Top Banner
Thought insertion as a symptom of disownership Michelle Maiese [A longer version of this paper has been published in Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences] Introduction In acute phases of schizophrenia, subjects sometimes describe various thoughts as alien despite their recognition that they occur within their own minds. They characterize these thoughts as ones that have been inserted by some outside source. Stephens and Graham (2000) maintain that in such cases, the sense of ownership is preserved, but there is a defect in the sense of agency (i.e. the sense that one is the author or initiator of the thought). When a subject says that a thought that occurs in her mind is not her own, what she means is that she experiences that thought as “subjectively, but not agentically” her own” (Stephens and Graham 2000, 153). However, their claim that ownership is preserved in such cases is undermined by the fact that “the subject affected by thought insertion is often radically alienated from the thought she reports” (Bortolotti and Broome 2009, 208). These theorists overlook the possibility that subjectivity and ownership might come apart, so that subjectivity is preserved despite a loss of the sense of ownership. To make sense of this, I will examine more 1
37

Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

Feb 21, 2023

Download

Documents

Welcome message from author
This document is posted to help you gain knowledge. Please leave a comment to let me know what you think about it! Share it to your friends and learn new things together.
Transcript
Page 1: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

Thought insertion as a symptom of disownership

Michelle Maiese

[A longer version of this paper has been published in Phenomenology and

the Cognitive Sciences]

Introduction

In acute phases of schizophrenia, subjects sometimes describe

various thoughts as alien despite their recognition that they occur

within their own minds. They characterize these thoughts as ones that

have been inserted by some outside source. Stephens and Graham (2000)

maintain that in such cases, the sense of ownership is preserved, but

there is a defect in the sense of agency (i.e. the sense that one is

the author or initiator of the thought). When a subject says that a

thought that occurs in her mind is not her own, what she means is that

she experiences that thought as “subjectively, but not agentically” her own”

(Stephens and Graham 2000, 153). However, their claim that ownership

is preserved in such cases is undermined by the fact that “the subject

affected by thought insertion is often radically alienated from the

thought she reports” (Bortolotti and Broome 2009, 208). These

theorists overlook the possibility that subjectivity and ownership

might come apart, so that subjectivity is preserved despite a loss of

the sense of ownership. To make sense of this, I will examine more

1

Page 2: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

closely some of the different ways that a thought might be said to

“belong” to a subject. I will maintain that ‘subjectivity’ should be

understood as the distinct “how” of experience, namely its for-me-ness

and first-personal presence; and that the ‘sense of ownership,’ on the

other hand, should be understood as a feeling of “mine-ness,” or an

impression of being entitled to a mental state. While subjectivity and

ownership ordinarily go hand-in-hand, they can come apart: inserted

thoughts are first-personally presented to the subject (and thus

subjectively experienced), but are not presented as hers.

The claim that schizophrenia indeed centers upon a loss of a

sense of ownership is supported by an examination of some of the other

notable disownership symptoms of the disorder, such as bodily

alienation and experiences of “unworlding.” Is there a way to make

sense of the “underlying characteristic modification” that ties

together the various symptoms of schizophrenia and disrupts subjects’

“hold” on their own bodies and surroundings? I will argue that what

accounts for subjects’ usual sense of ownership are fully embodied

processes of causal-contextual information integration, which are made

possible by subjects’ affective framing patterns. For a mental state to be

owned fully, subjectivity is not sufficient. Also required is

contextual integration: the mental state must occur against the

backdrop of a subject’s desiderative bodily feelings. Attenuated affective

2

Page 3: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

framings lead to a loss of a sense of ownership and cause subjects to

lose their “grip” on bodily sensations and mental states, which

ultimately can result in experiences of thought insertion. Thus,

thought insertion is best understood as one of several disownership

symptoms associated with acute phases of schizophrenia. I will

conclude with some brief remarks about implications for treatment, and

point to several body-centered intervention methods that might help to

restore subjects’ sense of ownership.

Thought insertion: Stephens and Graham

In their characterization of thought insertion, Stephens and

Graham (2000) make a crucial distinction between the sense of

ownership and the sense of agency. They characterize ownership in

terms of subjectivity: subjects acknowledge that that the thoughts

occur within their minds. What they lack is a sense of agency:

thinking, like action, normally is accompanied by a sense of effort

and deliberate choice as we move from one thought to the next. While

subjectivity (ownership) and agency ordinarily go together, they

“represent distinct strands or components of self-consciousness” that

sometimes break apart (Graham and Stephens 2000, 153). While subjectivity

(ownership) is preserved in cases of thought insertion, there is a loss of a

sense of agency. Because the schizophrenic subject finds herself 3

Page 4: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

thinking without any awareness of the sense of effort that ordinarily

accompanies thought, she has the impression that the thoughts were

unintended and therefore alien. She experiences the thoughts as “done

to” her by another. Stephens and Graham call this a “breakdown-in-

the-experience-of-agency model” of alienation. But why would a subject

feel that she is not the agent of a thought occurring in her stream of

consciousness? They maintain that a person denies that she is the

agent of a thought because she finds she cannot explain its occurrence

in terms of her theory or conception of her intentional psychology

(162). We tend to explain particular mental episodes or behavior as

expressions of our underlying, relatively persistent intentional

states (e.g, our beliefs and desires). A subject’s sense of agency

therefore might depend on her ability to integrate her thoughts into a

larger picture of herself. In cases where a subject’s behavior does

not seem appropriate to her and she has no conception of what she is

doing or why she is doing it, she might conclude that what is

happening is none of her doing (Stephens and Graham 2000, 165). In short,

if a subject she finds the thoughts inexplicable by reference to her

self-conception, she is unlikely to regard them as agentically her

own.

However, as these theorists acknowledge, this account does not

yet explain why subjects experience such thoughts as alien and

4

Page 5: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

controlled by some external agent, rather than merely as unintended or

a matter of thought influence. What is needed is an account of “how

the subject’s having the impression that she did not intend to think a

certain thought leads her to the hypothesis that someone else thinks

or causes her to think that thought” (Stephens and Graham 2000, 144).

There must be some reason why the subject takes her thoughts to be

expressions of another’s mental agency rather than mere mental

happenings. Stephens and Graham maintain that despite the subject’s

conviction that the episode of thinking does not express her

underlying psychology, “the episode may still impress her as

intentional” (2000, 172). This is because although the thoughts

“strike her as contextually unsuitable and personally

uncharacteristic,” their coherence, saliency, and directedness make it

seem as if some sort of agency or intelligence is responsible for

them. Rather than concluding that they are random mental activities,

the subject has a strong impression that someone else has produced

these thoughts. Thus, according to Stephens and Graham, it is the

apparent intelligence of the thoughts that provides the experiential

or epistemic basis for attributing them to another agent.

One problem with these theorists’ account is that it appears to

be unable to make sense of the difference between thought insertion

and other phenomena involving impairments in agency. Intrusive or

5

Page 6: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

unbidden thoughts, for example, are passive and enter the subject’s

stream of consciousness without her having a sense that she is the

author or initiator of these thoughts. Indeed, this is relatively

common in cases of obsessive compulsive disorder (OCD). However,

subjects with OCD readily acknowledge that these unbidden thoughts are

theirs. Thus, it is not clear that pointing to an impaired sense

agency allows us to distinguish between inserted thoughts and unbidden

thoughts and explain why subjects retain a sense of ownership in the

latter case but not the former. Stephens and Graham maintain that the

key difference between unbidden thoughts and inserted thoughts is that

the subject with OCD takes herself to have beliefs and desires of the

sort that explain these obsessive thoughts, and therefore experiences

compulsive thoughts as her own; whereas the schizophrenic subject has

no beliefs and desires that explain the inserted thoughts (2000, 178).

However, it turns out that unbidden thoughts, like inserted thoughts,

may seem not only truly surprising and unexpected, but also deeply

inconsistent with subjects’ overall self-view. Something similar might

be said even about non-pathological, ordinary cases in which

unsolicited thoughts spring spontaneously to mind. Thus, it seems

clear that “the sense of passivity in belief formation cannot be the

core element of the condition of thought insertion” (Bortolotti and

Broome 2009, 220). Moreover, given that the experience of alienation

6

Page 7: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

likely arises prior to a subject’s attempt to explain a thought’s

occurrence in terms of her theory or conception of her intentional

psychology, their account seems overly intellectualistic. While a

subject’s intentional attribution of thoughts to herself takes place

subsequently to the production of the thought, the subject’s

experience of thought insertion appears to involve a more immediate,

non-observational sense that something is ‘off.’ This sense of

alienness is part of the very process of thought production, and it is

unclear “how judging that a thought is alien to oneself would generate

the distinctive phenomenology required” (Gerrans 2001, 235).

Another shortcoming of Stephens & Graham’s account is that it

overlooks the sensory distortions and bodily disturbances involved in

schizophrenia and says little about how thought insertion is related

to some of the other characteristic symptoms and signs of the

disorder. These symptoms include not just delusions and

hallucinations, but also bodily alienation and experiences of

“unworlding.” Phenomenological psychopathology assumes that there is

some “underlying characteristic modification” of the world of

experience that ties together the various symptoms into a meaningful

whole (Stanghellini 2011, 164). Rather than focusing isolated

symptoms, such as delusions, we need to try to understand the “deeper”

phenomena that are at work. But how are the various sorts of abnormal

7

Page 8: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

phenomena found in schizophrenia interconnected? Many theorists would

agree that schizophrenia involves an altered sense of selfhood, but

there is less agreement about whether this involves loss of

subjectivity, loss of a sense of ownership, or loss of a sense of

agency.

Theorists who have written about thought insertion mention

several different ways in which a thought might be said to “belong” to

a subject. Here I will focus on a subset of the considerations

highlighted by Bortolotti and Broome (2009, 211).:

1) The subject locates the thought in her personal boundaries

(spatiality condition)

2) The subject has direct, first-personal access to the thought

(introspection condition)

3) The subject acknowledges, or is disposed to acknowledge, the

thought as her own (self ascription condition)

In my view, Stephens and Graham are correct when they claim that

the sense of subjectivity is preserved in schizophrenia. Available

evidence suggests that patients are well aware of “where” the thoughts

occur, and that they correctly regard them as occurring within their

own minds by virtue of their being first-personally presented.

Subjectivity involves the conjunction of 1) and 2) above. But

according to Stephens and Graham, locating the thought in one’s

8

Page 9: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

personal boundaries (the spatiality condition) and accessing the

content of the thought directly and first-personally (the

introspection condition) are sufficient to ensure not just subjectivity,

but also ownership (Bortolotti and Broome 2009, 211). They thereby

treat subjectivity and the sense of ownership as if they are the very

same thing. However, it seems clear that acknowledging a thought as

one’s own, or at least being disposed to acknowledge a thought as

one’s own (what Bortolotti and Broome call ‘the self ascription

condition’) is central to the sense of ownership. What makes thought

insertion seem so bizarre, in fact, is that it involves “the divorce

between first-personal awareness of the content of a thought, and the

possibility of self ascribing that thought” (Bortolotti and Broome

2009, 214). In other words, it involves a divorce between

subjectivity and the sense of ownership: while subjectivity (first-

personal access to the thoughts) is preserved, ownership (a sense of

“mineness” or entitlement to the thoughts) is lacking. There is a loss

of overall bodily attunement, and subjects commonly report a sense of

self-detachment, as well as feelings of being a robot, or of observing

their own mental processes from the outside. Of course, we need not

reject the claim that thought insertion also involves a loss of a

sense of agency. After all, if ownership is lacking, it would be

natural suppose that the subject also would lack a sense of agency or

9

Page 10: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

control over these thoughts. What is crucial to note is that the loss

of a sense of ownership exists prior to, and ultimately contributes

to, a loss of a sense of agency.

Disownership symptoms and context integration

Experiences of bodily alienation indicate that schizophrenia does

indeed center upon a loss of a sense of ownership. Here the tacit

self-awareness normally present in experience is weakened or lost,

leading to a felt scission between the schizophrenic subject and her

body. This has led some theorists to characterize those who suffer

from the disorder as “deanimated bodies” or “disembodied spirits.”

Fuchs (2005), for example, argues that the relation of the

schizophrenic subject to the world is deprived of its immediacy due to

what may be described as a disembodied mind (96). Ordinarily subjects

have a tacit, transparent knowledge of the body, and are not aware of

their bodies as thematic, explicit, or focal objects of awareness.

However, in schizophrenia, the body loses its transparency and begins

to seem unfamiliar or artificial. Sass (2004) likewise describes how

schizophrenic subjects experience “a fragmented and alienated sense of

the lived body,” which produces a sense of disharmony and

artificiality that can disrupt the flow of motor activity (134).

10

Page 11: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

Patients experience a variety of quasi-affective sensations and bodily

states, including “sensations of movement or pulling or pressure

inside the body or on its surfaces; electric or migrating sensations;

awareness of kinaesthetic, vestibular, or thermic sensations; and

sensations of diminution or enlargement of the body or its parts”

(Sass 2004, 135). Other abnormal bodily sensations include stiffness,

heaviness, and numbness. In addition to having a sense that the shape

or structure of their body has been altered, schizophrenic subjects

sometimes describe their own bodies as being falsely composed. Often

these experiences are accompanied by disruption of motor activity and

a diminution of automatic skills. Some patients even describe numbness

or vertigo, and report losing a sense of contact with their arms and

legs. However, these strange sensations often feel artificial, free-

floating, and distant rather than being part of one’s coherent and

meaningful engagement with the world. As even these strange sensations

lose their connection with the patient’s sense of self, they become

alienated and thing-like and begin to lose “their emotional aroma”

(Sass 2007, 370).

Similarly, Stangehillini and Ballerini (2004) describe how

subjects suffering from schizophrenic depersonalization experience a

loss of ease in their actions, changes to body morphology, and an

increasing sense of distance from their own bodies. Subjects report

11

Page 12: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

not feeling fully or vitally in touch with theri bodily dynamics, movements,

postures, and expressions. There is a feeling of vagueness and

fogginess, and of being deprived of the certainty of what is one’s

own. Sometimes they also undergo “morbid objectification,” which

involves attributing “thingness” to one’s own body and dismissing its

emotional qualities (Stangehillini and Ballerini 2004, 263).

Schizophrenia appears to involve a disorder of coenthesia, or what might

be described as an impairment of the “functional symphony” in which

all of subject’s various sensations are synthesized (Stanghellini

2004). Because intermodal integration of signals begins to break down,

integrated perception of one’s surroundings becomes very difficult.

Together with abnormal sensations, this disturbance of the synthesis

of sensations leads to a loss of a sense of self and sensory-motor

disintegration. Subjects may experience a lack of contact between

various parts of the body, and sometimes report that “they feel their

limbs detached from the prime initiator” of movement and experience

their actions as “detached from the energy that should spontaneously

feed it” (Stanghellini 2004, 157). As a result of this crisis of

sensory self-consciousness, bodily states are experienced as somehow

disconnected from the subject’s life, so that she begins to feel

deanimated and devitalized. In addition, her immediate experience of

thinking may be replaced by a second-order noetic awareness of perceiving

12

Page 13: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

that she is perceiving, acting, or thinking (Stanghellini 2004, 19), and

she may begin to describe herself as a mere spectator or scanner of her

own mental states. This objectification of thoughts and mental states

can contribute to as the experience of thought insertion.

Such self-detachment also can lead to experiences of

“unworlding.” When that which is typically a matter of automatic and

spontaneous processing becomes explicit, it “can no longer perform the

grounding, orienting, [and] constituting function that only what

remains in the background can play” (Sass and Parnas 2001, 351). As a

result, the “ipseity disturbance” associated with bodily alienation

also leads to an impaired capacity for cognitive engagement with one’s

surroundings. Subjects experience not just an altered sense of

selfhood, but also derealization and what some theorists have called

‘unworlding’: there is a sense of strangeness about external objects

that ordinarily would seem familiar. Schizophrenic subjects find

themselves less able to engage with and “grasp” their surrounding and

there is a loss of a sense of attunement to the world. The cognitive

or perceptual world undergoes a certain fragmentation and objects seem

to lack their recognizable significance and relevance. In addition,

people, actions or things may seem to be stripped of their

recognizable ‘affordances,’ which can result in feelings of anxiety,

wonderment, or awe. Patients feel somehow cut off from the external

13

Page 14: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

world and experience their surroundings as a distant spectacle rather

than “as a terrain of personally relevant opportunity and risk” (Sass

2007, 372). Minkowski and Targowla (2001) describe this phenomenon as

“pragmatic weakening” and a loss of vital contact with reality.

Similarly, Stanghellini (2004) maintains that schizophrenia involves a

“loss of practical references to the world,” so that things do not

“directly and immediately relate to [one’s] body as existentially

relative utensils” (194). As a result, things appear devoid of

meaning, and it becomes difficult for the subject to interact with

them effectively. Once concrete objects lose their incarnated

givenness, they may even transform into images, so that that world

becomes ghostly in a sense.

Bodily alienation, unworlding, and thought insertion all

centrally involve a loss of a sense of ownership. However, this is not

to deny that these phenomena also involve first-order phenomenology

and first-personal givenness (subjectivity). It’s just that their

being subjective does not guarantee these experiences involve a sense

of ownership (i.e. a sense of ”mineness”), though of course

subjectivity and a sense of ownership ordinarily go hand in hand.

(Indeed, what makes thought insertion so very puzzling is that

presents us with a case in which a subject introspects a thought and

experiences it subjectively, and yet does not claim ownership or

14

Page 15: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

acknowledge it as her own.) Whether a mental state is subjective

depends on whether it is given in a first-personal mode of

presentation. Whether a mental state is experienced as mine, on the

other hand, depends on whether I have the impression of being entitled to

it (Bortolotti and Broome 2009, 216). But what does entitlement

amount to exactly? According to Bortolotti and Broome (2009),

entitlement is a matter of self ascription: the subject acknowledges

the thought as her own and typically can give reasons for endorsing

the content of the thought. However, it is crucial to note that

subjects often do not explicitly acknowledge thoughts as their own nor

are they necessarily in a position to give reasons for endorsing their

content. Instead, the sense of “mineness” often seems to be part of,

or absent from, the very process of thought formation. Is there a way

to account for this more fully?

Whether a thought involves a sense of ownership depends on

whether that thought is causally integrated with relevant contextual

information (Martin and Pacherie, 2013, 113). In order to experience

coherent and unified episodes of thinking, one needs to be able to

coordinate relevant contextual information with the content of their

thoughts. A wide range of internal and external factors trigger

thoughts or constrain their content. First, both external factors

(e.g. objects in the environment) as well as internal factors (e.g.

15

Page 16: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

memories or goals) play a crucial role in producing particular

thoughts. Second, a thought that is initially externally- or

internally-driven can be modulated by additional factors, whether

internal or external. These supplementary factors help to determine

the content of one’s thoughts, and might include current perceptual

conditions, current situational conditions, the subject’s background

beliefs and knowledge, the content of preceding thoughts, memory

constraints, and/or the subject’s current emotional state. Due to all

of these contextual constraints and modulating factors, one’s mental

states ordinarily do not simply appear out of nowhere. Even when the

semantic content of one’s current thought does not match with what

would be expected based on one’s preceding thoughts (and thus there is

little semantic coherence), there typically still is causal coherence.

Suppose you are exercising at the gym and suddenly the thought, “I

must not forget my laptop for tonight’s meeting” pops into your head.

This content will appear salient due to the lack of semantic coherence

and your inability to predict that this thought would occur based on

your preceding thoughts. Nonetheless, this thought will not seem

abnormal or alien to you given that some item from your memory (in

this case, your prospective memory of tonight’s meeting) played a role

in triggering the thought about your laptop.

16

Page 17: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

However, it turns out that schizophrenic subjects have difficulty

integrating contextual information in various cognitive domains.

Because their Gestalt organizational processes are impaired, they

experience “basic deficits in the perceptual organization processes

that normally bind elements into a context-appropriate coherent whole”

(Martin & Pacherie 2013, 114). In addition, they have difficulty

processing contextual information related to linguistic stimuli, as

well as information related to events to be stored in memory. To

produce phenomenal causal coherence resulting in a sense of thought

ownership, a system must integrate the causal causal-contextual

information relevant to a subject’s thoughts with the thoughts

themselves. When this integration process is disrupted, a thought

occurs that is disconnected from its causal source, and therefore is

experienced as coming out of nowhere. The link between causal context

and thought is not dynamically maintained and relevant contextual

information is not integrated or coordinated with their thoughts

(Martin and Pacherie 2013, 117). This lack of causal integration leads

directly to an experience of thought insertion.

Note that this account explains why a subject might fail to

ascribe a thought to herself in the way that Bortolotti and Broome

describe. In addition, this account resonates with the one presented

by Stephens and Graham, which says that thoughts seem alien in the

17

Page 18: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

event that the subject does not attribute to herself the sorts of intentional

states that naturally would find expression in those thoughts (2000,

173). However, this new account is far less intellectualistic. It says

that prior to a subject’s considering whether thoughts conform to her

“theory” of what she is like (Stephens and Graham 2000, 163) and thus

what she is likely to do as a person (164), she has some basic, pre-

reflective sense of whether these thoughts “fit” with her surroundings

and with the rest of her beliefs, desires, emotions, memories, and

perceptions. This sense of “fit” has to do with causal coherence and

the integration of causal-contextual information.

Affective framing and the sense of ownership

Martin and Pacherie (2013) point to working memory impairments to

explain why causal-contextual information is not effectively

integrated with subjects’ thinking episodes. Working memory involves

the ability to maintain, manipulate, and coordinate information for a

short period of time. Schizophrenic subjects appear to have deficits

in the various sub-processes that make up working memory, including

encoding contextual information, inhibiting irrelevant information,

and retrieving relevant information. As a result, schizophrenic

subjects exhibit a wide range of information integration deficits that

impact their ability to process linguistic stimuli, remember events,

18

Page 19: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

engage interpersonally with others, and exhibit executive control. All

of these tasks require the inhibition of irrelevant of irrelevant

information and the ability to retrieve information that is relevant

or significant for that particular subject in that particular

situation. It seems clear that schizophrenic subjects exhibit an

overall inability to coordinate and integrate contextual information.

Executive functioning involves the ability to monitor the context

of action, as well as current personal circumstances that might affect

the accuracy of one’s perceptions or one’s ability to complete the

task at hand. While I do not deny that working memory plays a crucial

role in linking features across time and producing coherent thinking

episodes, I maintain that an even deeper explanation is needed. This

is because central to executive functioning is not just working

memory, but also selective attention: it appears that “selection and

intensity of arousal, based on the individual’s personal history,

usually occurs as an aspect of perception” and is linked to “how this

individual perceives any given stimulus or situation at a given

moment” (Brown 2005, 73). But just how are relevant situational

factors noticed, and how do individuals’ personal histories,

background beliefs, and desires shape their patterns of attention? It

is clear that the world somehow shows up as laden with value, but it is

not altogether clear how this occurs or how some segments and aspects

19

Page 20: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

of background context rather than others are deemed significant. It is

possible that selective attention and the weighting of importance is

achieved simply via circuits in the brain.However, it is more

plausible to suppose that the crucial management systems of the brain

are part of a much larger system that includes the whole living body.

After all,

the description that I have presented of some of the

characteristics signs and symptoms of schizophrenia suggest a profound

alteration to subjects’ lived bodily experience. . It appears that

these subjects have lost their “grip” on their own bodily sensations

and mental states and that they display diminished levels of bodily

attunement to their surroundings. I hypothesize that this loss of

bodily attunement is at the core of their loss of a sense of ownership

and agency, and also their inability to process contextual

information.

Most of us have an immediate, pre-theoretical, non-intellectual

understanding of where to direct our attention in a given context.

This ability to home in on salient features of our environment and

make a cut from the stream of information is what cognitive scientists

call ‘framing.’ What I call ‘affective framing’ is the process whereby

we interpret persons, objects, facts, states of affairs, and

20

Page 21: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

situations in terms of embodied desiderative feelings. Just as a conceptual

frame is a cognitive shortcut that people rely on in order to

categorize features of their surroundings, an affective frame operates

as a feeling-driven shortcut whose interpretive focus is targeted and

contoured by an individual’s embodied desires and cares. Detection of

which aspects of our surroundings are relevant typically occurs

outside of reflective self-awareness, is non-algorithmic , and is a

matter of bodily attunement and feelings of subjective import.

Affective framing patterns, developed over time, yield a pre-reflective,

fine-grained contouring of a subject’s surroundings, so that she

immediately can target and focus her attention. The affective arousal

involved in affective framing engages not just neural circuitry, but

also metabolic systems and endocrine responses, and the impact of this

arousal is spread throughout the body in muscles, increased blood

flood, heart rate and blood pressure increases, and vascular

constriction. Which contextual information is relevant to a subject’s

thoughts is partly a function of her desires, concerns, and overall

perspective, so that the bodily feelings of affective framing function

as a structure-giving background to all experience and a presupposed

context for all intellectual, practical, and social activity. This

caring-contoured map of affective framings plays an important role, for

example, in determining which information in working memory will be

21

Page 22: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

held onto, which will fade out, and which will be called into

conscious attention when needed. Affectivity and bodily feeling

thereby bias the competition for processing resources in favor of

information we feel is important.

This proposed conception of affective framing rests on the notion

that the mind is essentially embodied and enactive. Executive functioning and

cognition are not simply things that happen to us internally, but

rather something that we do, in part via our bodily feelings, over the

course of our active engagement with our surroundings. The notion

that we rely heavily on desire-based emotions and affectivity to

filter information about our environment builds on Colombetti and

Thompson’s claim that emotions are simultaneously bodily and

cognitive-evaluative and that they convey personal meaning and

significance (2008, 59). It also builds on Ratcliffe’s claim that

bodily feelings shape the manner in which things appear to us and

thereby structure our reasoning (2005 187).

I maintain that attenuated affective framing explains experiences

of bodily alienation, “unworlding,” and the disturbance in the

combining of context-related stimuli across many domains. Among

schizophrenic subjects there is a notable discrepancy between the

amount of attention something deserves and the amount that it

receives. Subjects with attenuated affective framing processes find it

22

Page 23: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

difficult to focus their attention on what matters and to disregard

things that are irrelevant or unimportant. They experience diminished

bodily attunement, and have lost much of their “grip” on their own

mental states and surroundings. Indeed, a disruption to affective

framing is the “underlying characteristic modification” that ties

together the various symptoms of schizophrenia and can help us to make

sense of the “deep architecture of [the schizophrenic’s] disembodied

and deanimated type of existence” (Stanghellini 2011, 165).

First, attenuated affective framing leads to the loss of personal

relevance, the diminishment of ‘self-affection,’ and the seeming

disruption of background bodily sensation that comprise bodily

alienation. Ordinarily, affective framing allows a subject’s cares and

concerns to serve as a backdrop for all of her experiences, including

basic perceptual experiences and bodily sensations. In schizophrenia,

however, the desiderative bodily feelings that undergird a sense of self are

diminished. Without this framework of bodily attunement to help the

subject make sense of things, intermodal binding and sensory

integration begins to break down. The subject begins to experience

sensations that are dissociated from her ongoing sense of self, lack a

sense of personal relevance, and are experienced as free-floating

rather than being meaningfully directed toward the world (Sass 2004,

135). Bodily feeling loses its intentionality, its desiderative tone,

23

Page 24: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

and its world-directedness. Without some framework in which bodily

feelings can take on relevance and significance, sensations come to be

experienced as distant and object-like, divorced from one’s sense of

self. As bodily tensions and associated affective states lose their

desiderative component, there is a disturbance in the synthesis of

sensations, a diminished sense of immediate acquaintance with one’s

own body, and a breakdown in self-experience.

Second, in the absence of “the targeted and temporal nature of

‘concern’,” (Sass 2004) the world as a whole begins to lose its

practical significance. Ordinarily, we engage with the world in and

through our bodily feelings of caring. It is the desiderative bodily

feelings of affective framing that direct our attention, drive us to

action, and give shape to our perceptual experience. Attenuated

affective framing disrupts perception and cognition (insofar as it

interferes with our focusing of attention) and leads to a disrupted

perceptual or cognitive “hold” or “grip.” For the schizophrenic

subject, things no longer are apprehended against the backdrop of

desiderative bodily feelings, and as a result objects in the world

lose their significance and appear as devoid of meaning. Without a

perspective to ground meaning and value, subjects find it increasingly

difficult to make sense of their surroundings. Like bodily alienation

and disturbed self-experience, “unworlding” is a result of the

24

Page 25: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

schizophrenic subject’s inability to appreciate salience. As a result

of this “unworlding,” the cognitive or perceptual world undergoes a

certain fragmentation and objects seem to lack their recognizable

significance and relevance. Some subjects experience deficits in

perceptual grouping, so that objects do not stand together in an

overall context and instead appear as meaningless details (Sass 2007,

373). They also have difficulty excluding distracting visual,

auditory, and tactile input when trying to concentrate on selected

parts of the environment (Maher 2003, 14).

Interestingly, my proposed account also helps to make sense of

the language disturbances commonly found in schizophrenia. Such

disturbances include the repetition of phrases, frequent uncompleted

sentences, the production of neologisms, circumlocution, and sudden

termination of an utterance before it is complete. Maher (2003)

maintains that these disturbances are caused “by defective deployment

of inhibitory activity necessary to exclude intrusions” (19). The

ability to speak a sequence of words in a sentence is made possible by

the ability to inhibit associations for each separate word, as well as

the ability to screen out external sources such as the speech of

others. In order to inhibit “irrelevant” input and screen out unneeded

information, we must have some way of determining which input is

salient and of subjective import. However, because schizophrenic

25

Page 26: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

subjects are deficient in these inhibition mechanisms and largely

insensitive to context, they are highly susceptible to intrusions,

internal and external distractions, and word associations that are not

relevant to the case at hand. Due to their diminished bodily

attunement, they find it difficult “feel” their way through a

conversation and appreciate the salience of contextual features. Even

the meaning of words may become abstract and divorced from context,

which can result in so-called ‘word salad’ and the overall jumbling of

speech.

Lastly, my account can help us to make sense of thought

insertion. Thought ordinarily depends on a background of beliefs,

desires, and interests, so that which trains of thought are opened up

to a subject usually depends on her particular background of cares and

concerns. It is only when a thought appears against the backdrop of

her beliefs, desires, and background bodily orientation that a subject

will experience herself as the owner (and agent) of the thought. In

schizophrenia, however, this background bodily orientation is severely

attenuated. When thoughts do not arise against the structure-giving

backdrop of a person’s desiderative feelings, her concerns about the

future, or her current needs and desires, these thoughts seem out of

context. Articulated in terms of the ‘mapping’ metaphor I have expressed

previously, these are thoughts that are ‘off the map.’ In an effort to

26

Page 27: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

make sense of these thoughts that seem to have come out of nowhere,

subjects attempt to recontextualize them by attributing them to some other

source (Martin and Pacherie 2013). So what makes inserted thoughts

different from unbidden thoughts that just spring spontaneously to

mind? In cases of unbidden thought, affective framing allows for the

integration of some relevant contextual information, and thus the

sense of ownership is preserved. These unbidden thoughts occur against

the backdrop of subjects’ beliefs, desires, or concerns, even if these

thoughts are not ones the subjects wish to have, nor ones that mesh

with their self-conception. Inserted thoughts, on the other hand, are

not just unintended, but also alien. This alienness, and the subject’s

sense that the inserted thoughts do not truly belong to her, results

from a failure to integrate relevant contextual information; and this

failure to integrate relevant contextual information, in turn, can be

traced to attenuated affective framing.

Can this account make sense of particularly perplexing instances of

thought insertion? There are cases in which the thoughts in question

are pretty mundane and are just the sort of thoughts that the subject

often has (e.g. “It’s about time for dinner.” Why would a subject

attribute such thoughts to an outside source when all signs point to

the thought belonging to her, including the fact that the thoughts

seem to “fit” her present context and circumstances? These are cases

27

Page 28: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

in which the thoughts do seem to be integrated appropriately with

various aspects of the surrounding context, and yet still are

experienced as alien. So how can a breakdown in the integration of

contextual information explain these cases? What is crucial to note is

that while some aspects of the background context (i.e. details of the

situation) seem to be integrated inappropriately, such thoughts

nevertheless may not be arising against the backdrop of bodily

feeling. Even if the thoughts are consistent with the subject’s

background psychology, there may still be a lack of causal-contextual

integration. This is because diminished bodily attunement can cause

thinking processes to lose their sense of naturalness and

transparency. As a result, subjects may assume an objectifying, hyper-

reflective stance (Sass 2000) toward their own thoughts, making even

the most ordinary, mundane thoughts seem foreign. Similarly, at the

level of bodily sensation, even typical feelings of hunger or thirst

may seem alien. This loss of bodily transparency creates a sense of

detachment from the subject’s own body as well as her surroundings, so

that even if her thoughts and sensations “fit” with her surroundings

and situation in some objective sense, she experiences them as free-

floating and distant, and as objects for potential reflection.

Implications for treatment

28

Page 29: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

Drawing upon the Daoist notion of wu-wei (naturalness) and John

Dewey’s conception of “know-how,” Krueger (2009) describes the “ethos

of expertise” as an affective, skill-based capacity that enables

subjects to navigate various domains. For example, the skilled swimmer

coordinates her strokes with the flow of the water “through a deep

ecological sensitivity—a felt union between body and environment” (35).

It is form of nonrepresentational bodily intelligence that involves a

feeling of contextual familiarity and a pre-reflective sense of one’s

own body as the “possessor of certain capacities for action” (Krueger

2009, 40). Certainly this “ethos of expertise,” which I have described

in terms of affective framing, is a matter of the body being attuned

and responsive to situational saliencies of the environment. However,

being attuned to one’s surroundings first requires that one be attuned

and “in touch” with one’s own body. This is because we make sense of

the world in-and-through our bodies, via the desiderative feelings of

affective framing. Ordinarily there is a “felt union” between body and

mind, but this appears to be disrupted in cases of schizophrenia.

Since schizophrenia involves disruptions to bodily attunement and

a diminished sense of ownership, treatment should involve

interventions that seek to transform an individual’s overall bodily

and neurobiological dynamics. We need to develop intensive,

comprehensive, and holistic behavioral interventions, ones which

29

Page 30: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

minister to the whole living body, and not just the brain. Indeed,

there is evidence that antipsychotic medications are not sufficiently

effective in managing the debilitating symptoms of schizophrenia, such

as delusions, hallucinations, and thought insertion. Many patients on

medication continue to experience psychotic symptoms throughout their

lifetimes, and it is generally acknowledged that pharmacological

treatment alone is insufficient (Pilling et al. 2002), and also that

such medications may cause cerebral abnormalities (Moncrieff and Leo

2010) as well as negative side effects. This has lead to the

development of a cognitive-behavioural therapy (CBT) approach to the

treatment of schizophrenia. By reflecting on and then modifying their

patterns of thinking, subjects can learn to avoid self-destructive

actions and beliefs. Some studies have found that CBT can be an

effective treatment for schizophrenia even in cases where medication

is not used, and that it reduces the frequency of hallucinations and

delusional beliefs (Chadwick, Birchwood, and Trower 1996).

While I do not dispute the claim that cognitive behavioural

therapy is a highly effective, top-down mode of treatment, I propose

that bottom-up treatment methods also deserve further attention. By

‘bottom-up’ interventions, I mean those that center on bodily

engagement that shifts bodily dynamics and feelings so as to allow for

changes in cognition and patterns of thought. For example, there is

30

Page 31: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

some evidence that yoga can be an effective treatment for

schizophrenia. Visceglia and Lewis (2011) found that adults with

schizophrenia who participated in an 8-week therapeutic yoga program

showed significant improvements in psychopathology and quality of life

compared with controls. One participant stated that “yoga makes me

feel like my whole body is functioning as it should,” and many of the

subjects reported that it made them feel calmer and more able to

function (Visceglia and Lewis 2011, 603). Likewise, the research of

Rohricht et al. (2009) showed that body oriented psychological

interventions had a positive impact on subjects suffering from chronic

schizophrenia. This intervention included dance movement

psychotherapy, sensory awareness exercises, and tactile self-

exploration. At the beginning of therapy, patients reported being

unable to connect with themselves, and having a diminished or

distorted sense of their bodies. Often their movements were

disorganized and uncoordinated, without any energy. After therapy,

there was a clearer differentiation of movement, feelings of

lifelessness diminished, and their ability to verbally express their

bodily sensations improved. In addition, there were significant

improvements in “ego-pathology” (disturbed self-experience), which

Rohricht et al. characterize as a basic symptom of schizophrenia. In

particular, subjects showed improvement with respect to ‘ego-activity’

31

Page 32: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

(the ability to function as a self-directing, self-governing unity

that intentionally directs one’s thinking and action), ‘ego-

consistency’ (the coherence and organization of self-experience), and

‘ego-demarcation’ (the ability to differentiate between ego and non-

ego spheres). Such evidence suggests that through body oriented

psychotherapy, subjects were able to engage directly with their bodies

and also to begin to articulate some of their abnormal bodily

sensations. As a result, their self-experience became more unified and

coherent and they were better able to distinguish between self and

non-self.

I hypothesize that yoga, dance, and other body oriented methods

of psychotherapy provide a way for subjects to re-inhabit their bodies

and restore bodily attunement, so that their sense of ownership begins

to be reinstated. One might say that such modes of therapy serve to

cultivate an “ethos of expertise.” Through movement, bodily self-

exploration, and enhanced sensory self-awareness, subjects are able to

forge more of a felt connection with their bodies. Neurobiologically,

this corresponds to the strengthening of existing affective framing

patterns, or, in some cases, the formation of new ones. If my proposed

account of affective framing is roughly correct, then this increased

bodily attunement will, in turn, contribute to subject’s ability to

appreciate the significance of features in their surroundings. In

32

Page 33: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

fact, the research of Rohricht et al. bears this out: by the end of

body oriented therapy, schizophrenic subjects became more positively

engaged with objects in the room (e.g. balls), they were more

interested in participating in group exercises, and they exhibited an

improved ability to identify and express basic emotions. Such evidence

suggests that these bodily-based treatment interventions have great

potential to restore bodily attunement and strengthen subjects’ sense

of ownership, and thus merit greater attention.

Conclusion

Stephens and Graham maintain that the sense of ownership is

preserved in cases of thought insertion, but there is a defect in the

sense of agency. However, this account makes it difficult to

distinguish between the inserted thoughts of schizophrenia and the

unbidden thoughts of OCD. In addition, some of the other

characteristic symptoms of schizophrenia indicate that subjects’ sense

of ownership indeed is diminished. My proposed account of affective

framing aims to make sense of how bodily alienation and unworlding are

linked to the phenomenon of thought insertion. All of these symptoms

center on a diminished sense of ownership and result in large part

from an inability to coordinate and integrate relevant contextual

information, which ordinarily is facilitated by the desiderative

33

Page 34: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

bodily feelings of affective framing. When background bodily feelings

of caring are diminished, subjects find it difficult to make sense of

their own bodily sensations and surroundings. If this is true, then

we should focus on treatment interventions which seek to reinstate

subjects’ sense of ownership and restore bodily attunement. More

research should be done to determine the efficacy of body-based

treatments for schizophrenia.

References

Bortlotti, L. & Broome, M. (2009). A role for ownership and authorship

in the analysis of thought insertion. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences,

8, 205-224.

Brown, T.E. (2005). Attention deficit disorder: The unfocused mind in children and

adults. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

Chadwick, P., Birchwood, M., & Trower, P. (1996). Cognitive therapy for

delusions, voices, and paranoia.Chichester: Wiley.

Colombetti, G. & Thompson, E. (2008). The feeling body: Towards an

enactive approach to emotion. In W.F. Overton, U. Muller, and J.L.

Newman JL (Eds.), Developmental perspectives on embodiment and consciousness (pp.

45-68). New York: Lawrence Erlbaum.

34

Page 35: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

Fuchs, T. (2005). Corporealized and disembodied minds: A

phenomenological view of the body in melancholia and schizophrenia.

Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology, 12 (2),95-107.

Gerrans, P. (2001). Authorship and ownership of thoughts. Philosophy,

Psychiatry, Psychology, 8 (2/3),231-237.

Krueger, J. (2009). Knowing through the body. Journal of Chinese Philosophy, 36

(1), 31-52.

Maher, B. (2003). Schizophrenia, aberrant utterance, and delusions of

control: The disconnection of speech and thought, and the connection

of experience and belief. Mind and Language, 18 (1), 1-22.

Martin, J. & Pacherie, E. (2013).Out of nowhere: Thought insertion,

ownership, and context-integration. Consciousness and Cognition, 22, 111-

222.

Minkowski, E. & Targowla, R. (2001).A contribution to the study of

autism: The interrogative attitude. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology, 8

(4), 271-278.

Montcrieff, J. & Leo, J. (2010). A systematic review of the effects of

antipsychotic drugs on brain volume. Psychological Medicine, 40, 1409-1422.

35

Page 36: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

Pilling, S. et al. (2002). Psychological treatments in schizophrenia:

Meta-analysis of family intervention and cognitive behaviour therapy.

Psychological Medicine, 32, 763-782.

Ratcliffe, M. (2005). William James on emotion and intentionality.

International Journal

of Philosophical Studies, 13 (2), 179-202.

Rohricht, F. et al. (2009). Ego-pathology, body experience, and body

psychotherapy in chronic schizophrenia. Psychology and Psychotherapy: Theory,

Research, and Practice, 82, 19-30.

Sass, L. (2004). Affectivity in schizophrenia: A phenomenological

view. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 11 (10-11), 127-147.

Sass, L. (2007). Contradictions of emotion in schizophrenia. Cognition

and Emotion, 21 (2), 351-390.

Sass, L. & Parnas, J. (2001). Phenomenology of self-disturbances in

schizophrenia: Some research findings and directions. Philosophy, Psychiatry,

and Psychology, 8 (4), 347-356.

Stephens, G.L. & Graham, G. (2000). When self-consciousness breaks: Alien voices

and inserted thoughts. Cambridge: MIT Press.

36

Page 37: Thought Insertion as a Disownership Symptom

Stanghellini, G. (2004). Disembodied spirits and deanimated bodies: The

psychopathology of common sense. New York: Oxford University Press.

Stanghellini, G. & Ballerini, M.(2004). Autism: Disembodied existence.

Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology, 11 (3),259-268.

Stanghellini, G. (2011). Phenomenological psychopathology, profundity,

and schizophrenia. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology, 18 (2), 163-166.

Visceglia, E. and Lewis, S. “Yoga Therapy as an Adjunctive Treatment

for Schizophrenia: A Randomized, Controlled Pilot Study,” The Journal of

Alternative and Complementary Medicine, 17 (7): 601-607.

37