Top Banner
The complexity within well-partial-orderings Antonio Montalb´ an University of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb´ an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22
93

University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Aug 26, 2020

Download

Documents

dariahiddleston
Welcome message from author
This document is posted to help you gain knowledge. Please leave a comment to let me know what you think about it! Share it to your friends and learn new things together.
Transcript
Page 1: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

The complexity within well-partial-orderings

Antonio Montalban–

University of Chicago

Madison, March 2012

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22

Page 2: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

1 Background on WQOs

2 WQOs in Proof TheoryKruskal’s theorem and the graph-minor theoremLinear orderings and Fraısse’s Conjecture

3 WPOs in Computability Theory

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 2 / 22

Page 3: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Well-quasi-orderings

Definition: A well-quasi-ordering (WQO), is quasi-ordering which has noinfinite descending sequences and no infinite antichains.

Example: The following sets are WQO under an embeddability relation:

finite strings over a finite alphabet [Higman 52];

finite trees [Kruskal 60],

labeled transfinite sequences with finite labels [Nash-Williams 65];

countable linear orderings [Laver 71];

finite graphs [Robertson, Seymour].

Definition:A well-partial-ordering (WPO), is a WQO which is a partial ordering.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 3 / 22

Page 4: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Well-quasi-orderings

Definition: A well-quasi-ordering (WQO), is quasi-ordering which has noinfinite descending sequences and no infinite antichains.

Example: The following sets are WQO under an embeddability relation:

finite strings over a finite alphabet [Higman 52];

finite trees [Kruskal 60],

labeled transfinite sequences with finite labels [Nash-Williams 65];

countable linear orderings [Laver 71];

finite graphs [Robertson, Seymour].

Definition:A well-partial-ordering (WPO), is a WQO which is a partial ordering.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 3 / 22

Page 5: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Well-quasi-orderings

Definition: A well-quasi-ordering (WQO), is quasi-ordering which has noinfinite descending sequences and no infinite antichains.

Example: The following sets are WQO under an embeddability relation:

finite strings over a finite alphabet [Higman 52];

finite trees [Kruskal 60],

labeled transfinite sequences with finite labels [Nash-Williams 65];

countable linear orderings [Laver 71];

finite graphs [Robertson, Seymour].

Definition:A well-partial-ordering (WPO), is a WQO which is a partial ordering.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 3 / 22

Page 6: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Well-quasi-orderings

Definition: A well-quasi-ordering (WQO), is quasi-ordering which has noinfinite descending sequences and no infinite antichains.

Example: The following sets are WQO under an embeddability relation:

finite strings over a finite alphabet [Higman 52];

finite trees [Kruskal 60],

labeled transfinite sequences with finite labels [Nash-Williams 65];

countable linear orderings [Laver 71];

finite graphs [Robertson, Seymour].

Definition:A well-partial-ordering (WPO), is a WQO which is a partial ordering.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 3 / 22

Page 7: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Well-quasi-orderings

Definition: A well-quasi-ordering (WQO), is quasi-ordering which has noinfinite descending sequences and no infinite antichains.

Example: The following sets are WQO under an embeddability relation:

finite strings over a finite alphabet [Higman 52];

finite trees [Kruskal 60],

labeled transfinite sequences with finite labels [Nash-Williams 65];

countable linear orderings [Laver 71];

finite graphs [Robertson, Seymour].

Definition:A well-partial-ordering (WPO), is a WQO which is a partial ordering.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 3 / 22

Page 8: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Well-quasi-orderings

Definition: A well-quasi-ordering (WQO), is quasi-ordering which has noinfinite descending sequences and no infinite antichains.

Example: The following sets are WQO under an embeddability relation:

finite strings over a finite alphabet [Higman 52];

finite trees [Kruskal 60],

labeled transfinite sequences with finite labels [Nash-Williams 65];

countable linear orderings [Laver 71];

finite graphs [Robertson, Seymour].

Definition:A well-partial-ordering (WPO), is a WQO which is a partial ordering.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 3 / 22

Page 9: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Well-quasi-orderings

Definition: A well-quasi-ordering (WQO), is quasi-ordering which has noinfinite descending sequences and no infinite antichains.

Example: The following sets are WQO under an embeddability relation:

finite strings over a finite alphabet [Higman 52];

finite trees [Kruskal 60],

labeled transfinite sequences with finite labels [Nash-Williams 65];

countable linear orderings [Laver 71];

finite graphs [Robertson, Seymour].

Definition:A well-partial-ordering (WPO), is a WQO which is a partial ordering.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 3 / 22

Page 10: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Well-quasi-orderings

Definition: A well-quasi-ordering (WQO), is quasi-ordering which has noinfinite descending sequences and no infinite antichains.

Example: The following sets are WQO under an embeddability relation:

finite strings over a finite alphabet [Higman 52];

finite trees [Kruskal 60],

labeled transfinite sequences with finite labels [Nash-Williams 65];

countable linear orderings [Laver 71];

finite graphs [Robertson, Seymour].

Definition:A well-partial-ordering (WPO), is a WQO which is a partial ordering.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 3 / 22

Page 11: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Well-partial-orders

There are many equivalent characterizations of WPOs:

P is well-founded and has no infinite antichains;

for every f : N→ P there exists i < j such that f (i) 6P f (j);

every subset of P has a finite set of minimal elements;

all linear extensions of P are well-orders.

The reverse mathematics and computability theory of these equivalenceswas been studied in [Cholak-Marcone-Solomon 04].

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 4 / 22

Page 12: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Well-partial-orders

There are many equivalent characterizations of WPOs:

P is well-founded and has no infinite antichains;

for every f : N→ P there exists i < j such that f (i) 6P f (j);

every subset of P has a finite set of minimal elements;

all linear extensions of P are well-orders.

The reverse mathematics and computability theory of these equivalenceswas been studied in [Cholak-Marcone-Solomon 04].

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 4 / 22

Page 13: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Well-partial-orders

There are many equivalent characterizations of WPOs:

P is well-founded and has no infinite antichains;

for every f : N→ P there exists i < j such that f (i) 6P f (j);

every subset of P has a finite set of minimal elements;

all linear extensions of P are well-orders.

The reverse mathematics and computability theory of these equivalenceswas been studied in [Cholak-Marcone-Solomon 04].

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 4 / 22

Page 14: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Well-partial-orders

There are many equivalent characterizations of WPOs:

P is well-founded and has no infinite antichains;

for every f : N→ P there exists i < j such that f (i) 6P f (j);

every subset of P has a finite set of minimal elements;

all linear extensions of P are well-orders.

The reverse mathematics and computability theory of these equivalenceswas been studied in [Cholak-Marcone-Solomon 04].

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 4 / 22

Page 15: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Well-partial-orders

There are many equivalent characterizations of WPOs:

P is well-founded and has no infinite antichains;

for every f : N→ P there exists i < j such that f (i) 6P f (j);

every subset of P has a finite set of minimal elements;

all linear extensions of P are well-orders.

The reverse mathematics and computability theory of these equivalenceswas been studied in [Cholak-Marcone-Solomon 04].

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 4 / 22

Page 16: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Well-partial-orders

There are many equivalent characterizations of WPOs:

P is well-founded and has no infinite antichains;

for every f : N→ P there exists i < j such that f (i) 6P f (j);

every subset of P has a finite set of minimal elements;

all linear extensions of P are well-orders.

The reverse mathematics and computability theory of these equivalenceswas been studied in [Cholak-Marcone-Solomon 04].

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 4 / 22

Page 17: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Closure properties of WPOs

The sum and disjoint sum of two WPOs are WPO

The product of two WPOs is WPO

Finite strings over a WPO are a WPO (Higman, 1952)

Finite trees with labels from a WPO are a WPO (Kruskal, 1960)

Transfinite sequences with labels from a WPO which use only finitelymany labels are a WPO (Nash-Williams, 1965)

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 5 / 22

Page 18: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Closure properties of WPOs

The sum and disjoint sum of two WPOs are WPO

The product of two WPOs is WPO

Finite strings over a WPO are a WPO (Higman, 1952)

Finite trees with labels from a WPO are a WPO (Kruskal, 1960)

Transfinite sequences with labels from a WPO which use only finitelymany labels are a WPO (Nash-Williams, 1965)

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 5 / 22

Page 19: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Closure properties of WPOs

The sum and disjoint sum of two WPOs are WPO

The product of two WPOs is WPO

Finite strings over a WPO are a WPO (Higman, 1952)

Finite trees with labels from a WPO are a WPO (Kruskal, 1960)

Transfinite sequences with labels from a WPO which use only finitelymany labels are a WPO (Nash-Williams, 1965)

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 5 / 22

Page 20: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Closure properties of WPOs

The sum and disjoint sum of two WPOs are WPO

The product of two WPOs is WPO

Finite strings over a WPO are a WPO (Higman, 1952)

Finite trees with labels from a WPO are a WPO (Kruskal, 1960)

Transfinite sequences with labels from a WPO which use only finitelymany labels are a WPO (Nash-Williams, 1965)

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 5 / 22

Page 21: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Closure properties of WPOs

The sum and disjoint sum of two WPOs are WPO

The product of two WPOs is WPO

Finite strings over a WPO are a WPO (Higman, 1952)

Finite trees with labels from a WPO are a WPO (Kruskal, 1960)

Transfinite sequences with labels from a WPO which use only finitelymany labels are a WPO (Nash-Williams, 1965)

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 5 / 22

Page 22: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Closure properties of WPOs

The sum and disjoint sum of two WPOs are WPO

The product of two WPOs is WPO

Finite strings over a WPO are a WPO (Higman, 1952)

Finite trees with labels from a WPO are a WPO (Kruskal, 1960)

Transfinite sequences with labels from a WPO which use only finitelymany labels are a WPO (Nash-Williams, 1965)

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 5 / 22

Page 23: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Length

Recall: Every linearization of a WPO is well-ordered.

(6L

is a linearization of (P,6P

) if it’s linear and x 6P

y ⇒ x 6L

y .

So, if xn is 6L

decreasing, ∀i < j (xi 66Pxj).

Definition: The length of P = (P,6P

) is

o(P) = supordType(W ,6L) : where 6

Lis a linearization of P.

Def: Bad(P) = 〈x0, ..., xn−1〉 ∈ P<ω : ∀i < j < n (xi 66Pxj),

Note: P is a WPO ⇔ Bad(P) is well-founded.

Theorem: [De Jongh, Parikh 77] o(P) + 1 = rk(Bad(P)).

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 6 / 22

Page 24: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Length

Recall: Every linearization of a WPO is well-ordered.(6

Lis a linearization of (P,6

P) if it’s linear and x 6

Py ⇒ x 6

Ly .

So, if xn is 6L

decreasing, ∀i < j (xi 66Pxj).

Definition: The length of P = (P,6P

) is

o(P) = supordType(W ,6L) : where 6

Lis a linearization of P.

Def: Bad(P) = 〈x0, ..., xn−1〉 ∈ P<ω : ∀i < j < n (xi 66Pxj),

Note: P is a WPO ⇔ Bad(P) is well-founded.

Theorem: [De Jongh, Parikh 77] o(P) + 1 = rk(Bad(P)).

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 6 / 22

Page 25: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Length

Recall: Every linearization of a WPO is well-ordered.(6

Lis a linearization of (P,6

P) if it’s linear and x 6

Py ⇒ x 6

Ly .

So, if xn is 6L

decreasing, ∀i < j (xi 66Pxj).

Definition: The length of P = (P,6P

) is

o(P) = supordType(W ,6L) : where 6

Lis a linearization of P.

Def: Bad(P) = 〈x0, ..., xn−1〉 ∈ P<ω : ∀i < j < n (xi 66Pxj),

Note: P is a WPO ⇔ Bad(P) is well-founded.

Theorem: [De Jongh, Parikh 77] o(P) + 1 = rk(Bad(P)).

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 6 / 22

Page 26: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Length

Recall: Every linearization of a WPO is well-ordered.(6

Lis a linearization of (P,6

P) if it’s linear and x 6

Py ⇒ x 6

Ly .

So, if xn is 6L

decreasing, ∀i < j (xi 66Pxj).

Definition: The length of P = (P,6P

) is

o(P) = supordType(W ,6L) : where 6

Lis a linearization of P.

Def: Bad(P) = 〈x0, ..., xn−1〉 ∈ P<ω : ∀i < j < n (xi 66Pxj),

Note: P is a WPO ⇔ Bad(P) is well-founded.

Theorem: [De Jongh, Parikh 77] o(P) + 1 = rk(Bad(P)).

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 6 / 22

Page 27: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Length

Recall: Every linearization of a WPO is well-ordered.(6

Lis a linearization of (P,6

P) if it’s linear and x 6

Py ⇒ x 6

Ly .

So, if xn is 6L

decreasing, ∀i < j (xi 66Pxj).

Definition: The length of P = (P,6P

) is

o(P) = supordType(W ,6L) : where 6

Lis a linearization of P.

Def: Bad(P) = 〈x0, ..., xn−1〉 ∈ P<ω : ∀i < j < n (xi 66Pxj),

Note: P is a WPO ⇔ Bad(P) is well-founded.

Theorem: [De Jongh, Parikh 77] o(P) + 1 = rk(Bad(P)).

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 6 / 22

Page 28: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Length

Recall: Every linearization of a WPO is well-ordered.(6

Lis a linearization of (P,6

P) if it’s linear and x 6

Py ⇒ x 6

Ly .

So, if xn is 6L

decreasing, ∀i < j (xi 66Pxj).

Definition: The length of P = (P,6P

) is

o(P) = supordType(W ,6L) : where 6

Lis a linearization of P.

Def: Bad(P) = 〈x0, ..., xn−1〉 ∈ P<ω : ∀i < j < n (xi 66Pxj),

Note: P is a WPO ⇔ Bad(P) is well-founded.

Theorem: [De Jongh, Parikh 77] o(P) + 1 = rk(Bad(P)).

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 6 / 22

Page 29: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

1 Background on WQOs

2 WQOs in Proof TheoryKruskal’s theorem and the graph-minor theoremLinear orderings and Fraısse’s Conjecture

3 WPOs in Computability TheoryAntonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 7 / 22

Page 30: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Kruskal’s theorem

Theorem: [Kruskal 60] Let T be the set of finite trees ordered byT 4 S if there is an embedding : T → S preserving 6 and g .l .b.

Then T is a WQO.

Theorem: [Friedman] The length of T is > Γ0.

(where Γ0 is the the proof-theoretic ordinal of ATR0.It’s the “least ordinal” that ATR0 can’t prove it’s an ordinal.

ATR0 –Arithmetic Transfinite Recursion– is the subsystem of 2nd-order arithmetic

that allows the iteration of the Turing jump along any ordinal.)

Corollary: [Friedman] (RCA0) Kruskal’s theorem ⇒ Γ0 well-ordered.Therefore,

ATR0 6` Kruskal’s theorem.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 7 / 22

Page 31: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Kruskal’s theorem

Theorem: [Kruskal 60] Let T be the set of finite trees ordered byT 4 S if there is an embedding : T → S preserving 6 and g .l .b.

Then T is a WQO.

Theorem: [Friedman] The length of T is > Γ0.

(where Γ0 is the the proof-theoretic ordinal of ATR0.It’s the “least ordinal” that ATR0 can’t prove it’s an ordinal.

ATR0 –Arithmetic Transfinite Recursion– is the subsystem of 2nd-order arithmetic

that allows the iteration of the Turing jump along any ordinal.)

Corollary: [Friedman] (RCA0) Kruskal’s theorem ⇒ Γ0 well-ordered.Therefore,

ATR0 6` Kruskal’s theorem.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 7 / 22

Page 32: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Kruskal’s theorem

Theorem: [Kruskal 60] Let T be the set of finite trees ordered byT 4 S if there is an embedding : T → S preserving 6 and g .l .b.

Then T is a WQO.

Theorem: [Friedman] The length of T is > Γ0.

(where Γ0 is the the proof-theoretic ordinal of ATR0.It’s the “least ordinal” that ATR0 can’t prove it’s an ordinal.

ATR0 –Arithmetic Transfinite Recursion– is the subsystem of 2nd-order arithmetic

that allows the iteration of the Turing jump along any ordinal.)

Corollary: [Friedman] (RCA0) Kruskal’s theorem ⇒ Γ0 well-ordered.Therefore,

ATR0 6` Kruskal’s theorem.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 7 / 22

Page 33: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Kruskal’s theorem

Theorem: [Kruskal 60] Let T be the set of finite trees ordered byT 4 S if there is an embedding : T → S preserving 6 and g .l .b.

Then T is a WQO.

Theorem: [Friedman] The length of T is > Γ0.

(where Γ0 is the the proof-theoretic ordinal of ATR0.It’s the “least ordinal” that ATR0 can’t prove it’s an ordinal.

ATR0 –Arithmetic Transfinite Recursion– is the subsystem of 2nd-order arithmetic

that allows the iteration of the Turing jump along any ordinal.)

Corollary: [Friedman] (RCA0) Kruskal’s theorem ⇒ Γ0 well-ordered.Therefore,

ATR0 6` Kruskal’s theorem.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 7 / 22

Page 34: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Kruskal’s theorem

Theorem: [Kruskal 60] Let T be the set of finite trees ordered byT 4 S if there is an embedding : T → S preserving 6 and g .l .b.

Then T is a WQO.

Theorem: [Friedman] The length of T is > Γ0.

(where Γ0 is the the proof-theoretic ordinal of ATR0.It’s the “least ordinal” that ATR0 can’t prove it’s an ordinal.

ATR0 –Arithmetic Transfinite Recursion– is the subsystem of 2nd-order arithmetic

that allows the iteration of the Turing jump along any ordinal.)

Corollary: [Friedman] (RCA0) Kruskal’s theorem ⇒ Γ0 well-ordered.Therefore,

ATR0 6` Kruskal’s theorem.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 7 / 22

Page 35: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

The “big five” subsystems of 2nd-order arithmetic

Axiom systems:RCA0:

Recursive Comprehension + Σ01-induction + Semiring ax.

WKL0:

Weak Konig’s lemma + RCA0

ACA0:

Arithmetic Comprehension + RCA0

⇔ “for every set X , X ′ exists”.

ATR0:

Arithmetic Transfinite recursion + ACA0.⇔ “ ∀X , ∀ ordinal α, X (α) exists”.

Π11-CA0:

Π11-Comprehension + ACA0.

⇔ “∀X , the hyper-jump of X exists”.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 8 / 22

Page 36: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

The “big five” subsystems of 2nd-order arithmetic

Axiom systems:RCA0: Recursive Comprehension + Σ0

1-induction + Semiring ax.

WKL0:

Weak Konig’s lemma + RCA0

ACA0:

Arithmetic Comprehension + RCA0

⇔ “for every set X , X ′ exists”.

ATR0:

Arithmetic Transfinite recursion + ACA0.⇔ “ ∀X , ∀ ordinal α, X (α) exists”.

Π11-CA0:

Π11-Comprehension + ACA0.

⇔ “∀X , the hyper-jump of X exists”.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 8 / 22

Page 37: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

The “big five” subsystems of 2nd-order arithmetic

Axiom systems:RCA0: Recursive Comprehension + Σ0

1-induction + Semiring ax.

WKL0: Weak Konig’s lemma + RCA0

ACA0:

Arithmetic Comprehension + RCA0

⇔ “for every set X , X ′ exists”.

ATR0:

Arithmetic Transfinite recursion + ACA0.⇔ “ ∀X , ∀ ordinal α, X (α) exists”.

Π11-CA0:

Π11-Comprehension + ACA0.

⇔ “∀X , the hyper-jump of X exists”.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 8 / 22

Page 38: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

The “big five” subsystems of 2nd-order arithmetic

Axiom systems:RCA0: Recursive Comprehension + Σ0

1-induction + Semiring ax.

WKL0: Weak Konig’s lemma + RCA0

ACA0: Arithmetic Comprehension + RCA0

⇔ “for every set X , X ′ exists”.

ATR0:

Arithmetic Transfinite recursion + ACA0.⇔ “ ∀X , ∀ ordinal α, X (α) exists”.

Π11-CA0:

Π11-Comprehension + ACA0.

⇔ “∀X , the hyper-jump of X exists”.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 8 / 22

Page 39: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

The “big five” subsystems of 2nd-order arithmetic

Axiom systems:RCA0: Recursive Comprehension + Σ0

1-induction + Semiring ax.

WKL0: Weak Konig’s lemma + RCA0

ACA0: Arithmetic Comprehension + RCA0

⇔ “for every set X , X ′ exists”.

ATR0: Arithmetic Transfinite recursion + ACA0.⇔ “ ∀X , ∀ ordinal α, X (α) exists”.

Π11-CA0:

Π11-Comprehension + ACA0.

⇔ “∀X , the hyper-jump of X exists”.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 8 / 22

Page 40: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

The “big five” subsystems of 2nd-order arithmetic

Axiom systems:RCA0: Recursive Comprehension + Σ0

1-induction + Semiring ax.

WKL0: Weak Konig’s lemma + RCA0

ACA0: Arithmetic Comprehension + RCA0

⇔ “for every set X , X ′ exists”.

ATR0: Arithmetic Transfinite recursion + ACA0.⇔ “ ∀X , ∀ ordinal α, X (α) exists”.

Π11-CA0: Π1

1-Comprehension + ACA0.⇔ “∀X , the hyper-jump of X exists”.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 8 / 22

Page 41: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

The exact reversals

[Friedman] Neither of ATR0, or Kruskal’s theorem implies the other.

Thm: [Rathjen–Weiermann 93] The length of T is the Ackerman ordinalθΩω.The following are equivalent over RCA0

Kruskal’s theorem.

The Π11-reflection principle for Π1

2-bar induction.

Thm: [M.–Weiermann 2006] The following are equivalent over RCA0

ATR0

For every P, if P is a WQO, then so is T (P),where T (P) is the set of finite trees with labels in P, ordered by

homomorphism.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 9 / 22

Page 42: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

The exact reversals

[Friedman] Neither of ATR0, or Kruskal’s theorem implies the other.

Thm: [Rathjen–Weiermann 93] The length of T is the Ackerman ordinalθΩω.The following are equivalent over RCA0

Kruskal’s theorem.

The Π11-reflection principle for Π1

2-bar induction.

Thm: [M.–Weiermann 2006] The following are equivalent over RCA0

ATR0

For every P, if P is a WQO, then so is T (P),where T (P) is the set of finite trees with labels in P, ordered by

homomorphism.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 9 / 22

Page 43: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

The exact reversals

[Friedman] Neither of ATR0, or Kruskal’s theorem implies the other.

Thm: [Rathjen–Weiermann 93] The length of T is the Ackerman ordinalθΩω.The following are equivalent over RCA0

Kruskal’s theorem.

The Π11-reflection principle for Π1

2-bar induction.

Thm: [M.–Weiermann 2006] The following are equivalent over RCA0

ATR0

For every P, if P is a WQO, then so is T (P),where T (P) is the set of finite trees with labels in P, ordered by

homomorphism.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 9 / 22

Page 44: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

The minor-graph theorem

Theorem: [Robertson, Seymour]

Let G be the set of finite graphs ordered by the minor relation.Then G is a WQO.

Theorem: [Friedman, Robertson, Seymour] The length of G is > φ0(εΩω+1).

(where φ0(εΩω+1), the Takeuti-Feferman-Buchholz ordinal,is the the proof-theoretic ordinal of Π1

1-CA0.

Π11-CA0 – is the system that allows Π1

1-comprehension.)

Corollary: [Friedman, Robertson, Seymour]

(RCA0) The minor-grarph theorem ⇒ φ0(εΩω+1) well-ordered.Therefore,

Π11-CA0 6` minor-graph theorem.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 10 / 22

Page 45: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

The minor-graph theorem

Theorem: [Robertson, Seymour]

Let G be the set of finite graphs ordered by the minor relation.Then G is a WQO.

Theorem: [Friedman, Robertson, Seymour] The length of G is > φ0(εΩω+1).

(where φ0(εΩω+1), the Takeuti-Feferman-Buchholz ordinal,is the the proof-theoretic ordinal of Π1

1-CA0.

Π11-CA0 – is the system that allows Π1

1-comprehension.)

Corollary: [Friedman, Robertson, Seymour]

(RCA0) The minor-grarph theorem ⇒ φ0(εΩω+1) well-ordered.Therefore,

Π11-CA0 6` minor-graph theorem.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 10 / 22

Page 46: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

The minor-graph theorem

Theorem: [Robertson, Seymour]

Let G be the set of finite graphs ordered by the minor relation.Then G is a WQO.

Theorem: [Friedman, Robertson, Seymour] The length of G is > φ0(εΩω+1).

(where φ0(εΩω+1), the Takeuti-Feferman-Buchholz ordinal,is the the proof-theoretic ordinal of Π1

1-CA0.

Π11-CA0 – is the system that allows Π1

1-comprehension.)

Corollary: [Friedman, Robertson, Seymour]

(RCA0) The minor-grarph theorem ⇒ φ0(εΩω+1) well-ordered.Therefore,

Π11-CA0 6` minor-graph theorem.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 10 / 22

Page 47: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

The minor-graph theorem

Theorem: [Robertson, Seymour]

Let G be the set of finite graphs ordered by the minor relation.Then G is a WQO.

Theorem: [Friedman, Robertson, Seymour] The length of G is > φ0(εΩω+1).

(where φ0(εΩω+1), the Takeuti-Feferman-Buchholz ordinal,is the the proof-theoretic ordinal of Π1

1-CA0.

Π11-CA0 – is the system that allows Π1

1-comprehension.)

Corollary: [Friedman, Robertson, Seymour]

(RCA0) The minor-grarph theorem ⇒ φ0(εΩω+1) well-ordered.Therefore,

Π11-CA0 6` minor-graph theorem.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 10 / 22

Page 48: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

The minor-graph theorem

Theorem: [Robertson, Seymour]

Let G be the set of finite graphs ordered by the minor relation.Then G is a WQO.

Theorem: [Friedman, Robertson, Seymour] The length of G is > φ0(εΩω+1).

(where φ0(εΩω+1), the Takeuti-Feferman-Buchholz ordinal,is the the proof-theoretic ordinal of Π1

1-CA0.

Π11-CA0 – is the system that allows Π1

1-comprehension.)

Corollary: [Friedman, Robertson, Seymour]

(RCA0) The minor-grarph theorem ⇒ φ0(εΩω+1) well-ordered.Therefore,

Π11-CA0 6` minor-graph theorem.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 10 / 22

Page 49: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Fraısse’s Conjecture

Theorem [Fraısse’s Conjecture ’48; Laver ’71]

FRA:The countable linear orderings are WQO under embeddablity.

Theorem[Shore ’93]

FRA implies ATR0 over RCA0.

Conjecture:[Clote ’90][Simpson ’99][Marcone]

FRA is equivalent to ATR0 over RCA0.

Π12-CA0

;;;

;;;;

;

Π11-CA0

FRA

wwoooATR0

ACA0

WKL0

RCA0

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 11 / 22

Page 50: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Fraısse’s Conjecture

Theorem [Fraısse’s Conjecture ’48; Laver ’71]

FRA:The countable linear orderings are WQO under embeddablity.

Theorem[Shore ’93]

FRA implies ATR0 over RCA0.

Conjecture:[Clote ’90][Simpson ’99][Marcone]

FRA is equivalent to ATR0 over RCA0.

Π12-CA0

;;;

;;;;

;

Π11-CA0

FRA

wwoooATR0

ACA0

WKL0

RCA0

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 11 / 22

Page 51: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

The “big five” subsystems of 2nd-order arithmetic

Axiom systems:RCA0: Recursive Comprehension + Σ0

1-induction + Semiring ax.

WKL0: Weak Konig’s lemma + RCA0

ACA0: Arithmetic Comprehension + RCA0

⇔ “for every set X , X ′ exists”.

ATR0: Arithmetic Transfinite recursion + ACA0.⇔ “ ∀X , ∀ ordinal α, X (α) exists”.

Π11-CA0: Π1

1-Comprehension + ACA0.⇔ “∀X , the hyper-jump of X exists”.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 12 / 22

Page 52: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Fraısse’s conjecture again.

Claim

RCA0+FRA is the least system where it is possible to develop a reasonabletheory of embeddability of linear orderings.

Theorem

The following are equivalent over RCA0

FRA;

Every scattered lin. ord. is a finite sum of indecomposables;

Every indecomposable lin. ord. is either an ω-sum or an ω∗-sum ofindecomposable l.o. of smaller rank.

Jullien’s characterization of extendible linear orderings

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 13 / 22

Page 53: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Fraısse’s conjecture again.

Claim

RCA0+FRA is the least system where it is possible to develop a reasonabletheory of embeddability of linear orderings.

Theorem

The following are equivalent over RCA0

FRA;

Every scattered lin. ord. is a finite sum of indecomposables;

Every indecomposable lin. ord. is either an ω-sum or an ω∗-sum ofindecomposable l.o. of smaller rank.

Jullien’s characterization of extendible linear orderings

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 13 / 22

Page 54: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

A Partition theorem

Theorem:[Folklore] If we color Q with finitely many colors, there exists anembedding Q→ Q whose image has only one color.

Theorem:[Laver ’72]

For every countable L, there exists nL ∈ N, such that:If L is colored with finitely many colors,

there is an embedding L → L whose image has at most nL colors.

Theorem ([M. 2005])

FRA is implied by Laver’s Theorem above over RCA0.

Theorem ([Kach–Marcone–M.–Weiermann 2011])

FRA is equivalent to Laver’s Theorem above over RCA0.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 14 / 22

Page 55: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

A Partition theorem

Theorem:[Folklore] If we color Q with finitely many colors, there exists anembedding Q→ Q whose image has only one color.

Theorem:[Laver ’72]

For every countable L, there exists nL ∈ N, such that:If L is colored with finitely many colors,

there is an embedding L → L whose image has at most nL colors.

Theorem ([M. 2005])

FRA is implied by Laver’s Theorem above over RCA0.

Theorem ([Kach–Marcone–M.–Weiermann 2011])

FRA is equivalent to Laver’s Theorem above over RCA0.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 14 / 22

Page 56: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

A Partition theorem

Theorem:[Folklore] If we color Q with finitely many colors, there exists anembedding Q→ Q whose image has only one color.

Theorem:[Laver ’72]

For every countable L, there exists nL ∈ N, such that:If L is colored with finitely many colors,

there is an embedding L → L whose image has at most nL colors.

Theorem ([M. 2005])

FRA is implied by Laver’s Theorem above over RCA0.

Theorem ([Kach–Marcone–M.–Weiermann 2011])

FRA is equivalent to Laver’s Theorem above over RCA0.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 14 / 22

Page 57: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

A Partition theorem

Theorem:[Folklore] If we color Q with finitely many colors, there exists anembedding Q→ Q whose image has only one color.

Theorem:[Laver ’72]

For every countable L, there exists nL ∈ N, such that:If L is colored with finitely many colors,

there is an embedding L → L whose image has at most nL colors.

Theorem ([M. 2005])

FRA is implied by Laver’s Theorem above over RCA0.

Theorem ([Kach–Marcone–M.–Weiermann 2011])

FRA is equivalent to Laver’s Theorem above over RCA0.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 14 / 22

Page 58: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Back to FRA

Def: Let Lα be the set of linear orderings of Hausdorff rank < α,quotiented by the bi-embeddability relation, andordered by the embeddability relation.

1 [Laver 71] For countable α, Lα is countable.

2 [M. 05] For computable α, (Lα,4) is computably presentable.

3 (This was used to prove that every hypearithmetic linear ordering is

bi-embeddable with a computable one in [M. 05])

4 FRA is equivalent to “∀ ordinal α < ω1 (Lα is WQO).”

Question: Given α, what is the length of Lα?

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 15 / 22

Page 59: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Back to FRA

Def: Let Lα be the set of linear orderings of Hausdorff rank < α,quotiented by the bi-embeddability relation, andordered by the embeddability relation.

1 [Laver 71] For countable α, Lα is countable.

2 [M. 05] For computable α, (Lα,4) is computably presentable.

3 (This was used to prove that every hypearithmetic linear ordering is

bi-embeddable with a computable one in [M. 05])

4 FRA is equivalent to “∀ ordinal α < ω1 (Lα is WQO).”

Question: Given α, what is the length of Lα?

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 15 / 22

Page 60: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Back to FRA

Def: Let Lα be the set of linear orderings of Hausdorff rank < α,quotiented by the bi-embeddability relation, andordered by the embeddability relation.

1 [Laver 71] For countable α, Lα is countable.

2 [M. 05] For computable α, (Lα,4) is computably presentable.

3 (This was used to prove that every hypearithmetic linear ordering is

bi-embeddable with a computable one in [M. 05])

4 FRA is equivalent to “∀ ordinal α < ω1 (Lα is WQO).”

Question: Given α, what is the length of Lα?

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 15 / 22

Page 61: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Back to FRA

Def: Let Lα be the set of linear orderings of Hausdorff rank < α,quotiented by the bi-embeddability relation, andordered by the embeddability relation.

1 [Laver 71] For countable α, Lα is countable.

2 [M. 05] For computable α, (Lα,4) is computably presentable.

3 (This was used to prove that every hypearithmetic linear ordering is

bi-embeddable with a computable one in [M. 05])

4 FRA is equivalent to “∀ ordinal α < ω1 (Lα is WQO).”

Question: Given α, what is the length of Lα?

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 15 / 22

Page 62: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Back to FRA

Def: Let Lα be the set of linear orderings of Hausdorff rank < α,quotiented by the bi-embeddability relation, andordered by the embeddability relation.

1 [Laver 71] For countable α, Lα is countable.

2 [M. 05] For computable α, (Lα,4) is computably presentable.

3 (This was used to prove that every hypearithmetic linear ordering is

bi-embeddable with a computable one in [M. 05])

4 FRA is equivalent to “∀ ordinal α < ω1 (Lα is WQO).”

Question: Given α, what is the length of Lα?

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 15 / 22

Page 63: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Back to FRA

Def: Let Lα be the set of linear orderings of Hausdorff rank < α,quotiented by the bi-embeddability relation, andordered by the embeddability relation.

1 [Laver 71] For countable α, Lα is countable.

2 [M. 05] For computable α, (Lα,4) is computably presentable.

3 (This was used to prove that every hypearithmetic linear ordering is

bi-embeddable with a computable one in [M. 05])

4 FRA is equivalent to “∀ ordinal α < ω1 (Lα is WQO).”

Question: Given α, what is the length of Lα?

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 15 / 22

Page 64: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Finite Hausdorff rank

Theorem ([Marcone, M 08])

The length of Lω is εεε... ,the first fixed point of the function α 7→ εα

Note: εεε... is the proof-theoretic ordinal of ACA+,where ACA+ is the system RCA0+∀X (X (ω) exists.

(So εεε... is the least ordinal that ACA+ can’t prove is well-ordered.)

Theorem ([Marcone, M 08])

The following are equivalent over ACA+:

εεε... is well-ordered

Lω is a WQO

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 16 / 22

Page 65: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Finite Hausdorff rank

Theorem ([Marcone, M 08])

The length of Lω is εεε... ,the first fixed point of the function α 7→ εα

Note: εεε... is the proof-theoretic ordinal of ACA+,where ACA+ is the system RCA0+∀X (X (ω) exists.

(So εεε... is the least ordinal that ACA+ can’t prove is well-ordered.)

Theorem ([Marcone, M 08])

The following are equivalent over ACA+:

εεε... is well-ordered

Lω is a WQO

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 16 / 22

Page 66: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Finite Hausdorff rank

Theorem ([Marcone, M 08])

The length of Lω is εεε... ,the first fixed point of the function α 7→ εα

Note: εεε... is the proof-theoretic ordinal of ACA+,where ACA+ is the system RCA0+∀X (X (ω) exists.

(So εεε... is the least ordinal that ACA+ can’t prove is well-ordered.)

Theorem ([Marcone, M 08])

The following are equivalent over ACA+:

εεε... is well-ordered

Lω is a WQO

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 16 / 22

Page 67: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

1 Background on WQOs

2 WQOs in Proof TheoryKruskal’s theorem and the graph-minor theoremLinear orderings and Fraısse’s Conjecture

3 WPOs in Computability TheoryAntonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 17 / 22

Page 68: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

complexity of maximal order types

Recall: o(P) = supordType(P,6L) : where 6

Lis a linearization of P.

Theorem: [De Jongh, Parikh 77]

Every WPO P has a linearization of order type o(P).

We call such a linearization, a maximal linearization of P.

Such linearizations have been found by different methods in differentexamples.

Question [Schmidt 1979]:Is the length of a computable WPO computable?

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 17 / 22

Page 69: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

complexity of maximal order types

Recall: o(P) = supordType(P,6L) : where 6

Lis a linearization of P.

Theorem: [De Jongh, Parikh 77]

Every WPO P has a linearization of order type o(P).

We call such a linearization, a maximal linearization of P.

Such linearizations have been found by different methods in differentexamples.

Question [Schmidt 1979]:Is the length of a computable WPO computable?

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 17 / 22

Page 70: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

complexity of maximal order types

Recall: o(P) = supordType(P,6L) : where 6

Lis a linearization of P.

Theorem: [De Jongh, Parikh 77]

Every WPO P has a linearization of order type o(P).

We call such a linearization, a maximal linearization of P.

Such linearizations have been found by different methods in differentexamples.

Question [Schmidt 1979]:Is the length of a computable WPO computable?

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 17 / 22

Page 71: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

complexity of maximal order types

Recall: o(P) = supordType(P,6L) : where 6

Lis a linearization of P.

Theorem: [De Jongh, Parikh 77]

Every WPO P has a linearization of order type o(P).

We call such a linearization, a maximal linearization of P.

Such linearizations have been found by different methods in differentexamples.

Question [Schmidt 1979]:Is the length of a computable WPO computable?

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 17 / 22

Page 72: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

complexity of maximal order types

Recall: o(P) = supordType(P,6L) : where 6

Lis a linearization of P.

Theorem: [De Jongh, Parikh 77]

Every WPO P has a linearization of order type o(P).

We call such a linearization, a maximal linearization of P.

Such linearizations have been found by different methods in differentexamples.

Question [Schmidt 1979]:Is the length of a computable WPO computable?

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 17 / 22

Page 73: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Computable Length

Q: Is the length of a computable WPO, computable?

We mentioned that o(P) + 1 = rk(Bad(P)), where

Bad(P) = 〈x0, ..., xn−1〉 ∈W<ω : ∀i < j < n (xi 66Pxj),

Since Bad(P) is computable and well-founded, it has rank < ωCK1 .

So, o(P) is a computable ordinal.

Q:Does every computable WPO have a computable maximal linearization?

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 18 / 22

Page 74: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Computable Length

Q: Is the length of a computable WPO, computable?

We mentioned that o(P) + 1 = rk(Bad(P)), where

Bad(P) = 〈x0, ..., xn−1〉 ∈W<ω : ∀i < j < n (xi 66Pxj),

Since Bad(P) is computable and well-founded, it has rank < ωCK1 .

So, o(P) is a computable ordinal.

Q:Does every computable WPO have a computable maximal linearization?

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 18 / 22

Page 75: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Computable Length

Q: Is the length of a computable WPO, computable?

We mentioned that o(P) + 1 = rk(Bad(P)), where

Bad(P) = 〈x0, ..., xn−1〉 ∈W<ω : ∀i < j < n (xi 66Pxj),

Since Bad(P) is computable and well-founded, it has rank < ωCK1 .

So, o(P) is a computable ordinal.

Q:Does every computable WPO have a computable maximal linearization?

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 18 / 22

Page 76: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

A computable maximal linearization

Theorem ([M 2007])

Every computable WPO has a computable maximal linearization.

Q: Can we find them uniformly?

Theorem ([M 2007])

There is computable procedure thatgiven P produces a linearization L such that for some δ

ωδ 6 L 6 o(P) < ωδ+1.

Theorem ([M 2007])

Let a be a Turing degree. TFAE:

1 a uniformly computes maximal linearizations of comp. WPOs.

2 a uniformly computes 0(β) for every β < ωCK1 .

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 19 / 22

Page 77: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

A computable maximal linearization

Theorem ([M 2007])

Every computable WPO has a computable maximal linearization.

Q: Can we find them uniformly?

Theorem ([M 2007])

There is computable procedure thatgiven P produces a linearization L such that for some δ

ωδ 6 L 6 o(P) < ωδ+1.

Theorem ([M 2007])

Let a be a Turing degree. TFAE:

1 a uniformly computes maximal linearizations of comp. WPOs.

2 a uniformly computes 0(β) for every β < ωCK1 .

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 19 / 22

Page 78: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

A computable maximal linearization

Theorem ([M 2007])

Every computable WPO has a computable maximal linearization.

Q: Can we find them uniformly?

Theorem ([M 2007])

There is computable procedure thatgiven P produces a linearization L such that for some δ

ωδ 6 L 6 o(P) < ωδ+1.

Theorem ([M 2007])

Let a be a Turing degree. TFAE:

1 a uniformly computes maximal linearizations of comp. WPOs.

2 a uniformly computes 0(β) for every β < ωCK1 .

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 19 / 22

Page 79: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

A computable maximal linearization

Theorem ([M 2007])

Every computable WPO has a computable maximal linearization.

Q: Can we find them uniformly?

Theorem ([M 2007])

There is computable procedure thatgiven P produces a linearization L such that for some δ

ωδ 6 L 6 o(P) < ωδ+1.

Theorem ([M 2007])

Let a be a Turing degree. TFAE:

1 a uniformly computes maximal linearizations of comp. WPOs.

2 a uniformly computes 0(β) for every β < ωCK1 .

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 19 / 22

Page 80: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

The height of a WPO

We denote by Ch(P) the collection of all chains of P.

P is a WPO ⇒ all its chains are well-orders.

Definition

If P is well founded, its height is

ht(P) = supα : ∃C ∈ Ch(P)α = ordType(L).We can also define the height of x ∈ P:

htP(x) = suphtP(y) + 1 : y <P x.

Theorem: [Wolk 1967]If P is a WPO, there exists C ∈ Ch(P) with order type ht(P).

Such a chain is called a maximal chain of P.

Q: How difficult is it to compute maximal chains?

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 20 / 22

Page 81: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

The height of a WPO

We denote by Ch(P) the collection of all chains of P.

P is a WPO ⇒ all its chains are well-orders.

Definition

If P is well founded, its height is

ht(P) = supα : ∃C ∈ Ch(P)α = ordType(L).We can also define the height of x ∈ P:

htP(x) = suphtP(y) + 1 : y <P x.

Theorem: [Wolk 1967]If P is a WPO, there exists C ∈ Ch(P) with order type ht(P).

Such a chain is called a maximal chain of P.

Q: How difficult is it to compute maximal chains?

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 20 / 22

Page 82: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

The height of a WPO

We denote by Ch(P) the collection of all chains of P.

P is a WPO ⇒ all its chains are well-orders.

Definition

If P is well founded, its height is

ht(P) = supα : ∃C ∈ Ch(P)α = ordType(L).

We can also define the height of x ∈ P:

htP(x) = suphtP(y) + 1 : y <P x.

Theorem: [Wolk 1967]If P is a WPO, there exists C ∈ Ch(P) with order type ht(P).

Such a chain is called a maximal chain of P.

Q: How difficult is it to compute maximal chains?

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 20 / 22

Page 83: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

The height of a WPO

We denote by Ch(P) the collection of all chains of P.

P is a WPO ⇒ all its chains are well-orders.

Definition

If P is well founded, its height is

ht(P) = supα : ∃C ∈ Ch(P)α = ordType(L).We can also define the height of x ∈ P:

htP(x) = suphtP(y) + 1 : y <P x.

Theorem: [Wolk 1967]If P is a WPO, there exists C ∈ Ch(P) with order type ht(P).

Such a chain is called a maximal chain of P.

Q: How difficult is it to compute maximal chains?

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 20 / 22

Page 84: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

The height of a WPO

We denote by Ch(P) the collection of all chains of P.

P is a WPO ⇒ all its chains are well-orders.

Definition

If P is well founded, its height is

ht(P) = supα : ∃C ∈ Ch(P)α = ordType(L).We can also define the height of x ∈ P:

htP(x) = suphtP(y) + 1 : y <P x.

Theorem: [Wolk 1967]If P is a WPO, there exists C ∈ Ch(P) with order type ht(P).

Such a chain is called a maximal chain of P.

Q: How difficult is it to compute maximal chains?

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 20 / 22

Page 85: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

The height of a WPO

We denote by Ch(P) the collection of all chains of P.

P is a WPO ⇒ all its chains are well-orders.

Definition

If P is well founded, its height is

ht(P) = supα : ∃C ∈ Ch(P)α = ordType(L).We can also define the height of x ∈ P:

htP(x) = suphtP(y) + 1 : y <P x.

Theorem: [Wolk 1967]If P is a WPO, there exists C ∈ Ch(P) with order type ht(P).

Such a chain is called a maximal chain of P.

Q: How difficult is it to compute maximal chains?

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 20 / 22

Page 86: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

The height of a WPO

We denote by Ch(P) the collection of all chains of P.

P is a WPO ⇒ all its chains are well-orders.

Definition

If P is well founded, its height is

ht(P) = supα : ∃C ∈ Ch(P)α = ordType(L).We can also define the height of x ∈ P:

htP(x) = suphtP(y) + 1 : y <P x.

Theorem: [Wolk 1967]If P is a WPO, there exists C ∈ Ch(P) with order type ht(P).

Such a chain is called a maximal chain of P.

Q: How difficult is it to compute maximal chains?

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 20 / 22

Page 87: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Computing maximal chains

Theorem ([Marcone-Shore 2010])

Every computable WPO P has a hyperarithmetic maximal chain.

(Recall: X ⊆ ω is hyperarithmetic iff it’s ∆11.)

Maximal chains aren’t easy to compute:

Theorem ([Marcone–M.–Shore 2012])

Let α < ωCK1 .

There exists a computable WPO P such that0(α) does not compute any maximal chain of P.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 21 / 22

Page 88: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Computing maximal chains

Theorem ([Marcone-Shore 2010])

Every computable WPO P has a hyperarithmetic maximal chain.

(Recall: X ⊆ ω is hyperarithmetic iff it’s ∆11.)

Maximal chains aren’t easy to compute:

Theorem ([Marcone–M.–Shore 2012])

Let α < ωCK1 .

There exists a computable WPO P such that0(α) does not compute any maximal chain of P.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 21 / 22

Page 89: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Computing maximal chains

Maximal chains are not easy to compute,but almost everybody can compute them.

Theorem ([Marcone-M.-Shore 2012])

Let G be hyperarithmetically generic.

Every computable WPO has a maximal chain computable in G .

Pf:• The key observation is that all downward closed subsets of P are computable.

• Then, build an operator ΦP,Gα , that returns a sequence of computablesub-partial orderings P0 6 P1 6 ..., such that, if P has cofinality ωα+1, and Gis generic, then infinitely many of the Pi will have cofinality ωα.

• Then use effective transfinite recursion.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 22 / 22

Page 90: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Computing maximal chains

Maximal chains are not easy to compute,but almost everybody can compute them.

Theorem ([Marcone-M.-Shore 2012])

Let G be hyperarithmetically generic.

Every computable WPO has a maximal chain computable in G .

Pf:• The key observation is that all downward closed subsets of P are computable.

• Then, build an operator ΦP,Gα , that returns a sequence of computablesub-partial orderings P0 6 P1 6 ..., such that, if P has cofinality ωα+1, and Gis generic, then infinitely many of the Pi will have cofinality ωα.

• Then use effective transfinite recursion.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 22 / 22

Page 91: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Computing maximal chains

Maximal chains are not easy to compute,but almost everybody can compute them.

Theorem ([Marcone-M.-Shore 2012])

Let G be hyperarithmetically generic.

Every computable WPO has a maximal chain computable in G .

Pf:• The key observation is that all downward closed subsets of P are computable.

• Then, build an operator ΦP,Gα , that returns a sequence of computablesub-partial orderings P0 6 P1 6 ..., such that, if P has cofinality ωα+1, and Gis generic, then infinitely many of the Pi will have cofinality ωα.

• Then use effective transfinite recursion.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 22 / 22

Page 92: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Computing maximal chains

Maximal chains are not easy to compute,but almost everybody can compute them.

Theorem ([Marcone-M.-Shore 2012])

Let G be hyperarithmetically generic.

Every computable WPO has a maximal chain computable in G .

Pf:• The key observation is that all downward closed subsets of P are computable.

• Then, build an operator ΦP,Gα , that returns a sequence of computablesub-partial orderings P0 6 P1 6 ..., such that, if P has cofinality ωα+1, and Gis generic, then infinitely many of the Pi will have cofinality ωα.

• Then use effective transfinite recursion.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 22 / 22

Page 93: University of Chicagoantonio/slides/Madison2012.pdfUniversity of Chicago Madison, March 2012 Antonio Montalb an (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 1 / 22 1

Computing maximal chains

Maximal chains are not easy to compute,but almost everybody can compute them.

Theorem ([Marcone-M.-Shore 2012])

Let G be hyperarithmetically generic.

Every computable WPO has a maximal chain computable in G .

Pf:• The key observation is that all downward closed subsets of P are computable.

• Then, build an operator ΦP,Gα , that returns a sequence of computablesub-partial orderings P0 6 P1 6 ..., such that, if P has cofinality ωα+1, and Gis generic, then infinitely many of the Pi will have cofinality ωα.

• Then use effective transfinite recursion.

Antonio Montalban (U. of Chicago) Well-Partial-Orderings Madison, March 2012 22 / 22