subject to the Rule of Law" (Hayek 2007: 119).

Hayek's and Mises' critiques were a public plea to

rescue "the free society" from the New Deal's threatening

transgression of classical liberal principles such as

individual freedom the rule of law, and the free market.

Hayek was quick to point out that Hilter's Kronjurist, Carl

Schmitt, vehemently impugned the rule of law in defense of

the emergency powers granted under Article 48 of the Weimar

Constitution that were used to substantiate the power of the

Nazi Reich in 1933 39. Subsequently, they were convinced

that all ideologies supporting government intervention for

the sake of the collective good inevitably led to erection

38 For both of them a planned society includes any society that attemptsto control the economy, especially through the practice of redistributive justice.39 Article 48 gave absolute emergency powers in the event of any emergency that gravely threatened public security. In fact, Schmitt wasalso critical of Article 48 because it enumerated the rights that could be suspended by emergency powers rather than giving limitless executive powers, which he deemed necessary for the strengthening of Nazi power against the Communist party (Schmitt 1985: xx)

Page 43: The Cause of Freedom

43

of totalitarianism. Something had to be done, and there

were plenty of intellectuals sympathetic to businessmen

frustrated by the New Deal and communist paranoia engendered

in McCarthyism to give a new voice to liberalism (Jones 53).

Hayek was one of the leaders of a communal project to

reinvigorate classical liberal ideology 40. Their task was

to reformulate the core principles in order to adapt them to

new social and historical realities. A few years before the

publication of Mises' and Hayek's critical texts, similarly

concerned intellectuals gathered at the Colloque Walter

Lipmann in 1938, where ordoliberal 41 Alexander Rüstow

suggested the term 'neoliberal' as the name "for a movement

to revive market liberalism" 42. Shortly after the

publication of Milton Friedman's "Neoliberalism and its 40 The collaborative aspect was part of new strategy to not only rigorously work out a new ideology but also to build a larger network todisseminate their message (Mirowski 2008: 113).41 Ordoliberalism is a German variant of neoliberalism developed during the 1930s and 40s as a "third way" to the Keynesian welfare state, proposing instead the social market economy. Opposite to the simple, self-establishing market system of classical liberalism that functioned best with a weak state, ordoliberalism valued a strong state capable of securing competition and fortifying the market society. Etymologically,the prefix ordo arose from its proponents in the Frieburg School frequently publishing in the Journal Ordo (Brown 38). While "the independent ordoliberal line of neoliberal thought" has nearly vanished,some of their "discoveries" — such as the importance of institutions, economics and law — have continued to noticeably influence the Anglo-Saxon world (Mirowski 2009: 27-8).42 It was during this transitional phase from what Jones labels the first phase of neoliberalism (which was during the interwar period and marked by ordoliberalism and Lippman's book The Good Society) to its philosophical crystallisation in the second phase (which is set between the 1950s-80s during the zenith of Keynesian policies) that the term wascommonly used by those involved in the project (Jones 167).

Page 44: The Cause of Freedom

44

Prospects" in 1951, the term dropped out of popular usage,

leaving it vulnerable to misuse (Mirowski 2008: 113). Even

though the word has ceased to be a self-consciously applied

label, it still has a "conceptual identity" that crucially

delineates the difference between it and older forms of

liberalism, making it an important tool for analysis and

diagnosing the present (Hall 2012: 9)

Writing on the prehistory of the Mont Pelerin Society43, Mirowski adumbrates their project as a dynamic

investigation and tense negotiation between "socialist

planning philosophies and classical laissez-faire

liberalism" and not a search "for timeless (essentialist)

content" (Mirowski 14-5). There were over a thousand

members in just the MPS; and while there is a general

agreement amongst their contributions, there are also

significant divergences 44. That being said,

neoliberalism's defining solution is an odd merging of the

notion of constructivism prevalent in "social planning

43 the most comprehensive neoliberal organisation established by Hayek, Mises and others in 195744 It would be incorrect and deficient to offer what I argue is their preeminent resolution, and thereby foundational principle to their specific ideology, without first qualifying it with the acknowledgement that there isn't a simple universal definition of the neoliberal ideology or the interpretation of its central principles. For example, Mises was more a "free market libertarian" because he did not believe — in contrast to many other neoliberal theorists and politicians — that market mechanisms could ever be the modus operandi of decidedly public tasks. Instead of applying market principles to operation of government, Mises asseverated that government simply had to be smaller (Jones 259-60).

Page 45: The Cause of Freedom

45

philosophies" and a principal faith in market solutions and

values (private property, individual freedom and spontaneous

order) representative of the laissez-faire attitude in

classical liberalism. Combined, however, these acquired

concepts change. Reverence for the market is no longer

based on its alleged superiority in achieving the optimal

balance of exchange (recall the hypothetical example cited

earlier concerning the wheat surplus versus dearth); rather,

its superiority is due to its being the most efficient

discovery mechanism whereby competition finds the best

solutions. Competition, unlike the market in laissez-faire,

is not a "natural given"; it is, as the ordoliberals say, a

fragile framework that must be constructed by the state in

order to guarantee its success. With neoliberalism,

constructivism operates in the opposite direction; instead

of the government correcting for the perpetual market

downturns in the capitalist cycle through demand-drive

initiatives designed to equalise access to consumer goods

and disciplining the market through regulations, the

government must not correct for the negative effects of the

market. Government interventions must act lightly on the

economy and heavily on society to maximally enable the

mechanisms of competition (Foucault 1979: 142-146). Using

the work of ordoliberal Walter Eucken, Foucault describes

light economic interventions as incremental adjustments to

the discount rate, foreign trade credit balance, and

Page 46: The Cause of Freedom

46

taxation with the aim of stabilising prices — but only for

the purpose of controlling inflation. Economic interventions

typical of Keynesianism — job creation, price control,

support for struggling sectors of the economy, public

investment, etc — are to be, ideally, completely avoided.

Heavy interventions operate on what ordoliberals call the

"framework", which are all those social factors that have

appreciable, yet indirect, impact on the economy — e.g., the

population, training and education, technology, and the

legal system (Foucault 1979: 157-8).

Foucault decidedly locates Hayek and Mises at the

juncture between German ordoliberalism and the American

brand of neoliberalism that came to maturation in the

Chicago School, whose most formative intellectuals were also

members of the MPS. Both schools of thought — the Chicago

School and the MPS — resolutely affirmed that the vitality

of the state and the market economy are mutually dependent

upon one another, ridding themselves of the classical

liberalist notion of the natural economy with the state

acting as a pure superstructure to be limited as much as

possible. For all that, where the two schools diverge is

crucial for the sake of avoiding an empty, grand theory of

neoliberalism. Sociologist Thomas Lemke offers a percipient

description of their key difference:

Page 47: The Cause of Freedom

47

"Whereas the Ordo-liberals in West Germany pursued the idea ofgoverning society in the name of the economy, the US neo-liberals attempt to re-define the social sphere as a form of the economic domain. The model of rational-economic action serves as a principle for justifying and limiting governmentalaction, in which context government itself becomes a sort of enterprise whose task it is to universalize competition and invent market-shaped systems of action for individuals, groups, and institutions" (Lemke 7).

In other words, what came to define American neoliberalism

is that it applied the economic grid to every domain of life

with a thoroughgoing intensity. And, in spite of the acme

of its intellectual and political articulations being

reached awhile ago within the Chicago School and the Reagan

administration in the 80s, it remains as an ideological

miasma obstructing visions of new horizons. This is

precisely what is lamented in Fisher's Capitalist Realism: it is

not even possible to imagine an alternative to capitalism, and

when that system is represented through a neoliberal

ideology 45 — "the capitalist realists par excellence"— it

reaches a nihilistic level of ambivalence. Thence, not even

a profound ideological rupture, which vigorously exposes its

underlying contradictions and hypocrisies, is affecting

enough to move people beyond symbolic resistance.

It should be made clear that neoliberalism is not just

an academic term for American conservatism; in fact, its

most astute theorist, Hayek, made certain to let everyone

45 see (Fisher 2)

Page 48: The Cause of Freedom

48

know that he is "not a conservative" in the postscript of

his seminal text The Constitution of Liberty (Hayek 397).

Neoliberalism does not die out with the election of a

democratic president; it is "a rationality that exceeds

particular positions on particular issues" (Brown 37). Such

a rationality has also seeped into the Obama administration;

his most recent proposal for higher education mimics the

same 'competitive' market strategy found in Bush's No Child

Left Behind 46. Without accounting for the initial

resources of institutions, Obama proposed a standardised

metric system that transforms federal financial aid into a

punitive instrument by attaching good or bad results to the

granting of more or less federal dollars. Such a proposal

could negatively affect the choice of less well-off

students, who are the most reliant upon federal financial

46 Signed into law by George W. Bush in 2002, NCLB continues to indirectly accelerate the privatisation of education via high-stakes standardised tests, creating a downward spiral for failing schools through punitive measures — for example, loosing funding for tutors. But, this disadvantage is glossed over with the heavily connotated neoliberal rhetoric of "being free to choose", which is indentified withconsumer choice, by its intellectual figureheads. If a student's assigned school is deemed too be "failing" according the new standards, his or her family can choose to place their child in charter school — anattractive option, considering that charter schools are "free from some of the rules, regulations, and statues that apply to other public schools" (National Education Association). A very recent study funded by the Walton Family Foundation found that charter schools received significantly less funding than public schools, and, therefore, have to rely more heavily on private donations (Layton 2013); the idea is that schools will be disciplined by market forces via cut-throat competition between other schools for resources and between individual families in the community shopping for the "best" school (Hursh 2007).

Page 49: The Cause of Freedom

49

aid, and the autonomy of institutions (Slack). Under his

administration H.R. 347 was made stronger and more

enforceable (the law permits the arrest of anyone who

knowingly enters an area that is under the jurisdiction of

Secret Service protection) 47, and the Trans-Pacific

Partnership (TPP) is currently being drafted behind closed

doors. A leaked chapter of the TPP draft revealed that the

agreement would allow foreign corporations operating in the

United States to "appeal key regulations to an international

tribunal"; for instance, if the labour laws or environmental

sanctions make it difficult for a U.S. company to profitably

operate in a foreign country, it can sue the country's

government not only to recover the initial investment but

for the profits the company expected to earn as well

(Democracy Now).

By now the justificatory narratives are familiar ones:

the nation needs to take such measures to increase security

or stay competitive in the global market. Constitutional

rights are threatened by H.R. 347, and the rights of

citizens in other countries will come under serious attacks

from TPP (Democracy Now). David Harvey, a professor of

anthropology and geography, still attaches the undying

thrust and resuscitation of neoliberalism in spite of its

obvious failures — its need for subsequent bailouts,

diminishing profits, and environmental catastrophes — to the

47 see (Verheyden-Hilliard)

Page 50: The Cause of Freedom

50

restoration and preservation of class power. But how much

more restoration does it need? Can that really be the main

reason for its unrelenting grip on our thought when we have

already reached the same level of inequality as arguably the

most unequal period in our history — i.e. the gilded age —

with the top ten percent of earners taking home 43.6 percent

of the wealth back then and 44.3 percent in the 2000s?

Wendy Brown attributes neoliberalism's recalcitrance to its

seditious government rationality that rids itself of any

kind of moral cogitations within its paradigm of economic

calculation. Consequently, she proceeds, the "Janus-face or

at least Janus-potential of liberal democracy" — which

"codes, reflects, and legitimates capitalist social

relations" while simultaneously offering an internal

critique of power via its principles — is nullified 48:

Brown is undoubtedly correct here but she gives only

cursory attention to how the neoliberal ideology creates a

subjectivity that internalises this duality. Many scholars

have brilliantly described the transformations of

subjectivity under liberal democracy but with only one set

of eyes at a time. Cultural anthropologist Illana Gershon

brilliantly shows how subjectivity is flattened even when

faced with a plurality of cultures because the otherness of

another culture can be deployed "to engage with the market 48 her "Janus-face" of liberal democracy functions in a strikingly analogous way to dual powers of freedom that we extracted from Nikolas Rose.

Page 51: The Cause of Freedom

51

to their advantage" through the commodification of their

difference (Gershon 451). In his 1978-9 lectures and the

College de France, Foucault presents the heterogeneous

relationship of homo oeconomicus and homo juridicus. But,

Gary Becker's theory of a totally calculating homo

oeconomicus contorts the latter into a homogeneous

relationship with the former — although he does not exactly

say this 49. Becker divulges the simplifications and

reduction of subjectivities to conform with purely economic

motivations through his speculations on the motivations of

the criminal:

"I was not sympathetic to the assumption that criminals had radically different motivations from everyone else...Rationality implied that some individuals become criminals because of the financial rewards" (Becker 1996).

Our genealogy has shown that the two formulae of

freedom do not faithfully function as two Janus faces

looking away from one another, with one looking to the past

and another to the future. Conspicuous contradictions

within any governmental rationality are, for a time,

successfully conflated with the face of idealism, so that

the two heads are turned toward one another, confusing the

past and the future with the present. Pejorative sentiments49 Gary Becker is a American Economist who has received multiple rewards, including the Presidential Medal of Freedom in 2007 granted by George W. Bush (Hoover Institution).

Page 52: The Cause of Freedom

52

about subjectivities interwoven with the cold calculation of

human capital are attenuated with ideas of self-ownership

and possibilities to 'make yourself'; there is a sense of

empowerment, since this concept rids the sense of alienation

in the capitalist mode of production (Foucault 1979 224).

Stereotyping individuals and groups with demographic

statistics are likewise also seen as an innovation to

improve endemic social problems. Private property rights

allow for profiteering while creating a 'refuge' from state

control. Or, as neoliberals like Hayek see it, private

property is a defensive against coercion, because, in

theory, if there are many owners of the means of production

— i.e. suppliers of goods and services — existing without

being centrally organised then one is free to produce, free

to take his labour anywhere he chooses, and free to consume

(Hayek 1960: 135-40). The etiolating of democratic rights,

as with H.R. 347, are furbished with new modes of democratic

expression, such as those enthusiastically put forth by

Ludwig Mises:

"The anonymous forces operating on the market are continuously determining anew who should be entrepreneur andwho should be capitalist. The consumers vote, as it were, for those who are to occupy the exalted positions in the setting of the nation's economic structure" (Mises 2007: 95).

Page 53: The Cause of Freedom

53

This perpetual recycling of ideals that produce new

forms of control is at its core a problem of posing new

realities in political ideologies: freedom is constantly

used as an empty vassal that needs to be given substance by

new interpretations, programs, policies, etc by an

intellectual or elite class.

However, Sartre would say that, our artful invention

and reinvention of meanings — of organising the universe

into ever-changing ideologies, cosmologies, or

Weltanschauungen — are only the manifestations of our

freedom. Freedom is not a thing in the world; it does not

authentically exist as a "bouquet of the Rights of Man and

of the Citizen" 50 from which an elite can determine who

deserves a rose and who does not, as if someone's life is

more necessary than another's, when all exists by sheer

contingency. All these fictions and scenarios arise from

the freedom that defines the very ontological structure of

our consciousness: "man does not exist first in order to be

free subsequently; there is no difference between the being of

man and his being-free" (Sartre 2003: 49). Once we stop

alienating our freedom by placing it within given systems of

ideas and practices — all those ideological pronunciations

that essentialise our nature, our psychology, our being and

give agnate formulae of power — we leave the sticky comfort

of irresponsibility begotten by externalising our freedom in

50 see (Sartre 2007: 90)

Page 54: The Cause of Freedom

54

conceptual trappings and can face our metaphysical

condition.

3. An Anticoagulant for the Thrombotic Heart

Towards a Sartrean Critique of Liberalism

"Thus all serious thought is thickened by the world; it coagulates; it is a dismissal of human reality in favour of the world...It is obvious that the serious man at bottom is hiding from himself the consciousness of his freedom; he is in bad faithand his bad faith aims at presenting himself to his own eyes as consequence..."

— Jean-Paul Sartre Being and Nothingness

“I confused things with their names: that is belief.”

— Jean-Paul Sartre The Words

We can make new worlds because we are not as the

unconscious pen or computer; whose phenomena are presented

as utilizable essences that are put to our own ends. With

man, there is no such self-identity; he is not a "sum

formulae of qualities" 51, rather:

51 see (Sartre 1946). There are countless practices in modern life thatencourage people to see and express themselves as a person-thing with special attributes and qualities.

Page 55: The Cause of Freedom

55

"man first of all exists, encounters himself, surges up in the world — and defines himself afterwards. If man as the existentialist sees him is not definable, it is because to begin with he is nothing. He will not be anything until later, and then he will be what he makes of himself. Thus, there is no human nature...Man simply is" (Sartre 1946)

Sartre's conclusion that existence precedes essence with the

being of man is arrived at from his ontology, which is quite

elaborate. Nevertheless, going over the basic points will

be enough for our critique and leave us with the fundamental

principle of what he judges to be the metaphysical condition

of man. Ontology is discerned from metaphysics by Sartre by

the special technical meanings he assigns to each; the

former deals with fundamental classifications and

descriptions of being, whereas the latter deals with the why

question — i.e. causal explanations and accounts of the

ultimate origins of being (Catalano 1974: 17). In his

ontology, he first deals with the problem of Cartesian

sceptical idealism 52 and adds to Descartes' cogito the pre-

reflective cogito. Consciousness is aware of a self at all

times, not just upon reflection where the self becomes an

ego; the true self for Sartre is pre-personal and indirectly

present in action. If consciousness was entirely

ontologically structured on the "I" or the ego, then we

would be utterly incapable of even partially receiving the 52 Briefly states, Descartes' cogito turns inwards to itself to questionthe existence of things in the world and one's own ideas, inferring thatthe only thing one can be sure of is his existence.

Page 56: The Cause of Freedom

56

world objectively and perceive reality; the opacity of the

ego would prevent any sort of objectivity by enmeshing man

in pure subjective idealism. From Husserl, Sartre takes the

principle that we are always conscious of something to

support his own predication that consciousness is a concrete

nothingness — not in the sense of an absence but due to its

"nihilating" activity:

"As nothingness it is separated from the object by not beingthe object, and preserves a distance from it. Nevertheless,consciousness is nothing but consciousness-of-the-object andtherefore present to it. It is this that Sartre has in mindwhen he terms nothingness being-for-itself; consciousness isan awareness of being. The relation between consciousness and its object might be compared with that between a mirror and the objects which are reflected in it; the mirror has nocontent of its own, containing merely reflections before it,yet it is always separate and never merges with the object" (Greene 17)

Nothingness, as a negation, requires being and the being

through which being is "made-to-be" is man (Sartre 2003:

46). Nihilation is a process by which one places oneself

"outside of being", which the human does by imaging,

questioning, doubting, and by thinking objects (Anderson

28). Because man can thus detach himself from the world

through the nothingness he brings to it, he is free.

At the same time, negation implies a relationship to

being outside of man's pre-reflective cogito — being that is

Page 57: The Cause of Freedom

57

not consciousness. In Sartre's ontology, opposed to the for-

itself (more or less identified with man's consciousness) is

the in-itself which includes all the objects in the world

one is conscious of; the in-itself is full, in unity of

itself, self-identical, and positive. Figuratively

speaking, the in-itself is solid and the for-itself is

liquid. Now, human reality comprises both in relation to

each other, as hinted at earlier, being (now understood as

being-in-itself) is the precondition of negation. Being-in-

itself is our facticity, the givens of ourselves and our

environment: the pens, the desk, the language we communicate

with, our past actions, our race, class, physical

constitution, etc. Conversely, being-for-itself is our

transcendence: the mode of being that assigns meanings and

purposes to my facticity in light of my project.

Objectively, the pen has the quality of releasing a

controlled amount of ink onto a surface, its ink is black.

And while the pen's blackness and power to deposit ink on

paper are objective aspects on its being, they are the

outcomes of the subjective activities of the for-itself.

Since the for-itself is negation, it can comprehend cause

and effect. My past praxis with these materials informs me

of the possibility of it making a mark on a paper, and in

order make a mark I need to nihilate their present state of

inertia on the table (Sartre 2003: 122-5).

Page 58: The Cause of Freedom

58

When we try to escape our freedom and the anguish it

brings — the anguish of having to create meaning for oneself

through one's project — we try to substitute our

transcendence with facticity and vice versa. Instead of

authentically coordinating them into a project by which one

aims to surmount them in a synthesis 53, we mistakenly

abdicate our project to only identify these two categories,

that is, we simply relate them with a prefabricated

experience. This is what Sartre calls being in bad faith.

To demonstrate this concept in a way relevant our

question of freedom in liberal ideologies, bad faith can be

explained in the following manner: one is in a state of bad

faith when one adopts the language of an ideology as the

objective truth of their situation, as describing their

proper place in its social ordering, as being wholly

determined by it, and so capitulates on their guiding their

actions — one's transcendence — in any other way than one

that would concur and be one with that ideology, to force it

be necessary — Amen 54. A good American citizen pays her

taxes, respects property rights, votes every two years

(maybe more if she is particularly active in local

politics), enjoys freedom and equality with her fellow 53 e.g. I see this blank paper and pen, project a drawing or some poetry, and take actions to bring it into being54 in reference to Althusser's characterisation of ideology; one of its facets being "the absolute guarantee that everything really is so, and that on condition that the subjects recognise what they are and behave accordingly, everything will be all right: Amen — 'So be it' " (Althusser 87).

Page 59: The Cause of Freedom

59

citizens as they are enumerated in the Bill of Rights and

accepts these very circumstances as her rights and duties

and her limitations for political action. Contrarily,

Sartre professes that all these rights and duties "refer to

the transcendent" 55, and to fuse their factual content to

them makes great inferences that ignore different histories

and societies. We have seen how idealised petitions for

freedom in the form of natural rights, economic, and socio-

political rights — deduced from various philosophical tracts

on human nature or psychological theories — have been

decisive in challenging institutions that were

superincumbent on the idealistic ideologies of the

dissenters. Once these new formulations became

institutionalised, however, their abstract possibilities are

concretised within their ideology, affirming what is as the

natural order. The transcendent principles of freedom and

equality become facticity — rights, rules, and regulations —

and our good citizen, with prudence and a spirit of

seriousness, confounds the ideal with the present real. If

she finds it necessary to mould her transcendence in

accordance with them, despite the requirements of a new

situation, then she acts in an in apoplectic fit of bad

faith.

55 this is his critical response to the famous example he gives of bad faith involving the cafe waiter, but the abstract content of his conduct that characterises it as Bad Faith fits the schema of treating one's facticity as transcendence and vice versa (Sartre 2003: 82-3).

Page 60: The Cause of Freedom

60

Yet, bad faith is metastable. It can slide into good

faith and vice versa; neither are permanent conditions. Man

can be in bad faith and leave it just the same because of

his ontological structure: "the origin of this risk is the

fact that the nature of consciousness simultaneously is to

be what it is not and not to be what it is" (Sartre 2003:

94). Bad faith, then, in no way resembles Engel's notion of

false consciousness 56. For Sartre man is consciousness — he

rejects Freud's notion of the unconscious — and a degree of

self-awareness is ceaselessly present in his life (Sartre

2003: 73). The structure of bad faith is analogous to that

of a lie (except it is one that we tell to ourselves) and is

composed of the following components arranged in the stated

order:

"First, one must believe something to be true. Second, one must express to another the opposite of what is believed. Third, for a lie to succeed, the other must believe in the statement expressed" (Catalano 1974: 79).

Joseph S. Catalano further expounded on bad faith in a

separate essay informatively entitled "Good and Bad Faith:

Weak and Strong Notions"; and, as the title suggests, this

lie we tell ourselves can be one lived in thought and action

(strong) or confined mostly to the latter (weak). In a weak

state of bad faith, one does not identify with pre-given

values and social roles but resigns herself to them 56 see "false consciousness" (Marxist Internet Archive)

Page 61: The Cause of Freedom

61

(Catalano 1997: 125). Someone who is a in a strong sense of

bad faith believes in the correctness of a certain order

based on very little evidence.

The ideologies we have discussed have all been built

from philosophical or theoretical assumptions concerning

human motivation, psychological propensities, social

ontology, or rationality. To unquestioningly believe in any

one of them would be a mark of bad faith; because, as Greene

succinctly puts Sartre's reasoning, "human consciousness is

nothingness, it cannot contain its own motives, and since it

acts by negation, it cannot be determined by any exterior

influence"; and he continues, "thus arises the necessity for

man to choose freely his own motivations..." (Greene 170).

4. Left with a Choice

Conclusion

 "...man finds himself in an organised situation in which he is himself involved: his choice involves mankind in its entirety, and he cannot avoid choosing."

— Jean-Paul Sartre Existentialism is a Humanism

America is still in the throes of neoliberalism and has

failed to assuage its overt rapaciousness that socialises

Page 62: The Cause of Freedom

62

the private risks of the rich and leaves the rest of the

population with the bill. Mary Hawkesworth, a distinguished

professor of Political Science and Gender Studies, wrote in

2008 that the United States is far from entering any sort of

"post-neoliberal" stage, which is defined by the use of

"progressive policy alternatives" to compensate for social

contradictions and malaise produced by a state vigorously

pursuing the freedom of capital rather than the freedom of

it's people (Hawkesworth 182). With its ideology out in the

open, our individual submission to it is a matter of weak

bad faith. Occupy Wall Street was a mass recognition of the

hollowness of neoliberal freedom, and it is within this

paradigm more than any other that freedom has been made into

a thing. Homo oeconomicus is a subject whose relationship

to freedom is expressed and measured by his ability to

"adjust himself to what to him must seem the blind forces of

the social process and obeying the orders of a superior",

says Hayek, and "man in a complex society can have no

[other] choice" (Hayek 1972: 24). Homo juridicus' relation

to the law is not one of judgement and interpretation but of

scientific application; it questions not its own values and

methods so much as it is strictly concerned with correctly

applying the code. Louiza Odysseos — a lecturer in

International Relations — critiques the legal structure of

human rights as purely being a means to govern in the most

Page 63: The Cause of Freedom

63

economically efficient way possible: "to put it cynically,

it says let them eat rights!" (Odysseos 764).

After sampling the various 'gifts' of freedom offered,

arrested, and deferred by the liberal ideologies, after

attending to each rose in the bouquet to behold the beauty

of its image and feel the pain of its thorns, there is

little room left for ideological mystification. As the

convulsions of violence continue to shake and rupture the

ground of neoliberal ideology, Sartre would argue that our

freedom to think will only grow stronger. He leaves us,

then, with a choice: one of which leads into living in bad

faith and the other in good faith; the former is our pre-

reflective choice, and is therefore foundation of the other.

The first comes naturally to us, it seeks to tuck away the

vertiginous burden of our absolute and spontaneous freedom

by delivering it to the stability of facticity, to ready-

made values and an ego cemented in contented conformity.

One needs to struggle to sustain a pure reflection that

recognises the self not as an ens causa sui — in this case a

self-caused ego — but as a contentless web of actions 57,

totally free and immersed in a world without any true

underlying meaning. Only then can we stop the futility of

57 In Sartre's terminology, an action is always intentional: "The careless smoker who has through negligence caused the explosion of a powder magazine has not acted." To act is to be aware of what one is doing; for instance, the engineer who accepts the project of designing anew missile as his task has acted, even if he may have done so begrudgingly (Sartre 2003: 455).

Page 64: The Cause of Freedom

64

trying to make freedom be and mould mankind into a one-

dimensional subjectivity. Once we can let the security of a

pre-ordered universe go, we can start a new project that

recognises what men have in common is not their natures,

desires, or rational dispositions, but their metaphysical

condition: we are all condemned to the necessity of being

finite — to labour and die here 58. These are the only

objective realities we encounter and are not free to

moderate. We need a new philosophical ground for our civil

liberties if they are to have any meaningful relationship to

the simple truth of our freedom and the metaphysical ground

that is common to us all. This cannot be accomplished here,

but an aperçu can be given. Our metaphysical condition, or

human condition if one prefers, would be the ground of

humanity's project, something to be intended at the start of

our actions, while also respecting that each man is a

totality unto him/herself. It would navigate individual

difference and the common needs we have as humans all at

once without subsuming one into the other.

58 see (Sartre 1988: 260) and (Sartre 1946)

Page 65: The Cause of Freedom

65

Works Cited

Adams, Donald R. Jr. "Wage Rates in the Early National Period: Philidelphia, 1785-1830". The Journal of Economic History 28.3 (Septemeber 1968): 404-426. Web. 8 August 2013.

Anderson, Thomas. Sartre's Two Ethics: From Authenticity to Integral Humanity. Peru, Illinois: Open Court Publishing, 1993. Print

Atkinson, Anthony B., Piketty, T., and Emmanuel Saez. "Top Incomes in the Long Run of History". Journal of Economic Literature49.1 (2011): 3-71. Web. 26 July 2013.

Page 66: The Cause of Freedom

66

Barrett, Michele. The Politics of Truth: From Marx to Foucault. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1992. Print

Brown, Wendy. Edgework: Critical Essays on Knowledge and Politics. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2005. Print

Catalano, Joseph S. A Commentary on Jean-Paul Sartre's Being and Nothingness. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press, 1974. Print

Catalano, Joseph S. "Good and Bad Faith: Weak and Strong Notions". Existentialist Ethics.

Christian, William. "The Moral Economics of Tom Paine". Journal of the History of Ideas 34.3 (July-September 1973): 367-380.JSTOR. Web. 28 July 2013

Church, Jeffery. "Selfish and Moral Politics: David Hume onStability and Cohesion in the Modern State". The Journal of Politics 69.1 (February 2007): 169-181. JSTOR. Web. 10 August 2013.

Cover, Albert D. and Jeffery A. Segal. "Ideological Values of the U.S. Supreme Court Justices". The American Political Science Review 83.2 (June 1989): 557-565. Web. 2 August 2013.

Dewey, John. "The Ethics of Democracy". The Early Works of John Dewey Vol. 1, 1882-1898: Early Essays and Leibniz's New Essays, 1882-1888 (Collected Works of John Dewey). Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press, 2008. Print

Diggins, John Patrick. The Lost Soul of American Politics: Virtue, Self-Interest, and the Foundations of Liberalism. New York: Basic Books, 1984. Print

Edwards, Chris. "Wisconsin Should Go Even Further". Cato Institute. 18 February 2011. Accessed 31 July 2013

Page 67: The Cause of Freedom

67

Foucault, Michel. The Birth of Biopolitics: Lectures at the College de France 1978-9. New York: Palgrave MacMillan, 2008. Print.

Foucault, Michel. The Essential Works of Foucault 1954-1984: Power Vol. 3. London: Penguin Books, 1994. Print

Foucault, Michel. The History of Sexuality Vol. 1. New York, NY: Penguin Paperbacks, 1978. Print

Freeden, Michael. "Ideology and Political Theory". Journal of Political Ideologies 11.1 (August 2006): 3-22. Web. 3 August 2013

Gershon, Illana. "Neoliberal Agency". Current Anthropology 52.4(August 2011): 537-555. JSTOR. Web. 12 July 2013.

Gramsci, Antonio. Selections from the Prison Notebooks. New York: International Publishers, 1971, Print.

Greene, Norman N. Jean-Paul Sartre: The Existential Ethic. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press, 1963. Print

Harvey, David. "The Crisis and Consolidation of Class Power: Is This Really the End of Neoliberalism?". Counterpunch. weekend ed 13-15 March 2009. http://www.counterpunch.org/2009/03/13/is-this-really-the-end-of-neoliberalism. Accessed 3 August 2013.

Hayek, F.A. The Constitution of Liberty. Chicago, IL: University ofChicago Press, 1960. Print

Hayek, F.A. Individualism and the Economic Order. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1958. eBook

Hayek, F.A. The Road to Serfdom: Text and Documents, The Definitive Edition. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 2007. Print

Hume, David. An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998. Print

Page 68: The Cause of Freedom

68

Hume, David. Essays: Moral Political Literary. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund Press, 1985. Print

Hursh, David. "Assessing No Child Left Behind and the Rise of Neoliberal Education Policies". American Education Research Journal 44.3 (September 2007): 493-518. Web. 1 August 2013.

"I.W.W. Strike Chief Lynched at Butte". New York Times. 2 August 1917. Web Archive. http://query.nytimes.com/mem/archive-free/pdf?res=9D06E3DA133AE433A25751C0A96E9C946696D6CF

Jones, Daniel Stedman. Masters of the Universe: Hayek, Friedman, and the Birth of Neoliberal Politics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2012. eBook

Kalish, John. "A Somber Centennial for the Triangle Factory Fire". All Things Considered. NPR. 24 March 2011. Radio

Keyssar, Alexander. The Right to Vote: The Contested History of Democracy in the United States.

Klausen, Jimmy Casas. "Room Enough, America, Natural Liberty, and Consent in Locke's Second Treatise". The Journal of Politics 69.3 (August 2007): 760-769. JSTOR. Web. 21 July, 2013.

Krugman, Paul. The Conscience of a Liberal. New York, NY: W.W. Norton & Company, Inc., 2007. eBook

Layton, Lyndsey. "Study: Charter schools get less funding than traditional public schools". The Washington Post. 7 April 2013. Accessed 1 August 2013.

Lemke, Thomas. "The Birth of Bio-Politics: Michel Foucault's Lecture at the College de France on Neo-Liberal

Page 69: The Cause of Freedom

69

Governmentality". Economy and Society 30.2 (May 2001): 190-207. Web. 25 July 2013.

Lindert, Perter H. and Jeffery G. Williamson. "American Incomes 1774-1860". The National Bureau of Economic Research. NBER Working Paper No. 18396 (September 2012). Web. 8 August 2013.

Locke, John and C.B. MacPherson, ed. Second Treatise of Government. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1980. Print—, Hollis, Thomas, ed. Two Treatises of Government. London: A Millar et al., 1764. eBook

MacPherson, C.B. The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism: Hobbes to Locke. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1962. Print

Madison, James. "The Federalist No. 10: The Utility of the Union as a Safeguard Against Domestic Faction and Insurrection". The Federalist Papers. www.consitution.org/fed/federa10.htm.

Mirowski, Philip and Dieter Plehwe, eds. The Road from Mont Pelerin. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2009. Print

Mises, Ludwig von. Bureaucracy. Indianapolic, IN: Liberty Fund, Inc, 2007. eBook

Mises, Magrit von. My Years with Ludwig von Mises. New Rochelle, NY: Arlington House Publishers, 1976. Print

McGowan, John. American Liberalism: An Interpretation of Our Time. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 2007. Print

"Monongah Mining Disaster of 1907". Encyclopaedia Britannica. http://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/389922/Monongah-mining-disaster-of-1907. 12 July 2013

Page 70: The Cause of Freedom

70

Morgan, Matthew. "The Paradoxical Perpetuation of Neoliberalism: How Ideologies are Formed and Dissolved". Heathwood Press. Heathwood Institute and Press., 19 June 2013. Web. 29 July 2013.

Mouffe, Chantal. The Return of the Political. New York: Verso, 1993.Print

"Obama-Backed Trans-Pacific Partnership Expands Corporate Lawsuits Against Nations for Lost Profits". Democracy Now. Democracynow.org. 6 June 2013. Internet.

Odysseos, Louiza. "Human Rights, Liberal Ontogenesis and Freedom: Producing a Subject for Neoliberalism?". Millennium - Journal of International Studies 38.3 (April 2012): 747-772. Sagepub. Web. 21 May 2013.

Ranelagh, John. Thatcher's People: An Insider's Account of the Politics, Power, and the Personalities. New York: Harper Collins, 1991.

Reagan, Ronald. "A Time for Choosing". http://www.reagan.utexas.edu/archives/reference/timechoosing.html

Roosevelt, Franklin Delano. "The Four Freedoms". American Rhetoric: Top 100 Speeches. www.americanrhetoric.com. accessed 1 August 2013.

Rose, Nikolas. Powers of Freedom: Reframing Political Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004. Print

Sartre, Jean-Paul. Being and Nothingness. Abingdon, OX: Routledge Classics, 2003. Print

Sartre, Jean-Paul. "Existentialism is a Humanism". Marxist Internet Archive, 1946. http://www.marxists.org/reference/archive/sartre/works/exist/sartre.htm. accessed 31 May 2013.

Page 71: The Cause of Freedom

71

Sartre, Jean-Paul. Nausea. New York, NY: New Directions, 2007. Print

Sartre, Jean-Paul. The Words. New York, NY: Vintage Books, 1981. Print

Schmitt, Carl. The Crisis of Parliamentary Democracy. Cambridge: MITPress, 2000. Print.

Schmitt, Carl. Political Theology. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 1985. Print

Simon, Roger. Gramsci's Political Thought: An Introduction. London: TheElectric Book Company, 2001. eBook

Slack, Megan. "President Obama Explains His Plan to Combat Rising College Costs". The White House Blog. The White House: President Obama. Whitehouse.gov. 22 August 2013. Internet

Smith, Aaron. "The Costs of Compulsory Education". Mises Daily. Ludwig von Mises Institute. Mises.org. 22 June 2011. Web. 8 July 2013.

Smith, Joseph. The American Constitution: The First Two Hundred Years, 1787-1987. Exeter: University of Exeter Press, 1987. Print

Sumner, William Graham. What the Social Classes Owe Each Other. Caldwell, Idaho: The Caxton Printers, Ltd., 1974. eBook

Turner, Rachel. Neo-Liberal Ideology: History, Concepts, and Policies. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2008. Print

Verheyden-Hilliard, Mara. "Getting the Facts Straight on H.R. 347, WBAI News Interview with Mara Verheyden-Hilliard".Partnership for Civil Justice Fund. 8 March 2013. Audio File. Accessed 2 August 2013.

Page 72: The Cause of Freedom

72

Werner, John M. "David Hume in America". The Journal of the History of Ideas 33.3 (September 1972): 439-456. JSTOR. Web. 10 August 2013Wilson V. New. 243 U.S. 332. Supreme Court of the United States. 1917. Justia: The Supreme Court Center. Web. 13 August 2013.https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/243/332/

Wood, Gordon S. "Ideology and the Origins of Liberal America". The William and Mary Quarterly 44.3 (July 1987): 628-640. JSTOR. Web. 01 August 2013.

Zernike, Kate. "Wisconsin's Legacy of Labor Battle". New York Times. 5 March 2011. Accessed 31 July 2013.

Zizek, Jacques. Mapping Ideology. London: Verso, 1994. Print


Related Documents