Top Banner
Introduction to Philosophy Truth, Postmodernism & Pluralism By Professor Christopher Ullman
42

Introduction to Philosophy

Feb 09, 2016

Download

Documents

Italia

Introduction to Philosophy. Truth, Postmodernism & Pluralism By Professor Christopher Ullman. A statement is true if it corresponds to reality, and a statement is false if it does not correspond to reality. All truth claims are absolute, narrow and exclusive. - PowerPoint PPT Presentation
Welcome message from author
This document is posted to help you gain knowledge. Please leave a comment to let me know what you think about it! Share it to your friends and learn new things together.
Transcript
Page 1: Introduction to Philosophy

Introduction to Philosophy

Truth, Postmodernism & PluralismBy Professor Christopher Ullman

Page 2: Introduction to Philosophy

10 Truths about Truth1. A statement is true if it

corresponds to reality, and a statement is false if it does not correspond to reality.

2. All truth claims are absolute, narrow and exclusive.

3. Truth is discovered, not invented. It exists independently of anyone’s knowledge of it.

4. Truth is indispensable for living. Consider the need for truth in matters relating to safety, money, relationships, transportation, and court proceedings.

5. Beliefs cannot change a fact.

6. Truth is trans-cultural. 7. Being raised in a given

culture doesn’t make the beliefs of that culture true.

8. Truth is not affected by the attitude of the one professing it.

9. Contrary beliefs are possible, but contrary truths are not possible.

10. We can believe everything is true, but we cannot make everything true.

Page 3: Introduction to Philosophy

Think about these 10 statements, then …

Ask yourself, “What if even one of these statements was not true? How would that change the way I think?”

Page 4: Introduction to Philosophy

The Three Laws of Rational Thought The Principle of Identity: “It is what it

is.”One must be able to say, “If a thing is A,

then it is A”. A thing (object, person, entity, concept) cannot continue to exist and at the same time cease to exist.

Examples:• A = A• If it is a cat, then it is a cat.• If Springfield is the capital of Illinois, then it

is true that Springfield is the capital of Illinois.

Page 5: Introduction to Philosophy

The Three Laws of Rational Thought The Principle of Non-Contradiction: “It is not

what it isn’t.”One must be able to say, “If a thing is A, then it is

not non-A”. A thing (object, person, entity, concept) cannot be itself and its opposite, in the same sense at the same time.

Examples:• A non-A• If it is a cat, then it is not a non-cat.• If Springfield is the capital of Illinois, then it is not

true that Springfield is the non-capital of Illinois.

Page 6: Introduction to Philosophy

The Three Laws of Rational Thought The Principle of the Excluded Middle: “It

either is or it isn’t.”One must be able to say, “A thing is either A

or non-A.” A thing (object, person, entity, concept) must be either exactly as it is described or not.

Examples: Either A or non-A It is either a cat or it is a non-cat. Either Springfield is the capital of Illinois

or it is not the capital of Illinois.

Page 7: Introduction to Philosophy

These Three Laws make it possible for you to speak or write a statement, and expect it to be:

Understood, and • Accepted, or• Rejected, or • Shelved, awaiting more information

Each truth claim must be either1. Accepted for sufficient reasons2. Rejected for sufficient reasons3. Shelved with judgment suspended, pending the

investigation of reasons for and against it.

Page 8: Introduction to Philosophy

What cannot happen, if one intends to be rational, is to respond to a truth claim in these ways:

“That may be true for you but not for me.”

“Everything is merely an opinion, and each opinion is as good as another.”

“You can believe it’s up, and I can believe it’s down, and we can both be right.”

“If you think it is, then it is. If you think it isn’t, then it isn’t. It’s all in a person’s mind.”

Page 9: Introduction to Philosophy

A Postmodernist’s Creed

“Nothing is certain.” “Nobody knows anything for

sure.” “Everything ought to be

doubted.” “What is true for you may not

be true for me.”

Page 10: Introduction to Philosophy

“Nothing is certain.”

Is this statement certain? a. If so, it contradicts itself, since one thing

is certain: that nothing is certain. b. If this statement isn’t certain, why is it

stated in such certain terms? It’s wording doesn’t convey a sense of

uncertainty about its truth. The postmodernist apparently is certain about this. See a.

c. Either way, I must conclude that this statement is false.

Page 11: Introduction to Philosophy

“Nobody knows anything for sure.”

Can I know this for sure? a. If I can know this for sure, then the

statement contradicts itself. b. If I can’t know this for sure, then why is it

stated so surely, in such forceful, confident language?

It seems as if the postmodernist believes this to be a certainty. See a.

c. Either way, I must conclude that this statement also is false.

Page 12: Introduction to Philosophy

“Everything ought to be doubted.”

Does this include the statement, “Everything ought to be doubted?”

a. `If it does include the statement “Everything must be doubted,” then I must doubt that everything ought to be doubted.

I will either end up rejecting the statement or accepting it.

Page 13: Introduction to Philosophy

“Everything ought to be doubted.” (continued)

If I refuse to doubt the above statement, I will be creating a “DO NOT DOUBT!” box.

“DO NOT

DOUBT THIS!”

If I put anything in this box, I refute the above statement!

“Everything ought to be doubted.”

Page 14: Introduction to Philosophy

“Everything ought to be doubted.” (continued)

If I decide to doubt the above statement,

What criterion will I use to determine if the statement can survive my doubting process, and become a certainty?

Choosing any criterion establishes something objective that cannot be doubted.

This refutes the above statement.

“Everything ought to be doubted.”

• If I can’t find a criterion, I can’t start doubting!

• Either way, I must conclude the above statement is false.

Page 15: Introduction to Philosophy

“What’s true for you may not be true for me.”

Obviously, this statement must apply to itself, as well as to all other truth claims. If so, then the above statement is true for you,

but not necessarily for me. So, if it’s not true for me, then I must be open

to the idea that some things that are true for you are also true for me.

There must be a jointly held “truth box” we both can access.

How we decide what belongs in it requires criteria we can both agree about.

The criteria become some things that are both true for you and true for me, and for everyone.

This means the statement above is false.

Page 16: Introduction to Philosophy

Self-referential Incoherence This occurs when a statement cannot be true if it

is applied to itself. All four of the Postmodern Creed truth claims are

this way. The only way they can be true is if they are false. This results in a self-contradicting set of beliefs.

The Law of Noncontradiction is essential to rationality. Therefore, this Postmodernist’s Creed is irrational.

Page 17: Introduction to Philosophy

The truth is: There must be truth.

This truth entails (requires) • Criteria for evaluating truth claims• Minds to do the evaluating tasks

If you are reading this, it means you have a mind, and are capable of evaluating truth

claims using criteria, and we can continue for a bit longer in

this discussion.

Page 18: Introduction to Philosophy

CriteriaWhat are they?1. Standards on which

a judgment or decision may be based

2. Characterizing marks or traits

Why are they needed? To answer these

questions When we say

something is true, what convinces us?

How can we hope to convince others?

Page 19: Introduction to Philosophy

Four Major Groups

1. Immediate criteria

2. Social criteria

3. Philosophical criteria

4. Revelation

Page 20: Introduction to Philosophy

Immediate Criteria

1. Instinct - "My instincts tell me this is true."

2. Feeling - "My gut tells me this is true," or "I can feel it in my bones."

3. Sensed experience - "My senses tell me this is true."

4. Intuition - "It came to me in a flash!"

Page 21: Introduction to Philosophy

Social Criteria

1. Custom - "It is our custom to say this is true."

2. Tradition - "For generations, we have held this to be true."

3. Universal agreement (consensus) - "Everyone knows this is true."

Page 22: Introduction to Philosophy

Philosophical Criteria

1. Correspondence - "This idea corresponds with reality, so it is true."

2. Pragmatism - "It works, so it must be true.”

3. Coherence - "It is systematically consistent with what has been found to be probably true, so it is probably true."

Page 23: Introduction to Philosophy

Revelation

Divine revelation - "It is true because God has said in the Scriptures that it is true."

Page 24: Introduction to Philosophy

A Question

Which criteria can serve as the final court of appeal?

Probably only revelation

Page 25: Introduction to Philosophy

Why revelation?

The revelation criterion presupposes

1. A perfectly intelligent being to whom all truth is known

2. That this being has self-disclosed

3. That this being values truthfulness

If these three presuppositions are true, then

1. Divine revelation will stand as the ultimate arbiter of all truth-claims

2. Nothing that can be called "true" can possibly contradict this revelation

Page 26: Introduction to Philosophy

Religion and Truth

1. No one follows a religion that s/he believes to be false

2. Confidence in the truthfulness of one’s religion is important

3. Truth claims build belief systems for the religion’s adherents

4. Truth claims can be based on several different criteria at once

Each truth claim must be either1. Accepted for sufficient reasons2. Rejected for sufficient reasons3. Shelved with judgment suspended,

pending the investigation of reasons for and against it.

Page 27: Introduction to Philosophy

Different uses of “knowledge”

A. I know how to ride a bicycle.B. I know that it is cold outside.C. I know my A, B, C’s.D. I know my friend John very well.E. I know that he would not lie.F. I know my next-door neighbor.Group this into similar ways of using

the word “know.”

Page 28: Introduction to Philosophy

Different uses “knowledge”Knowledge by acquaintance.

I know my friend John very well.I know my next-door neighbor.

Knowledge howI know how to ride a bicycleI know my A, B, C’s.

Knowledge that (propositional knowledge)I know that it is cold outside.I know that he would not lie.

Philosophers have tended to focus on “knowledge that,” propositional knowledge.

Page 29: Introduction to Philosophy

What does it mean to “know” something?

In order to know something, one must believe that it is true. One can’t know something that one does not

believe. (Believing is a necessary condition for knowing.)

For example: Imagine that I don’t believe that George Bush in the President of the U.S. If this is true, I could not be said to know that George Bush is the President of the United States.

One can believe something that one does not know. (Believing is not a sufficient condition for knowing.

For example: Imagine that on the basis of a vague horoscope message for the day, I believe I will win the lottery. I believe it, but I do not know it.

Page 30: Introduction to Philosophy

Belief is a necessary, but not a sufficient condition for knowledge:

Page 31: Introduction to Philosophy

What does it mean to “know” something? In order to know something, the thing

I know must be true. One can’t know something that is false.

(The truth of the proposition known is a necessary condition for knowing.)

For example: I cannot know that John Kerry is the president of the U.S.

A proposition can be true without my knowing it. (The truth of a proposition not a sufficient condition for knowing it.)

For example: Imagine that it there are 200 patients at Finley Hospital right now. The fact that this is true does not mean that I know that it is true.

Page 32: Introduction to Philosophy

Truth is a necessary, but not a sufficient condition for knowledge:

Page 33: Introduction to Philosophy

True beliefs could be diagrammed like this:

Page 34: Introduction to Philosophy

What does it mean to “know” something?

True beliefs may not be knowledge: For example: Imagine that every Monday I

wake up with the belief that I will win the lottery.

I have never won the lottery in my life, in spite of the fact that every Monday I believe I will.

Imagine that I do win the lottery today. Did I know I would?

My belief is true, but it is not knowledge. The problem is, I did not have a good reason for

my belief, I wasn’t “justified” in my belief.

Page 35: Introduction to Philosophy

Only justified, true beliefs are cases of knowledge:

Page 36: Introduction to Philosophy

But what does it mean to say that a belief is justified?

Descartes was looking for evidence that the belief could not be false, for absolute certainty. (Infallible justification) Although Descartes didn’t think so,

most philosophers today believe this results in skepticism.

Alternative: Justification can be fallible. One can have good reasons or evidence without absolute certainty.

Page 37: Introduction to Philosophy

Three kinds of knowledge

Acquaintance knowledge I know Oxford.

Ability knowledge I know how to ride a bike.

Propositional knowledge I know that elephants are heavier than

mice.

Page 38: Introduction to Philosophy

Justified true belief

Analyses knowledge in terms of necessary and sufficient conditions

‘I know that p’: The proposition ‘p’ is true; I believe that p; and My belief that p is justified.

Page 39: Introduction to Philosophy

Necessary and sufficient conditions

Each condition is necessary for knowledge. The three conditions together are sufficient for

knowledge.

Page 40: Introduction to Philosophy

The appeal of Justified True Belief

I can’t know what is false. I can’t know a proposition that I don’t

believe to be true. Beliefs that are irrational or aren’t

based on the evidence aren’t knowledge.

Page 41: Introduction to Philosophy

Objection

Is this enough for knowledge? Or should we consider what the facts

might have been?

That’s Judy!

Case 1: Meeting Judy

That’s Judy!

Case 2: Meeting Trudy

Page 42: Introduction to Philosophy

Development Condition 4: My justification for

believing that p ‘stands up to the facts’. I know that p if my justification for

believing that p is ‘undefeated’.