Top Banner
1 The Concept of Law in ‘Law and Finance’: Towards a Comprehensive Framework Gerhard Schnyder [email protected] Paper to be presented at the 28 th Annual SASE Meeting University of California, Berkeley June 2426, 2016 Very first draft – work in progress ABSTRACT Since its inception in the late 1990s, the Law and Finance School (LFS) has become a very influential line of research in the area of corporate governance. La Porta and coauthors have published a series of papers that argued for the crucial importance of law in determining countries’ corporate governance systems. As the name of the school suggests, law is considered a key variable in explaining both corporate governance outcomes and overall economic performance. This paper reviews the LFS literature and shows that in spite of the centrality of law, it is based on a surprisingly ‘thin’ theory of law and does not have much to say about how law is conceptually expected to impact firmlevel practices. In other words, while a lot of effort has gone into empirically showing that law matters for corporate finance and governance outcomes, much less effort has been spent on the question how we would expect law to matter. The paper shows that this is a major neglect that not only limits the theoretical contribution of the LFS, but also undermines empirical strategies used to test the link between law and economic outcomes. The present paper aims to fill this gap by developing a more comprehensive and theoretically grounded framework that explains not just whether, but how law can be expected to impact economic outcomes via corporate practices. The paper discusses implications for empirical research by developing empirically testable propositions regarding the link between law and finance.
42

TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an!...

Aug 04, 2020

Download

Documents

dariahiddleston
Welcome message from author
This document is posted to help you gain knowledge. Please leave a comment to let me know what you think about it! Share it to your friends and learn new things together.
Transcript
Page 1: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  1  

The  Concept  of  Law  in  ‘Law  and  Finance’:  Towards  a  Comprehensive  Framework  

 Gerhard  Schnyder  

[email protected]      

Paper  to  be  presented  at  the    

28th  Annual  SASE  Meeting  University  of  California,  Berkeley  

June  24-­‐26,  2016    

Very  first  draft  –  work  in  progress  

 

ABSTRACT  

Since  its  inception  in  the  late  1990s,  the  Law  and  Finance  School  (LFS)  has  become  a  very   influential   line  of   research   in   the  area  of  corporate  governance.  La  Porta  and  co-­‐authors  have  published  a  series  of  papers  that  argued  for  the  crucial  importance  of  law  in  determining  countries’  corporate  governance  systems.  As  the  name  of  the  school   suggests,   law   is   considered   a   key   variable   in   explaining   both   corporate  governance   outcomes   and   overall   economic   performance.   This   paper   reviews   the  LFS   literature   and   shows   that   in   spite   of   the   centrality   of   law,   it   is   based   on   a  surprisingly   ‘thin’   theory  of   law  and  does  not  have  much   to   say  about  how   law   is  conceptually  expected  to  impact  firm-­‐level  practices.  In  other  words,  while  a  lot  of  effort  has  gone  into  empirically  showing  that  law  matters  for  corporate  finance  and  governance   outcomes,   much   less   effort   has   been   spent   on   the   question   how  we  would  expect   law  to  matter.  The  paper  shows  that   this   is  a  major  neglect   that  not  only   limits   the   theoretical   contribution   of   the   LFS,   but   also   undermines   empirical  strategies  used   to   test   the   link  between   law  and  economic  outcomes.  The  present  paper   aims   to   fill   this   gap  by  developing   a  more   comprehensive   and   theoretically  grounded  framework  that  explains  not  just  whether,  but  how  law  can  be  expected  to  impact   economic   outcomes   via   corporate   practices.   The   paper   discusses  implications  for  empirical  research  by  developing  empirically  testable  propositions  regarding  the  link  between  law  and  finance.  

   

Page 2: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  2  

1.  Introduction  

Scholars   have   argued   for   some   time   that   certain   wide-­‐spread   theories   in  management  scholarship,  such  as  agency  theory,  adopt  a   ‘thin  view  of  institutional  environment[s]’   (Aguilera   &   Jackson   2003:   449).   This   tendency   can   even   be  observed   in   fields   of   studies   that   attribute   much   importance   to   the   explanatory  power   of   institutional   factors   such   as   law.   Indeed,   this   paper   shows   that   the   Law  and   Finance   School   (hereinafter   LFS)   has   astonishingly   little   to   say   about   law  considering   that   law   figures   so   prominently   as   its   key   explanatory   variable.1   The  paper  argues  that  this  is  a  serious  neglect,  which  not  only  limits  the  conceptual  and  theoretical   contribution   of   the   LFS,   but   also   undermines   empirical   studies   that  attempt  to  test  hypotheses  derived  from  the  LFS.  More  precisely,  the  LFS  is  crucially  based  on  the  notion  that  ‘law  matters’  for  economic  outcomes  (Coffee  2000,  Armour  et   al.   2009a).   Yet,   the   extant   literature   remains   surprisingly   silent   about   the  conceptualisation  of  how  exactly  ‘law  matters’,  i.e.  how  law  affects  firm-­‐  and  macro-­‐level  economic  outcomes.  

The  LFS  has  come  under  a  great  deal  of  criticisms  on  various  grounds.  For  one  their  measure   of   the   quality   of   company   law   have   been   in   terms   of   the   consistency   of  coding  (Spamann  2006,  Braendle  2005)  and  the  choice  of  variables  to  be   included  (Armour  et  al.  2009a).  Moreover,  various  aspects  of  the  historical  analysis  as  well  as  the   characterisation  of   common-­‐  versus   civil   law   that   the  LFS  provides  have  been  criticised  and   rejected   (e.g.  Dam  2006;   Siems  2007,  2005).  The  proponents  of   the  LFS  have  reacted,  on  the  one  hand,  by  developing  new  empirical  measures  (Djankov  et   al.   2008)   and,   on   the   other,   by   retreating   somewhat   from   the   originally   strong  claims   about   the   causal   importance   of   substantive   legal   rules   in   explaining  corporate  governance  outcomes.  Indeed,  the  Anti-­‐Director  Rights  Index  (ADRI)  used  six  items  as  substantive  criteria  to  proxy  for  the  level  of  legal  minority  shareholder  protection   (MSP).   Increasingly,   however   the   focus   shifted   towards   more   basic  differences   in   the   functioning   of   legal   systems   in   different   countries.   Glaeser   &  Shleifer  (2002),  for  instance,  see  the  main  difference  between  English  common  law  and  French  civil  law  in  the  degree  of  centralisation  of  the  legal  system  and  the  level  of  control  of  the  ‘sovereign’  over  judges:  “the  difference  [between  common  and  civil  law]   can   be   plausibly   trace   to   the   fundamental   choice   of   state-­‐controlled   versus  independent   justice”   (p.1196).   Many   other   studies   in   the   area   reveal   an   even  broader   understanding   of   the   differences,   whereby   the   different   types   of   legal  systems   are   mainly   a   proxy   for   different   degrees   of   state   intervention   in   the  economy   or   for   different   ‘regulatory   styles’   (La   Porta,   Lopez-­‐de-­‐Silanes,   Shleifer  (LLS)  2008).  This  has  also  raised  questions  whether  it  is  indeed  law  that  matters  for  economic   outcomes,   or   whether   other,   unmeasured   factors   –   such   as   historical  contingency  and  politics  –  may  have  more  explanatory  power  (Coffee  2000,  Cheffins  

                                                                                                                         1  For  a  similar  point  about  ‘property  rights’  in  economics  more  broadly  see  Deakin  et  al.  2015;  Lueck  &  Miceli  2007.  

Page 3: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  3  

2001,  Roe  &  Siegel  2009).  These  are  well-­‐known  criticisms  and  replies,  which  have  been   extensively   discussed   in   the   literature   (see   for   instance   Deakin   et   al.   2011;  Armour  et  al.  2009a).  

The  present  paper  starts  from  there,  arguing  not  so  much  that  the  LFS  overplays  its  hand  when   stating   that   ‘law  matters’,   but   that   it   does   not   provide   the   theoretical  tool  to  understand  why  and  how  we  would  expect  it  to  matter.  In  other  words,  the  LFS’s   problem   is   not   that   it   takes   law   too   seriously,   but   that   it   does   not   take   it  seriously  enough.  The  solution  to  the  criticisms  of  the  LFS  should  not  be  to  abandon  the   investigation   of   how   substantive   differences   in   laws   affect   differences   in  corporate   governance   outcomes,   but   to   develop   and   then   test   a   more   solid  theoretically-­‐based  framework  of  how  we  would  expect  law  to  matter.  

An   extensive   review   of   the   articles   that   can   be   considered   the   core   of   the   LFS   to  date,  confirms  previous  scholarship’s  observation  that  the  LFS  narrowly  focuses  on  the  ‘protective  function  of  law’  (Milhaupt  &  Pistor  2008),  but  it  also  reveals  that  it  is  based  –  often   implicitly  –  on  a  narrow  conception  of  how   law   impacts   (economic)  actors.   This   view   comes   closest   to  what   is   known   in   legal   theory   as   ‘the   coercive  view  of   law’  where   the  main  mechanism  of   how   law  matters   is   through   threat   of  punishment.  The  literature  review  also  shows  that  the  LFS  draws  on  various  strands  of   legal   scholarship,   but   that   the   ‘concept  of   law’   that   is   emerging   is  not   coherent  and   indeed  may   be   contradictory   across   different   studies.   This   paper   argues   that  this   is  a  non-­‐negligible  omission,  which  may  be  part  of   the  explanation  why   it  has  been  proven  surprisingly  difficult  to  clearly  establish  a  link  between  legal  MSP  and  economic   outcomes   (see   Coffee   2001,   Cuomo   et   al.   2012).   If  we   are   interested   in  testing   the   question   ‘does   law   matter?’   it   would   seem   important   to   first   ask   the  question  ‘how  do  we  expect  law  to  matter?’  The  latter  question  hinges,  in  turn,  on  a  clear   conceptualisation   of   the   link   between   laws   and   firm-­‐level   practices.   Legal  theory  has  been  used  to  great  effect  to  advance  management  theories,  where  such  theories  are  oftentimes  needed,  but  rarely  explicitly  marshalled  (see  Oosterhout  et  al.   2006   for   the   use   of   Fuller’s   (1964)   concept   of   internal   morality   to   advance  business  ethics,  Lan  &  Heracleous  2010  for  the  use  of  legal  theory  to  advance  agency  theory).   In   a   similar   vein,   this   paper   attempts   to   remedy   the   considerable  shortcoming   in   the   LFS   by   explicitly   developing   empirically   testable   hypotheses  based  on  legal  theory.  

The  paper  proceeds  as  follows:  Part  two  reviews  what  the  LFS  literature  has  to  say  about   how   law   impacts   firm-­‐level   outcomes.   Part   three   presents   current   debates  about  the  coercive  view  of  law  and  presents  an  alternative  conceptualisation  of  the  link  between  law  and  firm-­‐level  outcomes,  based  on  legal  theory.  Part  four  develops  testable  propositions  based  on  the  preceding  discussion.  A  last  part  concludes.  

 

2.  Literature  Review:  The  ‘Thin’  Concept  of  Law  in  Law  &  Finance  

Page 4: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  4  

The   Law   and   Finance   School   is   a   term   that   has   come   to   be   used   to   designate   an  approach  related  to  a  series  of  influential  papers  co-­‐authored  by  La  Porta,  Lopez-­‐de-­‐Silanes,   Shleifer   and   Vishny   (often   shortened   to   LLSV)   and   various   co-­‐authors  starting   in   1997.2   It   is   broadly   speaking   cognate   to   New   Institutional   Economics  (NIE)  and  the  Law  and  Economics  (L&E)  school  with  both  of  which  it  has  affinities,  but   also   certain   differences.   The   LFS   started   of   by   focussing   on   investigating   in  comparative  fashion  the  impact  of  legal  factors  on  different  characteristics  of  firm-­‐level   corporate   finance   and   corporate   governance.  As   this   section  will   show,   over  the  years,  however,  it  has  increasingly  broadened  its  scope,  going  beyond  company  law   –   and   indeed   law   per   se   –   as   key   independent   variable,   investigating   instead  broad   institutional-­‐regulatory   factors’   impact   on   various   economic   and   societal  outcomes.  Thus,  authors  associated  with  the  LFS  have  investigated  as  independent  variables  employment  protection,  bankruptcy  law,  creditor  protection,  and  broader  factors   such   as   constitutional   provisions.   The   dependent   variables   were   initially  ownership  structures   (dispersion  or   concentration)  and  market   capitalisation,  but  then  came  to  include  a  variety  of  outcomes  including  firm-­‐level  growth  and  military  conscription  (see  for  a  summary  of  the  first  ten  years  of  the  research  La  Porta  et  al.  2008).  

This   section  provides  a   systematic   review  of   the  work   that   can  be   considered   the  core  of  the  LFS.  To  this  effect,  a  list  of  all  articles  published  by  the  original  authors  LLSV   since   1997   was   compiled   based   on   their   personal   web   pages   and   online  Curricula   Vitae.   Articles   that   did   not   focus   on   legal   or   institutional   factors   as   key  explanatory  or  dependent  variables,  but  only  included  them  as  controls  and  articles  that   did   not   refer   to   the   LFS   main   claims   at   all   were   excluded   (e.g.   Chong   et   al.  2014).   Similarly,   papers   that   did   have   legal   factors   as   their   key   variables,   but  focused   on   an   area   other   than   corporate   governance   and   finance   were   excluded  (Djankov   et   al.   2010   on   disclosure   regulations   for   politicians).   To   these   papers,   a  handful   of   articles   authored   not   by   the   original   group   (LLSV),   but   by   later   co-­‐authors   and  articles   in   the  LFS   tradition  often   cited  by  LLSV  were  added.  Overall,  this   left   us   with   42   articles   published   between   1997   and   2015,   which   can   be  considered  to  constitute  the  core  of  the  LFS.  

This  section  attemtps  to  distill   from  this  wealth  of  publications  the  concept  of   law  that   underlies   the   LFS.   The   question   the   paper   tries   to   answer   is:   what   are   the  theortical   assumptions   regarding   the   impact   of   law   on   economic   outcomes   that  inform  the  LFS  research  programme?  The  section  proceeds  by   first  explaining   the  two  core  claims  of  the  LFS,  which  are  the  ‘quality  of  law  claim’  (QLC)  and  the  ‘legal  origins  thesis’  or  theory  (LOT).  The  initial  ambition  of  the  LFS  was  to  explain  cross-­‐

                                                                                                                         2  Initially,  this  approach  designated  itself  as  the  ‘legal  approach  to  corporate  governance’  (e.g.  LLSV  2000:  4),  but  it  soon  branched  out  to  investigate  phenomena  that  go  well  beyond  corporate  governance  and  finance,  which  makes  the  term  LFS  more  appropriate.  

Page 5: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  5  

country  differences  in  ownership  structures  and  the  availability  of  external  finance  (LLSV  1997,  1998,  1999a).  The  key  argument  and  main  novelty  of  LLSV’s  work  was  to   argue   that   it   was   a   country’s   laws   that   determined   different   corporate  governance   structures   across   countries   (size   of   stock   markets,   type   of   corporate  finance,   ownership   structure).   More   precisely,   the   LFS   focused   on   certain  substantive   characteristics   of   a   country’s   company   law,   which   taken   together,  provided   a   measure   of   its   ‘quality’,   where   quality   meant   high   levels   of   minority  shareholder   protection   (LLSV   1997,   see   Armour   et   al.   2009a).   However,   the   LFS  quickly   evolved   from  explaining   economic  outcomes  based  on   the  QLC,   to   a  more  fundamental   argument   that   has   been   termed   the   Legal   Origin   Thesis   (LOT)   (see  Armour  et  al.  2009a).  The  LOT  links  the  characteristics  of  law  to  more  fundamental  features   of   a   country’s   legal   system   and   distinguishes   in   particular   common   law  from  civil  law  countries.  

This  section  discusses  both   these  central  claims   in   turn.   It   then   turns   to  analysing  what   concept   of   law   the   LFS   is   based   on   by   asking   three   questions   in   order   of  increasing  specificity:  Firstly,  and  very  broadly,  what  postulates  does  the  LFS  make  about   the   importance   of   law   in   the   economy?   Secondly,   how   does   the   LFS   define  ‘good’   law?   Thirdly,   what   does   the   LFS   have   to   say   about   the   way   in   which   law  impacts  economic  actors?  

2.1  The  Quality  of  Law  Claim:  Property  Rights  and  the  Protective  Function  of  Law  

The   quality   of   law   claim   hints   already   at   an   important   element   of   the   LFS’s  conception  of   law,   i.e.   the   importance  attributed   to   the  protective   function  of   law.  Scholars  have  criticised  the  LFS  for  narrowly  focussing  on  just  one  function  of  law,  namely  the  protective  function  (Milhaupt  &  Pistor  2008).  Indeed,  the  quality  of  law  is  largely  defined  as  the  extent  to  which  company  law  protects  investors’  rights  and  in   particular   their   property   rights.   In   their   seminal   article   ‘Law   &   Finance’   from  1998,  LLSV  state  that    

“Law   and   the   quality   of   its   enforcement   are   potentially   important  determinants   of   what   rights   security   holders   have   and   how   well   these  rights   are   protected.   Since   the   protection   investors   receive   determines  their  readiness  to  finance  firms,  corporate  finance  may  critically  turn  on  these  legal  rules  and  their  enforcement”  (p.1114)  

Similarly,  LLSV  (2000:4)  state  that:  

“The   legal   approach   to   corporate   governance   holds   that   the   key  mechanism   is   the   protection   of   outside   investors   (whether   shareholders  or   creditors)   through   the   legal   system,   meaning   both   laws   and   their  enforcement.   […]  To  a   large  extent,  potential  shareholders  and  creditors  finance  firms  because  their  rights  are  protected  by  the  law.  These  outside  investors  are  more  vulnerable   to  expropriation,  and  more  dependent  on  

Page 6: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  6  

the   law,   than   either   the   employees   or   the   suppliers,   who   remain  continually   useful   to   the   firm   and   are   thus   at   a   lesser   risk   of   being  mistreated.”  

Two   points   are   important   here:   firstly,   it   is   indeed   the   function   of   protecting  property  rights  which  is  at  the  heart  of  the  LFS  from  the  beginnin;  Secondly,  the  first  quote  hints  at  the  fact  that  shareholder  rights  are  not  just  protected  by  law,  but  may  actually  be  created  by  law  in  the  first  place  («  what  rights  security  holders  have  »).  This  hints  at  the  constitutive  function  of  law  (Deakin  et  al.  2015)  whereby  law  does  not   just   protect   certain   pre-­‐existing   or   objective   rights   or   states   of   fact,   but   it  actually  is  the  reason  why  these  rights  exist  in  the  first  place.  This  quote  from  1998  is,   however,   one   of   the   rare   places   in   the   LFS   where   the   constitutive   function   is  acknowledge  and  it  is  not  done  explicitly.  Most  of  the  LFS  literature  seems  rather  to  suggest  that  shareholder  rights  pre-­‐exist  the  law  and  are  or  are  not  protected  by  a  given  country’s  legal  rules.  This  latter  view  may  derive  from  the  “contractual  view  of  the   firm”   (Jensen  &  Meckling  1976,  Grossman&Hart  1988,  Hart  1995)  which  LLSV  cite  as  the  basis  for  the  LFS.  Thus,  the  contractual  view  “[…]  sees  the  protection  of  the   property   rights   of   the   financiers   as   essential   to   assure   the   flow   of   capital   to  firms”  (La  Porta  et  al.  2008:  Footnote  1).  However,  it  also  explains  why  shareholder  rights  may  be  conceived  as  pre-­‐legal  in  nature:  they  may  be  contractual  rights  that  simply   are   protected   under   general   contract   or   tort   law.   To   be   sure,   the   LFS  distinguishes  itself  from  other  streams  in  the  NIE  tradition  and  from  L&E  precisely  by   going   beyond   the   purely   contractualist   view   (e.g.   Stigler   1964;   Easterbrook   &  Fischel   1991;   cf.   Glaeser  &   Shleifer   2002:   1223).   This   departure   from   the  Coasian  approach,   however,   is   mainly   explained   by   a   stronger   focus   on   problems   with  judicial   enforcement   of   complex   contracts,   which   may   make   (public)   legal   rules  more  efficient  than  purely  private  contracting  (Glaeser  et  al.  2001).  The  contractual  view  still  remains,  however,  the  basis  for  the  LFS  (see  LLS  2008),  which  may  explain  why  it  tends  to  neglect  the  constitutive  function  of  law  regarding  shareholder  rights.  

Consequently,   the   protective   function   of   law   is   at   the   centre   of   the   quality   of   law  claim.  The  law’s  role  is  to  protect  economic  actors’  –  here  minority  shareholders’  –  property-­‐   and   other   rights   (similarly   LLSV   1997:   1149;   Mahoney   2001:   523).  Various  LFS  studies  refer  to  the  long  pedigree  of  this  idea,  citing  Smith  (1776)  and  Montesquieu  (1748)  –  and  at  times  Locke  1690  –  as  the  main  sources  for  the  insight  that   ‘good  economic  institutions  must  secure  property  rights’  (Djankov  et  al.  2003:  596  [new  comparative  economics];  also  Djankov  et  al.  2003[courts]:  453;  Glaeser  et  al.  2003:  200;  2004:  272;  La  Porta  et  al.  2004).  

The  protection  of  property  rights  explains  then  the  link  with  financial  development.  If   institutions   –  which   are   equated  here  with   law   (see  discussion  below)   –   enable  “people  to  keep  the  returns  on  their  investment,  make  contracts,  and  resolve  disputes”  (Djankov  et   al.   2003:  596),   then  a   sentiment  of   security  will   lead  people   to   invest  their  capital,  rather  than  burying  it  in  their  garden,  promoting  thus  the  development  

Page 7: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  7  

of   financial  markets   (ibid.   citing   Smith   1776).   In  modern   terms,   if   laws   guarantee  property   rights   and   hence   return   on   investments,   the   incentive   structure   will   be  such   that  sources   for  external   finance  are  readily  available   to  companies,  allowing  firms  to  grow  faster  (Levine  1999).    

Legal   scholars   have   criticised   this   narrow   conception   of   law.  Milhaupt   and   Pistor  (2008:   17)  write:   ‘According   to   the   prevailing   view,   law   fosters   economic   activity  (exclusively)  by  protecting  property  rights.’  And  to  continue:  ‘This  view  amounts  to  ‘a   formalistic   and   deterministic   view   of   the   relation   between   law   and   markets’  (Milhaupt  &  Pistor  2008:  7-­‐8;  also  Armour  et  al.  2009a).    

To  be  fair,  though,  some  of  the  LFS  articles  do  contain  a  somewhat  more  variegated  view   of   the   functions   of   law   than   the   usual   narrow   focus   on   the   protection   of  property  rights.  Thus,  Djankov  et  al.  (2003:  596)  state  that:    

“Since  the  days  of   the  Enlightenment,  economists  have  agreed  that  good  economic   institutions   must   secure   property   rights,   enabling   people   to  keep   the   returns   on   their   investment,   make   contracts,   and   resolve  disputes.”  

Here,   two   additional   functions   of   law   are   mentioned:   Enabling   people   to   make  contracts   hints   at   the   enabling-­‐   or   coordinative   function   of   law   rather   than   its  protective   one.   Indeed,   the   type  of  enabling   legal   rules  defining   the   criteria   that   a  valid  contract  has  to  fulfil  are  a  fundamentally  different  type  of  legal  rules  compared  to   rules   that  constrain   actors  by  proscribing  or  prescribing   certain  behaviours   (cf.  Hart  1961  discussed  below).  Solving  disputes  is  the  third  function  that  Djankov  et  al.  (2003)  refer  to.  This  is  a  function  of  law  that  mainly  relates  to  the  laws  enforcement  through   litigation   or   other   dispute   settlement   procedures.   Yet,   if   some   papers  suggest  a  broader  conceptualisation  of  why  law  is  expected  to  matter,  Milhaupt  and  PIstor   (2008)   are   right   in   saying   that   this   is   done  only   in  passing   and   there   is   no  discussion  of  the  theoretical  or  empirical   implications  of  this  multi-­‐functionality  of  law  on  the  causal  link  between  law  and  economic  outcomes.  

The   literature   distinguishes   different   very   broad   functions   of   law.   Very   broadly  speaking,   the   Thomist   view   holds   that   the   primary   function   of   law   is   to   guide  conduct,  which   is   also   the  view  Fuller   (1969)  adopts.  Others   include  doing   justice  (Moore   1992)   and   licensing   coercion   (Dworkin   1988).   In   addition,   Finnis   (1980)  sees   law’s  main  purpose   to  be   to  coordinate  activity.  This  coordinative   function  of  law  is  important  but  very  largely  neglected  in  the  LFS  literature  (MIlhaupt  &  Pistor  2008).  This   function  does  not  consist   in   law  primarily  determining  and  protecting  actors’  rights,  but  provides  them  with  instruments  that  help  them  coordinate  their  economic   activities   with   other   actors   while   negotiating   the   precise   allocation   of  property  rights  within  the  boundaries  of  the  law  (Milhaupt  &  Pistor  2008:  7).  Legal  instruments   such   as   contracts   come   closer   to   the   second   function   than   to   the  protective  function.  

Page 8: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  8  

In   the  earlier  papers  of   the  LFS’s   formalism  was  expressed   in   the  definition  of   the  quality  of   company   law  via  a   simple   indicator   capturing   the  extent  of   shareholder  protection.   This   Anti-­‐Director   Rights   Index   (ADRI)   was   simply   the   sum   of   six  dummy   variables,   which   measured   different   shareholder   rights   that   were   –  according   to   LLSV’s   assessment   –   crucial   for   shareholders’   to  make   sure   they   get  ‘their  money   back’   (cf.   Shleifer   &   Vishny   1997).   Here,   the   LFS   uses   a   substantive  definition  of  the  quality  of  law  directly  associated  with  six  specific  rights.  However,  it  very  soon  changed  somewhat  in  focus.  Rather  than  measuring  the  ‘quality  of  law’  per  se,  the  focus  shifted  to  a  more  fundamental  –  and  in  some  respects  contradictory  claim   –   namely   that   different   legal   origins   of   countries’   company   laws   was   the  underlying   factor   explaining   the   differences   in   the   nature   of   law   and   hence   in  economic  outcomes.  The  next  section  turns  to  this  second  key  claim.  

2.2  The  Legal  Origin  Theory:  A  Broad  Conception  of  Law…or  Something  Else?  

The  legal  origin  theory  (LOT)  associates  economic  outcomes  not  so  much  with  the  substantive   content   of   laws,   but   with   the   more   fundamental   nature   of   the  ‘regulatory  style’  in  a  given  country  (La  Porta  et  al.  2008).  In  this  respect  it  stands  in  contradiction  with  the  QLC.  The  latter  suggests  that  countries  can  choose  their  laws  in  an  instrumental  fashion  to  achieve  certain  desired  outcomes.  Indeed,  the  need  for  (radical)  legal  reform  is  one  of  the  key  themes  of  the  LFS  and  is  explicitly  advocated  in   various  papers   (see   in  particular  Hay  &  Shleifer  1998,   LLSV  1999a:  512;  2000;  Johnson   et   al.   2000;   LLSV   2006)   and   has   indeed   been   applied   in   the   investor  protection   section   of   the   World   Bank’s   ‘Doing   Business’   programme   (Ohnesorge  2009).  The  LOT,  on  the  other  hand,  suggests  very  strong  path  dependence  at  work,  which  makes  it  highly  unlikely  that  a  country  can  move  away  from  its  original  legal  system  whose  fundamental  characteristics  may  have  been  established  as  far  back  as  the  12th  century  (Glaeser  &  Shleifer  2002;  cf.  Armour  et  al.  2009a).3  

Initially,  the  LOT  was  born  out  of  a  methodological  concern:  Since  there  is  a  difficult  question  about  the  endogeneity  of  law  and  the  economic  context  (see  Glaeser  et  al.  2004),   LLSV   used   ‘legal   origin’   as   an   instrument   variable   to   control   for   this  endogeneity   (LLSV   1999a:   505).   Legal   origin   was   first   simply   defined   as   the  historical   origin   of   a   country’s   legal   system   in   one   of   four   ‘mother   systems’:  Common   Law,   French-­‐,   German-­‐,   and   Scandinavian   Civil   Law   (LLSV   1998:   1126).  Despite   its  methodological   beginnings,   legal   origin   soon   acquired   a   life   of   its   own  and   became   the   key   explanatory   variables   in   the   LFS   framework.   Subsequently,  various   economic   and   societal   outcomes  were   explained   referring   to   legal   origins  rather  than  substantive  features  of  company  law  as  the  main  explanatory  variable.  

                                                                                                                         3  The  main  mechanism  via  which  this  path  dependency  can  be  overcome  however,  is  through  ‘legal  transplants’,  i.e.  the  import  of  legal  rules  from  other  countries  either  voluntarily,  through  conquest  or  colonialisation  (e.g.  Djankov  et  al.  2003).  The  concept  of  transplants  and  problematic  ‘transplant  effects’  (Berkowitz  et  al.  2003)  associated  with  it  raise  a  whole  host  of  new  questions  (see  for  a  discussion  Larsson-­‐Olaisson  2014).  

Page 9: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  9  

Thus,   LLS,   in   a   review   article   of   their   own   research,   list   among   the   outcome  variables   that   can   be   explained   by   legal   origins:   government   ownership   of   banks,  the  burden  of  entry  regulations,  regulation  of  labour  markets,  incidence  of  military  conscription,  and  government  ownership  of  the  media  (La  Porta  et  al.  2008:  286).  

However,  the  idea  of  legal  origins  and  the  use  of  the  concept  in  empirical  research  has  been  extensively  criticised.  Siems  (2007)  has  shown  that  it  is  far  from  obvious  how   to   classify   different   countries   into   one   of   the   four   ‘mother   systems’.   Also,  critiques   have   observed   that   the   LFS   is   not   clear   on   the   precise  mechanism   that  explains   why   legal   origins   should   matter,   or   in   other   words   why   common   law  should  be  expected  to  be  superior  to  civil   law  in  terms  of  economic  outcomes  (see  Armour  et  al.  2009a).    The  question  arises  whether   legal  origin  develops   its  effect  indeed   through   the   quality   of   company   law   to   cause   the   observed   outcomes,   or  whether  legal  origin  is  a  proxy  for  something  else,  e.g.  culture  (Armour  et  al.  2009b;  see  Mahoney  2001  for  an  acknowledgement  of  this  point).    

The   most   explicit   acknowledgement   perhaps   that   LOT   is   about   something   quite  different   than   law  is  a  paper  by  Mahoney  (2001).  The  author  uses  Hayek  to  argue  that  it  is  not  the  substantive  nature  of  laws  in  common  law  countries  that  explains  their  superior  economic  outcomes,  but  the  different  philosophies  of  government  and  the   resulting   differences   in   the   structure   of   the   state.   In   a   nutshell,   common   law  countries  tend  to  define  liberty  based  on  the  Humian-­‐Lockian  tradition  as  individual  liberty,   while   civil   law   countries   follow   a   Hobbesian-­‐Rousseauist   tradition   of  seeking   to  achieve   liberty   through  collective  goals  pursued  by   the  state   (Mahoney  2001:  511).  This  philosophical  difference   leads  according   to  Mahoney   (2001)   to  a  difference   in   the   structure   of   government:   common   law   countries   tend   to   adopt  institutions   that   fragment   the   power   of   government,   by   creating   various  independent   authorities   (e.g.   the   courts),   while   civil   law   countries   tend   to  concentrate  governmental  power  more,  which  also  implies  that  institutions  such  as  courts   are   less   independent   from   the   executive   branch   of   government.   More  importantly   for   the   purpose   of   this   paper,   however,   Mahoney’s   (2001)   analysis  moves  away  from  the  LFS  focus  on  the  role  of  law  in  the  economy.  

Other   LFS   papers,   however,   do   attempt   to   specify  more   precise  mechanisms   that  link  legal  origins  to  outcomes.  The  most  explicit  discussion  identifies  two  channels:  firstly,   the   ‘adaptability   channel’   and   secondly   the   ‘political   channel’   (Beck   et   al.  2003).  

The   adaptability   channel   claims   that   common   law   systems   allow   judges   more  discretion  in  interpreting  legal  rules  on  a  case-­‐by-­‐case  basis  than  civil  law  systems.  This   leads   to   efficient   evolution   of   the   law   through   litigation   and   elimination   of  inefficient  rules  by  courts  (Beck  et  al.  2003  citing  Posner  1973).  The  litigation-­‐based  system   of   common   law   also   implies   that   judges   have   a   great   deal   of   discretion,  which  they  can  use  to  apply  broad  principles  such  as  ‘fairness’,  ‘fiduciary  duty’,  ‘duty  

Page 10: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  10  

of  loyalty’,  and  ‘duty  of  care’  to  cases  that  are  not  explicitly  covered  in  any  statutory  law  (Johnson  et  al.  2000).  Consequently,  common  law  judges  can  react  to  new  kinds  of  wrongdoings  by  insiders  and  protect  investors  efficiently  (LLSV  2000).  Civil  law,  on   the   other   hand,   is   seen   as   rigid,   formalistic,   and   based   on   the   principle   that  anything   that   is   not   explicitly   forbidden   is   allowed   (LLSV   2000:   9).   As   a   result,  insiders  will  be  able  to  invent  new  ways  of  expropriating  shareholders  without  the  judges  having  any  means  to  stop  them  from  doing  so,  unless  the  law  changes.  Broad  common  law  principles  may  hence  be  a  better  way  of  protecting  investors  than  the  written  ‘bright-­‐line  rules’  typical  of  civil  law  statutes.  

Various  authors  have  criticised  the  LFS  for  this  –  in  their  view  –  too  strong  contrast  between   the   two   generic   legal   systems,   which   is   according   to   them   greatly  exaggerated  and  out-­‐dated,  underestimating  the  adaptability  of  the  civil  law  system  (see  Armour  et  al.  2009b,  Dam  2006,  Siems  2007,  Roe  &  Siegel  2009).  Siems  (2007)  showed   that   civil   law   systems   use   ‘framework   laws’,   which   provide   quite   a  substantial   amount   of   flexibility   for   judges   to   adapt   bright-­‐line   rules   to   changing  circumstances.   Dam   (2006)   argued   forcefully   that   in   today’s   world,   the   idea   that  common   law   countries   relied   less   on   statutes   and   regulations   and   more   on  principles   such   as   ‘fiduciary   duty’   was   plain  wrong,   as   codification   has   increased  dramatically   even   in   common   law   countries.   As   for   the   efficiency   of   litigation,  Posner  himself  –  who  had  introduced  the  thesis  of  efficiency  of  common  law  (Posner  1973)   –   together  with   authors   from   the   LFS   have   found   contrary   evidence   to   the  notion  that  common  law  converges  to  efficiency  thanks  to  ‘adversarial  adjudication’  through  private  litigation.  Based  on  a  case  study  of  the  so-­‐called  Economic  Loss  Rule  (ELR),  Niblett  et  al.  (2010)  found  no  convergence  to  efficiency  over  a  30-­‐year  period  of  litigation.  

The  second,  ‘political’  channel  by  which  legal  origin  affects  the  quality  of  law  refers  to  two  fundamentally  different  goals  of  law  in  the  two  systems:  common  law,  so  the  argument   runs,  was  mainly   created   to   protect   private   property   rights   against   the  power  of   the  English  monarchy,  while   civil   law  emerged   to   strengthen   the  grip  of  the   French   king   over   powerful   local   interests   (Glaeser   &   Shleifer   2002)   and  was  further  developed  after  the  French  revolution  to  “solidify  state  power”,  to  limit  the  leeway  of  judges  (Beck  et  al.  2003:  654),  and  to  implement  state  policy  (LLS  2008:  286;  also  Mahoney  2001;  Djankov  et  al.  2003).  While  earlier  LFS  studies  suggested  that  legal  origins  diverged  after  the  French  revolution,  Glaeser  and  Shleifer  (2002)  argue  that  these  differences  can  be  traced  back  to  the  12th  century  when  France  and  England  made   fundamental   choices  about   the  centralisation  or  decentralisation  of  state  control  over  the  judiciary.  While  the  English  crown  in  the  12th  century  enjoyed  a  relatively  peaceful  phase  and  enjoyed  strong  control  over  local  lords,  France  was  in  a  state  of  contestation  of  the  King’s  power  by  local  lords,  which  implied  that  there  was  a  threat  to  law  enforces  at  the  local  level  (Glaeser  &  Shleifer  2002).  As  a  result,  the  French  crown  moved  to  a  centralised  system  based  on  state-­‐employed  judges  in  order   to   protect   law   enforces   from   strong   local   pressures,   while   the   English  

Page 11: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  11  

monarchy  had   the   luxury  of   relying  on  a  decentralised   judiciary   system   thanks   to  the  relative  weakness  of  local  lords  (Glaeser  &  Shleifer  2002).  Fundamentally,  then,  the   difference   between   civil   law   and   common   law   is   one   of   state   control   versus  independent  judiciary  (Glaeser  &  Shleifer  2002:  1196).  

On  this  account,  a  key  difference  between  different   legal  origins   is   indeed   ‘judicial  independence’.  La  Porta  et  al.   (2004)   investigate   the  role  of  constitutional  rules  of  judicial  independence,  as  an  important  check  in  a  political  system.  They  find  indeed  that   judicial   independence  leads  to  greater  economic  freedom  and  conclude  that  it  might   be   the   ‘micro-­‐foundation’   of   the   positive   impact   of   English   legal   origin   on  economic   outcomes   (La   Porta   et   al.   2004:   449).   This   analysis,   based   on  constitutionally  guaranteed  checks-­‐and-­‐balances  enshrined   in   the  political   system,  however,   seems  already   far   removed   from   the   substantive   claims  made  about   the  quality  of  law  in  the  earlier  work.    

This  shift  away  from  a  narrow  –  but  seemingly  clear  –  definition  of  legal  origins  as  a  country’s   legal  system  being   ‘rooted   in  one  of   the   four  mother  systems’  and  being  associated   with   substantive   legal   features,   is   quite   explicit   in   the   LFS   literature.  More  recent  LFS  studies  explicitly  define  legal  origin  as  “a  style  of  social  control  of  economic  life  (and  maybe  of  other  aspects  of   life  as  well)”  (LLS  2008:  286),  where  “English  Legal  Origin  is  a  broad  indicator  of  a  market-­‐supporting  regulatory  stance”  (Gennaioli  et  al.  2014:  290).  Mahoney  (2001:  523)  explicitly  rejects  the  substantive  link  and  argues  that  legal  origins  reflect  different  ‘philosophies  of  government’.  

The  more   recent   definitions   of   legal   origin,   then,   are   not   so  much   about   specific,  substantive   characteristics   of   common   law   versus   civil   law,   but   rather   about   the  different  purposes  and  structures  of  the  legal  and  indeed  political  systems  in  these  two  broad  families.  The  purpose  of  common  law  is,  according  to  this  interpretation,  one  of  dispute  resolution,  while  civil  law  is  considered  to  have  as  its  main  purpose  to  implement  state-­‐made  policies  (LLSV  2008:  285,  citing  Damaska  1986;  Glaeser  &  Shleifer  2002).    Common  law  is  hence  considered  less  politicised,  leading  to  smaller  and   more   fragmented   governments,   and   focused   on   supporting   private   market  outcomes,   while   civil   law   seeks   to   achieve   ‘state-­‐desired   allocations’   through  centralised  policy  implementation  (LLS  2008).  

This  does  raise  the  question  why  we  should  use  legal  origin  to  capture  such  broad  characteristics   of   the   polity   (e.g.   judicial   review   and   independence)   rather   than  using  measures   of   the   centralisation   of   policy-­‐making,   the   number   of   formal   veto  points   in   policy-­‐making,   or   similar   measure   of   the   (de-­‐)centralisation   of   a   polity  common   in   political   science.   More   importantly,   however,   this   shift   towards  increasingly  broad  definition  of  legal  origins  leads  the  LFS,  however,  to  the  verge  of  rather   culturalist   arguments   about   the   superiority   of   certain   civilisations   over  others.   LLSV   (2004:   445)   most   explicitly   make   this   point   stating   that   there   are  “significant   benefits   of   the   Anglo-­‐American   system   of   government   for   freedom.”  

Page 12: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  12  

Already   LLSV   (1997b:333)   employed   similarly   culturalist   arguments   essentially  arguing   that   Catholicism   (and   Islam)   are   inferior   to   Protestantism   in   terms   of  economic   outcomes,   because   they   prevent   the   emergence   of   ‘horizontal   trust’  among  people.    

In  short  then,  the  LFS  –  also  pressured  by  critiques  of  the  initial  claims  –  has  moved  into   a   increasingly   broad   –   but   also   vague   –   theory   that   ultimately   does   not   say  much  more  than  that  market-­‐based,  non-­‐interventionist  system  of  the  Anglo-­‐Saxon  countries  is  superior  to  others  in  terms  of  economic  development  and  freedom.  

In   this   sense,   the   very   designation   of   this   stream   of   research   as   ‘Law   &   Finance’  becomes   a   misnomer,   because   the   causal   arguments   made   are   very   marginally  about   law  and  are  much  more   about  broad   characteristics   of   the   role  of   the   state  and  of  markets   in  different  countries.  Civil   law   features  such  as  more  government  ownership,   more   regulation,   and   closer   ties   between   the   government   and   the  judiciary   are   expected   to   lead   to  more   corruption,   rent-­‐seeking,   a   larger   informal  economy,  and  higher   levels  of  unemployment.  Common  law  is  associate  with   legal  independence,  contract  enforcement,  and  hence  protection  of  property  rights,  which  is  associated  with  better  economic  outcomes  (LLSV  2008:  286).  

This   is   an  unfortunate  development,   because   it  moves   the   attention  of   the   theory  away   from  explaining  not   just   that   law  matters,  but  also  how   it  matters.   Indeed,  a  central   thesis   of   the   present   paper   is   that   the   shift   from   quality   of   law   to   legal  origins,   however   defined,   has   considerably  weakened   the   analytical   power   of   the  LFS   approach   and   has   undermined   the   initial   attempts   to   contribute   to   our  understanding   of   the   impact   of   institutional   factors   on   economic   outcomes.   The  more  recent  LFS  studies  could  quite  conceivably  renounce  any  reference  to  the  law.  The   goal   of   the   present   paper,   however,   is   to   investigate   and   refine   our  understanding   of   why   we   would   expect   law   to   play   an   important   role   in   the  economy.   Therefore,   moving   away   from   questions   substantive   law   to   broader  historical,   cultural,   and   political   factors   does   not   seem   to   be   the   right   strategy.  Instead,  we  ask  a  series  of  questions  regarding  the  concept  of  law  in  the  LFS,  which  will  allow  us  to  further  clarify  –  rather  than  avoid  –  the  question  of  how  law  matters.  

2.3.  What  is  the  role  of  law  in  the  economy?  

As  noted  above,   it   is   certainly  a  key   contribution  of   the  LFS   to  have  brought   ‘law’  into   the   debate   on  what   determines   differences   in   national   corporate   governance  systems.   In   this   respect,   LFS   can   broadly   be   categorised   as   a   New   Institutional  Economics   (NIE)   approach   (LLSV   1999b).   Ronald   Coase,   Harold   Demsetz   and  Douglas  North’s  work  –  all  of  which  are  usually  associated  with  the  NIE  approach  –  are   often   cited   in   the   LFS   literature.   In   this   respect,   LFS  may   also   be   considered  close   to   the  Law  and  Economics   school,  which   is  often  associated  with   the   rise  of  NIE.   However,   LLSV   are   clear   on   distinguishing   their   approach   –   which   they   call  ‘legal   approach   to   corporate   governance’   in   some   of   their   papers   (LLSV   2000)   –  

Page 13: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  13  

from  the  L&E  school.  Thus,  LLSV  (2000:  7)  state  that  “The  emphasis  on  legal  rules  and   regulations   protecting   outside   investors   stands   in   sharp   contrast   to   the  traditional   `law  and  economics’  perspective  on   financial   contracting.”   Indeed,   they  reject   the  more   libertarian   ideas   in   the   field,  which  consider  –  based  on  the  Coase  theorem  (Coase  1960)  –  that  rational  actors  will  find  optimal  solutions  to  allocation  problems  via  private  contracts,  as  long  as  the  contracts  are  enforced  (Stigler  1964;  Easterbrook&Fischel   1991).   In   such   situations   no   regulations   of   markets   is  required.  The  LFS  rejects  this  view  and  emphasises  the  importance  of  laws  and  even  government   regulation   in   certain   –   limited   –   circumstances  when   enforcement   of  contracts   cannot   be   taken   for   granted   (LLSV   2000:   7).   Indeed,   much   of   the   LFS  literature   is   about   finding   out   under   what   circumstances   certain   institutional  choices   are   optimal.   Most   explicitly,   Glaeser   and   Shleifer   (2003:   403)   argue   that  depending  on   the  general   level  of   ‘law  and  order’   in  a  country,  a  system  based  on  pure  private  litigation  in  public  courts  may  not  be  optimal.4  Rather,  if  law  and  order  is  only  moderate  in  a  country,  some  state  regulation  may  be  more  efficient.  Law  and  regulation  play  hence  have  a  more  important  –  and  potentially  more  benign  –  role  than  in  the  traditional  L&E  literature.  To  be  sure,  the  LFS  is  eager  to  stress  that  state  intervention   is   always   second   best   to   private,   decentralised,   market-­‐based  solutions.  Thus,  Glaeser  and  Shleifer  (2003)  consider  that  private  litigation  is  indeed  the   best   solutions   in   very   advanced   countries   with   high   levels   of   law   and   order.  LLSV  (2000:  22)  state  that  government  regulation  should  be  used  only  if  contracts  are   not   enforceable.   These   cases,   however,   are   very   rare.     Shleifer   (2005:   440)  approvingly   cites   the  Chicago   School’s   view   that   “the  domain  of  market   failure  or  socially  harmful  conduct  that  is  not  automatically  controlled  by  impersonal  forces  of  competition   is   extremely   limited.”   Nevertheless,   there   are   cases   in   which   state  regulation  may   be  warranted   and   achieve   optimal   outcomes.   These   cases   include  situations   where   economic   and   political   inequality   is   high,   which   favours   the  subversion  of  courts  by  powerful  litigants,  leading  to  a  situation  where  the  “strong”  not   the   “just’   win   court   cases   (Glaeser   &   Shleifer   2002;   Glaeser   et   al.   2003).  Depending   on   the   “enforcement   environment”   –   i.e.   the   cost   of   enforcement   –,  different   types   of   legal   systems   may   hence   be   optimal,   including   in   some   cases  public  regulation  (Djankov  et  al.  2003:  605;  Glaeser  &  Shleifer  2002).  Therefore,  LFS  treats  the  choice  of  the  optimal  legal  regime  as  an  empirical  question,  which  leaves  room   even   for   state   intervention   and   regulation;   although,   the   authors   seem   to                                                                                                                            4  It  should  be  noted  that  there  is  possibly  some  circularity  in  the  argument  here:  ‘law  and  order’  is  not  defined  at  the  outset  of  the  paper,  but  p.423  refers  to  Coase  1960  and  equates  ‘securing  property  rights’  with  ‘establishing  law  and  order’.  This  would  imply  that  the  above  argument  essentially  states  that  the  protection  of  property  rights  via  courts  or  regulation  depends  on  the  level  of  the  (de  facto?)  protection  of  property  rights.  From  the  remainder  of  the  paper,  however,  it  would  rather  seem  that  ‘law  and  order’  is  considered  to  be  a  more  general  tendency  among  a  country’s  population  to  respect  the  law  or  follow  rules.  This  could  possibly  be  interpreted  as  a  Weberian  understanding  of  legitimacy,  i.e.  that,  in  general,  laws  are  accepted  to  be  binding  (cf.  Green  2013:  489).  Either  way,  the  argument  does  border  on  tautology  here  in  the  sense  that  they  investigate  what  institutional  choices  are  optimal  to  secure  property  rights  depending  on  different  levels  of  ‘law  and  order’,  which  in  turn  is  defined  as  the  extent  to  which  property  rights  are  de  facto  secure.    

Page 14: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  14  

consider  state   intervention  second  best  and  only   required   in   situations  where   the  overall   institutional  or   socio-­‐economic  environment   (law  and  order,   inequality)   is  sub-­‐optimal.  Thus,  on   the   finding   that  French-­‐civil   law  countries  often  have  credit  registration   agencies   that   do   seem   to  work  well,   they   consider   this   to   be   a   “rare  example  of  an  apparently  successful  state  intervention”  (Djankov  et  al.  2007:  301).  

In   short   then,   the   LFS  distinguishes   itself   from  other   branches   of  NIE   in   that   it   is  more  open  to  the  efficiency  of  various  governance  mechanisms  and  attributes  law  a  larger   role   in   the   economy   than   other   approaches.   Indeed,   while   many   scholars  writing   in   the   L&E   tradition   consider   the   role   of   legal   rules   to   be   secondary  compared   to   private   contracts   (Easterbrook   &   Fischel   1991)   or   market   forces  (Fama   1980),   LLSV   consider   law   to  matter   in   important  ways   for   the   nature   and  development   of   financial   markets.   This   view   is   based   on   what   LLS   (2008:   FN1)  consider  to  be  the  ‘standard  proposition’  in  corporate  law,  i.e.  that  legal  protection  of   outside   investors   limits   expropriation   by   insiders   and   promotes   financial  development.  

The  originality  of  the  initial  LFS  studies  was  also  to  go  beyond  this  broad  statement  that   ‘law   matters’   and   empirically   determine   which   aspects   of   law   matter.   This  question  will  be  investigated  in  the  next  sub-­‐section.  

2.4  What  is  good  law?  

The  ‘quality  of  law’  claim  is  crucial  to  the  early  LFS  studies.  Quality  of  company  law  refers   to   the   level   of   protection   from   expropriation   by   insiders   that   law   affords  minority  shareholders:  higher  levels  of  MSP  are  equated  with  ‘better  quality’  (LLSV  1997,  1998,  1999a,  2000).  The  choice  of  the  term  ‘quality’  is  telling  here,  because  it  refers  to  an  explicit  normative  judgement,  which  is  also  reflected  in  the  use  of  terms  like   ‘improve’,   ‘better’,   etc.   to   characterise   legal   changes   (e.g.   LLSV   1999a:   505;  2000:   6,   20;   Glaeser   et   al.   2003:   272),   and   of   the   terms   ‘good   law’,   ‘good  governance’,  ‘good  government’  (e.g.  LLSV  1997a:  1194),  which  are  pervasive  in  the  LFS   literature.   LLSV   (1999b:   223)   explicitly   state   their   normative   stance   writing  that  they  narrowly  define  ‘good’  as  what  is  “good-­‐for-­‐economic-­‐development”.  Good  law  is  hence  defined  as  law  that  leads  to  good  (or  efficient)  economic  outcomes.  This  is  broadly  in  line  with  the  economic  analysis  of  law  tradition  (Posner  1973)  and  NIE,  which  is  very  much  concerned  with  outcomes  and  the  efficiency  of  law  on  which  the  LFS  clearly  draws.  In  this  context,  the  early  studies  present  the  Anti-­‐Director  Rights  Index   (ADRI)   as   one   empirically   tested   proxy   of   substantive   standards   for   good  company   law.  These  substantive  standards,  however,  are  not   to  be  seen  as  purely  the   result   of   positive   law.   Rather   they   are   standards   that   ought   to   apply   in   any  country.   Consider   the   following   passage   in   Johnson   et   al.   (2000:   3),   defining  “tunnelling”   transactions:   “[A]   controlling   shareholder   can   simply   transfer  resources  from  the  firm  for  his  own  benefit  through  self-­‐dealing  transactions.  Such  transactions   [of   ‘tunnelling’]   include   outright   theft   or   fraud,   which   are   illegal  

Page 15: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  15  

everywhere   though   often   go   undetected   or   unpunished,   but   also   asset   sales,  contracts   such   as   transfer   pricing   advantageous   to   the   controlling   shareholder,  excessive   executive   compensation,   loan   guarantees,   expropriation   of   corporate  opportunities,  and  so  on.”  This  passage  shows  that  transactions  are  categorised  as  tunnelling  –  and  hence  considered  to  be  ‘bad’  –  even  when  they  are  not  prohibited  by  the  laws  of  the  country  in  question.  Further,  the  passage  even  implies  that  ‘theft’  and  ‘fraud’  have  an  objective  existence  independent  from  the  positive  law  in  a  given  country,  although  they  happen  to  be  made  illegal  in  virtually  all  legal  systems.  This  clearly  hints  at   the  existence  of  external  standards   to   judge  the  quality  of   law  and  reveals  the  underlying  concept  of  law  in  LFS.  

Similarly,   Djankov   et   al.   (2008)   investigate   the   extent   to   which   minority  shareholders  can  oppose  self-­‐dealing  transactions  by  controlling  shareholders.  The  focus  is  explicitly  on  transactions  where  ‘a  controlling  shareholder  wants  to  enrich  himself  while  following  the  law’  (Djankov  et  al.  2008:  432).  Again,  if  the  controlling  shareholder   follows   the   law,   i.e.   the   transaction   is   not   illegal  per   se,   the   question  arises  on  what  normative  basis  the  assessment  is  made  that  minority  shareholders  should  be  able  to  prevent  the  transaction  or  to  sue  for  damages  if  it  does  go  through.  The  implicit  answer  is  that  ‘self-­‐dealing’  is  considered  ‘bad’  per  se  possibly  –  but  not  explicitly   –   based   on   general   principles   such   as   ‘fairness’,   ‘fiduciary   duty’,   or   the  respect  of  property  rights.  But  this  is  precisely  the  point,  if  we  assess  the  ‘quality’  of  a  country’s  laws  against  some  external  standard,  which  is  not  explicitly  part  of  the  positive   law  in  question,  we  are  already  making  assumptions  about  the  concept  of  law  that  is  being  applied.  The  LFS  acts  on  the  assumption  that  laws  have  to  live-­‐up  to  certain  criteria  to  be  considered  ‘good’  or  even  valid.  

This  view  is  quite  incompatible  with  both  a  legal  positivist  view  of  the  law  and  with  the   constitutive   function   of   law.   Positivists   like   John   Austin   (1832)   posited   two  fundamental   principles:   Firstly,   laws   are   orders   issued   by   a   supreme,   legally  unlimited  sovereign  and  backed  by  the  threat  of  punishment.  Secondly,  such  orders  do   not   need   to   conform  with   any   substantive  moral   standards   or   social   norms   in  order   to   be   considered   valid   law.   The   fact   that   it   emanates   from   a   sovereign   is  sufficient.  This  view  is  most  strongly  opposed  by  natural  law  theories  that  consider  valid  law  only  law  that  is  in  accordance  with  certain  substantive  principles.  In  other  words,   morally   ‘bad   law’   is   not   considered   law   at   all.   Strong   legal   positivism,   as  defended  by  Austin  and  Kelsen  (1967),  on  the  other  hand  posits  a  strict  separation  of  law  and  morality  and  social  custom.  Therefore,  for  a  legal  positivist,  the  acts  that  are   outlawed   as   ‘theft’   and   ‘fraud’   only   become   ‘theft’   and   ‘fraud’   once   the   law  defines  them  as  such.  There  may  be  social  norms  that  consider  ‘theft’  and  ‘fraud’  to  be  morally   condemnable,   but   as   long   as   the   law   does   not   agree  with   these   social  norms,   there   is   no   reason   to   assess   the   quality   of   the   law   against   external  moral  standards  about  what  is  right  or  wrong.  Positive  law,  from  this  perspective,  does  not  have  to  follow  social  morality.    

Page 16: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  16  

From  the  constitutive  point  of  view,  ‘theft’  and  ‘fraud’  are  creations  of  the  law  in  the  first  place  (see  Deakin  et  al.  2015;  Sarat  &  Kearns  1993).  That   is   to  say,   if   the   law  does  not  define  them  as  such,  they  do  not  have  an  object  existence  outside  the  law.  The  constitutive  role  of  the  law  is  neglected  by  the  LFS.  

On  the  other  hand,  however,  certain  LFS  studies  refer  to  another  criterion  for  ‘good’  law,  which   is  not   substantive  but  what  one  could  call   a   legitimacy  criteria,   i.e.   the  extent  to  which  a  given  law  is  enforceable  in  a  given  context,  because  it  is  acceptable  to  its  population.  Thus,  LLSV  (2000:22)  state:    

 “[G]ood  legal  rules  are  the  ones  that  a  country  can  enforce.  The  strategy  for  reform  is  not  to  create  an  ideal  set  of  rules  and  then  see  how  well  they  can  be  enforced,  but  rather  to  enact  the  rules  that  can  be  enforced  within  the  existing  structure.”  

The  quality  of  law  is  hence  also  related  to  the  question  of  enforcement.  Enforcement  is   indeed   a  major   concern   of   the   LFS.   Different   factors   affecting   the   ‘enforcement  environment’  are  analysed:  The  competence  and  incentives  of  judges  (Glaeser  et  al.  2001;   Glaeser   &   Shleifer   2002;),   the   degree   of   subversion   of   courts   by   particular  interests   (Glaeser  et  al.  2003;  Glaeser  &  Shleifer  2003),   the  quality  of  government  (LLSV  1999b),  as  well  as  characteristics  of  jurisprudence  in  common  law  countries  such  as  the  role  of  precedents  (Gennaioli  and  Shleifer  2007a,  2007b,  2008,  Niblett  et  al.  2010).  Here,  however,  we   find  an  additional  element,   i.e.   that  enforcement  will  also   depend   on   the   degree   to   which   laws   reflect   the   ‘communities   standards’.  Glaeser   and   Shleifer   (2002:   1202)   even   suggest   that   a   decentralised   judiciary  implies  that  ‘community  standards  of  justice’  are  more  closely  reflected  in  the  legal  system,  which  may  be  one  of  the  reasons  for  English  common  law’s  superiority.  

More  fundamentally,  the  question  of  proximity  with  community  standards  reveals  a  further   departure   from   legal   positivism.   Associating   the   ‘quality’   of   law   with   the  degree  to  which  it  reflects  ‘community  standards’  hints  at  a  distinctly  non-­‐positivist  conception  of   law  in  the  LFS.  There  are  various  elements  in  the  LFS  literature  that  confirm   this   view   of   a   non-­‐positivist   concept   of   law.   Thus,   in   a   rare   explicit  reference   to   legal   theory,   LLS   (2008:   footnote  2)   associate   legal  positivism,  which  they  summarise  as  conceiving  of  law  as  the  ‘expression  of  the  will  of  the  legislator  as  supreme  interpreter  of   justice’  with  the  socialist   legal  tradition,  which  they  clearly  reject  (LLS  2008:  FN2).  

More   generally,   the   above-­‐mentioned   broad   definitions   of   legal   origins   also  make  the   boundary   between   law   and   other,   non-­‐legal   social   norms   of   conduct   more  permeable,   hinting   at   a   non-­‐positivist   conception   of   law.   Thus,   already   LLSV  (1997a)   hint   at   the   possibility   that  what   drives   the   association   between   the   legal  system   and   economic   outcomes   may   be   societal   factors   that   filter   into   the   legal  system.   LLSV   (1997a:   1150)   acknowledge   that   ‘[l]t   is   possible   that   some   broad  underlying  factor,  related  to  trust,  influences  the  development  of  all  institutions  in  a  

Page 17: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  17  

country,   including   laws   and   capital   markets.’   One   such   factor,   which   has   been  explored  in  the  LFS,   is  ideology.  Thus,  Zweigert  and  Kotz  (1998:72)  state  that  "the  style  of  a  legal  system  may  be  marked  by  an  ideology,  that  is,  a  religious  or  political  conception  of  how  economic  or  social  life  should  be  organized".  This  line  of  thought  is  also  explored  in  LLSV  (1997b)  where  the  level  of  trust  in  a  society  is  related  to  the  prevailing   religion   in   a   country.   Indirectly,   the   LFS   postulates   hence   a   connection  between   the   law   and   rules   stemming   from   non-­‐legal   sources   such   as   ideologies,  religions,  and  –  presumably  –  other  moral  norms  more  generally.  

Therefore,  we  can  conclude  that  the  LFS  rejects  legal  positivism  whose  main  tenant  –  at  least  in  its  exclusive  or  hard  form  –  is  the  notion  of  a  strict  separation  of  law  and  morals.   The   LFS’s   acknowledgement   of   ideological,   religious,   and   ‘community  standards’  as  a   fundament   for   legal   rules  as  well  as   the  assessment  of   law  against  external  criteria  both  suggest   that   laws  are  conceived  of  as  having   to   fulfil   certain  substantive  criteria.  LFS  clearly  does  not  seem  to  adhere  to  a  positivist  conception  of  law,  what  alternative  concepts  of  law  does  it  adhere  to  instead?  Here,  a  discussion  of  the  LFS’s  customary  conception  of  legal  rules  may  provide  some  insights.  

Probably  the  most  explicit  statement  of  the  view  that  legal  rules  necessarily  need  to  be  grounded  in  a  society’s  practices  can  be  found  in  Hay  and  Shleifer  (1998:  402):  ‘Whenever   possible,   laws   must   agree   with   prevailing   practice   or   custom.’   The  reason  for  this  necessary  correspondence  between  law  and  social  practice  is  not  a  pragmatic  concern  with  the  effectiveness  of  laws:  ‘If  public  laws  violate  the  practice,  then  private  parties  may  refuse  to  enforce  them  either  on  their  own  or  with  ultimate  reference  to  courts.  The  coordination  benefit  of  public  laws  would  then  be  lost’  (ibid.  1998:  402).  A  gap  between  social   custom  or  practice  and   law  will  hence   lead   to  a  reduced   efficiency   of   the   legal   system.   This   view   is   in   line   with   old   institutional  scholarship  and  in  particular  Commons’s  (1924)  understanding  according  to  which  to  be  enforceable,  laws  must  be  perceived  as  reasonable,  appropriate,  and  fair  (see  Deakin   et   al.   2015:   3).   This  may   be   interpreted   as   a   concern  with   a   fundamental  willingness  of  a   society   to   follow   the   law   in  general.   Indeed,   the  above-­‐mentioned  concern   in  Glaeser  and  Shleifer   (2003:  403)   that  a  certain   level  of   ‘law  and  order’  needs   to   be   present   in   order   for   a   court-­‐based   system   to   be   effective.   This   idea,  which   we   may   seem   tautological   at   first   glance,   becomes   understandable   if   we  interpret  precisely  as  implying  a  certain  willingness  of  the  population  to  accept  the  law  as  legitimate.  Here  this  Weberian  legitimacy  may  be  the  result  of  the  closeness  of  legal  rules  to  the  social  morality  of  the  society  in  question.  

Therefore,  like  LLSV  (2000,  cf.  supra),  Hay  and  Shleifer  (1998)  define  ‘good  rules’  in  a   first   instance   via   their   acceptability:   ‘good   legal   rules   are   those   likely   to   be  adopted  by  private  parties  for  both  structuring  and  enforcing  their  transactions,  as  well  as  used  by  courts’  (Hay&Shleifer  1998:  401).  The  definition  of  ‘good  law’  is  here  a   purely   pragmatic   and   practical   one,   which   does   not   presuppose   any   specific  

Page 18: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  18  

substantive  content  of   legal  rules  to  be  considered   ‘good’,  but  simply  that  they  are  accepted.    

This   focus   on   acceptability   recalls   what   has   come   to   be   known   as   Hart’s   (1961)  ‘practice   theory   of   rules’   (Hart   2012[1961]:   254-­‐5).   On   this   ‘soft’   legal   positivist  account,  legal  systems  are  necessarily  based  on  ‘social  rules’,  which  –  however  –  are  not   defined   in   a   substantive   or   normative   way,   but   rather   are   defined   as   social  practices   that   are   generally   used   and   accepted   as   guides   for   action   (Hart  2012[1961]:  89).  More  precisely:  

“Social  Rules  of  a  group  [are  defined]  as  constituted  by  a   form  of  social  practice  comprising  both  patterns  of  conduct  regularly  followed  by  most  members   of   the   group   and   a   distinctive   normative   attitude   to   such  patterns  of  conduct  which  I  have  called  ‘acceptance’”  (Hart  2012[1961]:  255)  

Here,   the   key   characteristic   of   a   valid   rule   is   a   widespread   expression   of  endorsement,  but  not  a   cognitive  belief   in   the   legitimacy  of   the   rule  on  normative  grounds   (Perry   2006).   This   pragmatic   and   non-­‐cognitivist   view   of   rules   seems   in  line  with  the  concept  of  law  that  the  LFS  adopts,  albeit  implicitly.  

However,  this  view,  while  acknowledging  a  fundamental  role  for  norms,  downplays  the   extent   of   the   normative   nature   of   law   (Perry   2006).   Hart   (2012[1961]:   256)  himself,   in   the   post-­‐script   to   the   second   edition   of   ‘The   Concept   of   Law’   (TCL)   –  published   posthumously   in   1994   –,acknowledges   that   Dworkin   is   correct   in  pointing   out   that   the   ‘practice   theory’   only   applies   to   conventional   rules.  Conventional  rules  are  defined  as  rules  that  are  based  on  a  consensus  of  convention,  whereby  the  reason  for  people  for  acceptance  of  the  practice  is  because  most  other  people   follow  the  rule  as  well.  Such  rules  are  different   from  the  situation  where  a  social  practice   is   followed  not  by   convention  within   a   group,  but  by   its   individual  members’  independent  conviction.  Conversely,  Hart  accepts  that  his  practice  theory  is  not  a  sound  explanation  of  individual  or  social  morality  or  enacted  –  as  opposed  to  customary  –  legal  rules,  which  do  not  require  specific  acceptance  as  long  as  they  were  enacted  in  accordance  with  the  rules  for  adopting  enacted  rules  that  the  rule  of   recognition   establishes   (ibid.).   The   above-­‐mentioned   view   in   some   LFS   studies  that  legal  rules  should  be  customary  rules  whose  main  characterised  is  (or  ought  to  be)  their  acceptance  in  a  society  appears  to  be  subject  to  the  same  shortcoming  as  Hart’s  conception  of  rules  as  social  practice.  Indeed,  it  is  at  best  a  partial  description  of  what  law  is.  

The   customary   nature   of   legal   rules   is   not   the   only   criterion   for   their   ‘goodness’  however.   As   mentioned   above,   in   some   places,   the   LFS   does   make   explicit  statements   about   the   content   of   legal   rules   that   substantively   defines   ‘good   law’.  Hay   and   Shleifer   (1998:   401)   explicitly   add   to   the   criterion   of   the   acceptance   of  rules  that  ‘some  rules  facilitate  trade  better  than  others.’  The  facilitation  of  trade  –  

Page 19: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  19  

and  economic  activity  more  generally  presumably  –  constitutes  hence  a  substantive  criterion  for  good  law.  Here  we  can  observe  some  affinity  of  the  LFS’s  concept  of  law  with   another   important   strand   of   customary-­‐conventional   theory   of   law,  which   is  the   evolutionary-­‐functionalist   theory   of   F.   A.   Hayek   (1960;   1983).   Hayek’s  (2011[1960]:  115-­‐6)  idea  of  law  as  a  spontaneous  order  that  crystallises  as  a  result  of  a  process  of   ‘adaptive  evolution’   through  survival  of   the   fittest  rules  has   indeed  influenced   some   authors   in   the   LFS   tradition.   Besides   explicitly   Hayekian   papers  (Mahoney  2001,   see  supra),  different  LFS  publications  refer   to  Hayekian  concepts.  La   Porta   and   Shleifer   (2009)   and   Djankov   et   al.   (2003a)   for   instance   base   their  conceptualisation  of  legal  procedure  and  its  impact  on  the  economy  on  an  explicitly  Hayekian  analysis  (also  LLSV  1999b,  Glaeser  &  Shleifer  2002).  Thus,  Djankov  et  al.  (2003a:  600)  cite  Hayek’s  evolutionary  view  as  one  among  others  that  may  explain  how  efficient  laws  emerge.  

It  is  hence  worth  looking  at  Hayek’s  evolutionary  theory  of  law  in  some  more  detail.  Hayek’s  theory  of   law  has  some  affinities  with  Hart’s  concept  of   law.  Thus,   in  Law,  Legislation  &  Liberty  (2013[1982]:  p.125  and  FN19),  Hayek  points  to  the  importance  of   the   distinction   between   ‘rules   of   just   conduct’   and   ‘rules   of   organisation   of  government’.   He   cites   Hart   (1961),   suggesting   that   this   distinction   is   indeed  equivalent  to  Hart’s  distinction  between   ‘primary  rules’   that  are  addressed  to   ‘law  takers’  and  ‘secondary  rules’,  which  are  the  rules  establishing  how  valid  law  needs  to  be  adapted  and  changed.  Primary  rules  are,  in  Hayek’s  view,  the  original  type  of  laws,  which  guarantee  a  society’s  liberty.  They  are  substantively  defined  as  negative  ‘rules   of   just   conduct’   protecting   individuals’   private   sphere   from   interference   by  the  state  and  others.  They  constitute   together   the  system  that  he  calls  nomocracy,  which   allows   him   to   distinguish   rules   of   just   conduct   (nomos)   from   ‘other  commands   called   law‘   (Hayek   2013[1982]:   200).   Secondary   rules,   on   the   other  hand,  are  useful  and  acceptable  as  long  as  they  simply  aim  at  enforcing  the  rules  of  just   conduct.   Indeed,   enforcing   the   latter   is   the   only   justification   for   the   use   of  coercion,  which  is  determined  by  secondary  rules  (Hayek  2013[1982]:  130).  This  is  where  Hayek  departs   from  Hart.  Hayek’s  concept  of   law   is  based  on  a  substantive  definition  of  what  valid  law  is.  Therefore,  he  rejects  Hart’s  claim  that  the  acceptance  by  a  society’s  officials  of  a  ‘Rule  of  Recognition’  (RoR)  constitutes  a  sufficient  basis  of  validity  for  any  positive  law.  Rather,  Hayek  –  while  acknowledging  the  existence  of  a  RoR  –  considers  that  the  RoR  alone  would  not  confer  on  the  pre-­‐existing  law  its  validity  (Hayek  2013[1982]:  130).   In  order   for   law  to  be  valid,   it  will  also  need  to  conform  with   substantive   criteria,   the  most   fundamental   of  which   are   that   law   is  limited  to  defining  in  negative  fashion  what  conducts  the  subjects  of  the  law  have  to  refrain  from  in  order  not  to  infringe  on  others’  private  sphere  and  that  these  rules  be   universal.   Universality   is   in   turn   defined   as   a   negative   test   which   assesses  whether   rules  are   ‘end-­‐independent’,   i.e.   they  do  not  attempt   to  achieve  a   specific  outcome,   and   that   they   only   refer   to   facts   which   can   be   known   or   readily  ascertained  by  all  rule-­‐takers  (Hayek  2013[1982]:  205).  This  departure  from  Hart  is  

Page 20: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  20  

not   surprising   given  Hayek’s   aversion   for   legal  positivism.  While  Hayek   calls  Hart  the  most  effective  critique  of  older   forms  of   legal  positivism,   the   fact  remains   that  Hart’s   theory   is   still   a   positivist   one,   which   essentially   provides   a   purely   formal  definition  of  valid  law.  

Hayek’s  concept  of   law   is  at   the  same  time  broader  and  narrower   than  Hart’s  and  other  positivists’.  Narrower   in  the  sense  that   law  is  only  what  conforms  to  certain  substantive  criteria  of  legal  rules,  but  at  the  same  time  broader  in  that  the  sources  of  law  are  more  varied,  because   law  is  not  exclusively  defined  as  the  commands  that  emanate  from  a  sovereign.  Indeed,  Hayek  (2012[1982]:  69)  famously  held  that  ‘law  is  older  than  legislation’.  This  also  relates  to  the  question  of  enforcement:  While  he  holds   that   unenforced   rules   cannot   be   considered   law   (a   contrario  Deakin   et   al.  2015),   he   also   considers   –  with  Hart   –   that   the   existence   of   a   centrally   organised  system  of  sanctions  is  not  a  necessary  condition  for  the  existence  of  a  legal  system  (Hayek   2013[1982]:   200).   Thus,   rules   that   are   enforced   by   social   pressure   or  ostracism  can  be  considered  law  too,  as  long  as  the  rules  conform  to  the  criteria  of  valid  law  (negativity,  generality,  and  universality).  This  is  where  the  departure  from  Hart  emerges  the  most  clearly:   In  Hart’s  (1961)  view,   the  existence  of  a  system  of  secondary   rules   is   the  defining  element  distinguishing  a   system  of   law   from  more  archaic,   pre-­‐modern   types   of   customary   and   tribal   systems  of   social   rules.   Law   is  indeed  defined  as   the   union   of   primary   and   secondary   rules.   Hayek   (2013[1982]:  314-­‐5)   rejects   this   view,   stating   that   a   legal   system   does   not   necessarily   require  secondary   rules.   This   difference   with   Hart   becomes   understandable   when   we  consider  that  Hayek  essentially  equates  the  secondary  rules  with  ‘public  law’,  which  in   turn   is   –   according   to   him   –  what   legal   positivists   such   as  Kelsen   focus   on.  He  considers  that  only  a  very  narrow  range  of  secondary  rules  are  permissible  (those  aiming   at   enforcing   primary   rules),   while   most   secondary   rules   constitute   a  ‘corruption’  of  the  legal  system,  which  aim  at  imposing  state  policies  or  the  interests  of   certain   interest   groups   on   the   population.  Hayek   (2013[1982]:   211)   associates  the   latter   project  with   socialism   and   considers   that   “all   the   leading  modern   legal  positivists   have   been   public   lawyers   and   in   addition   usually   socialists.”   As  mentioned  above,  the  LFS  seems  to  follow  Hayek  in  his  rejection  of  legal  positivism  as  essentially  a  socialist  theory.  

Hayek   also   partly   follows   Dworkin   in   that   he   agrees   with   the   latter   that   legal  systems   are   more   than   a   ‘system   of   rules’   in   that   it   also   contains   less   explicit  elements   that   Dworkin   (1977)   calls   ‘principles’   and   Hayek   himself   calls  ‘unarticulated’   or   implicit   rules   (Hayek   2013[1982]:   315).   But   again,   Hayek’s  concept  of  law  is  narrower  than  Dworkin’s  in  the  sense  that  ultimately  it  boils  down  to   the  protection  of   individual  rights   through  the  enforcement  of  negative  rules  of  just  conduct.  Hayek  thus  explicitly  abolishes  the  distinction  between  duty-­‐imposing  rules   and   power-­‐conferring   rules:   ‘All   the   rules  which   state   the   conditions   under  which  property  can  be  acquired  and   transferred,  valid   contracts  or  wills  made,  or  other  ‘rights’  or  ‘powers’  acquired  and  lost,  serve  merely  to  define  the  conditions  on  

Page 21: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  21  

which  the  law  will  grant  the  protection  of  enforceable  rules  of  just  conduct’  (Hayek  2013[1982]:   201).   This   view   in   turn   derives   from   Hayek’s   narrow   conception   of  justice   as  merely   being   the   absence   of   injustice   (cf.   Gamble   2013)   and   it   explains  why  the  protective  function  of  law  becomes  the  main  function  of  law.  Rules  of  just  conduct  are  negative  in  that  they  do  not  normally  impose  positive  duties  on  people,  but   negative   duties   to   abstain   from   certain   conducts   (Hayek   2013[1982]:   202).  Indeed,   while   Hayek’s   account   of   liberty   relies   –   contrary   to   more   libertarian  accounts  –  very  strongly  on  law,  the  purpose  of  law  is  narrowly  defined  as  ‘merely  [serving]   to   prevent   conflict   and   to   facilitate   co-­‐operation   by   eliminating   some  sources  of  uncertainty’  (Hayek  2013[1982]:  204).    

Clearly,   the  LFS   largely  accepts  Hayek’s  account  notably   in  terms  of   the  protective  function   of   law,   its   limited   scope,   and   extent.   However,   on   some   points   Hayek’s  theory  of  law  may  not  be  a  good  basis  for  some  of  the  LFS  claims.  Most  importantly,  Hayek’s   notion   of   nomocracy   is   based   on   a   resolute   rejection   of   goal-­‐orientated  systems  (teleocracy).  Any  system  that  aims  at  achieving  certain  collective  goals  is,  in  Hayek’s  view,  subject  to  the  erroneous  naivety  of  ‘constructivism’  and  ‘pragmatism’.  He  criticises  legal  positivism  as  part  of  a  pragmatist  philosophy,  explicitly  referring  to  pragmatist  philosophers,  but  also  marginalist  economists:  "legal  positivism,   like  the  other  forms  of  constructivist  pragmatism  of  a  William  James  or  John  Dewey  or  Vilfredo   Pareto,   is   therefore   profoundly   antiliberal   in   the   original  meaning   of   the  word,   though   their   views   have   become   the   foundations   of   that   pseudo-­‐liberalism  which   in   the   course   of   the   last   generation   has   arrogated   the   name”   (Hayek  2011[1982]:  209).    Hayek’s   theory   rejects  hence  both   legal  positivism  –  whom  he  reproaches   its   absence  of   substantive  definition  of   law  –  but  also   the   teleological-­‐utilitarian   paradigm   according   to   which   law   can   be   used   to   achieve   certain  collective   goals.   The   LFS,   on   the   other   hand,   does   contain   quite   clear   utilitarian,  instrumentalist,  and  ultimately  teleological  claims,  notably  regarding  the  feasibility  and  desirability  of  legal  reform  (see  supra).  

Hayek  only  considers  law  to  be  real  law  that  is  historically  grown  and  emerged  from  a  process  of  evolutionary  progress  towards  efficient  rules  not  in  the  sense  of  their  outcome,  but  in  the  sense  of  creating  a  Great  Society  where  individuals’  liberties  are  optimally  protected  from  interference  by  others  and  by  the  state.  The  LFS  notion  of  efficiency   or   optimality   of   a   regulatory   regime   is   a   different   one.   For   instance,  Glaeser  &  Shleifer  2002[regulatory  state]  and  Djankov  et  al.  (2003)  consider  the  rise  of   the  statute-­‐based  regulatory  state   in   the  US  during   the  progressive  era  and   the  relative   decline   of   a   purely   court-­‐based   private   litigation   system   of   the   earlier  period,  as  an  efficient  choice  to  adapt  the  system  to  a  new,  more  complex  economic  and   social   environment.   This   can   be   seen   as   broadly   in   line   with   certain  functionalist-­‐evolutionary   theories   that   interpret   the   crisis  of   legal   formalism  as  a  result  of  the  increasing  complexity  of  society  (see  Teubner  1981).  Hayek  (1960)  on  the  other  hand  saw  this  evolution  not  as  an  efficient  choice,  but  rather  part  of   the  

Page 22: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  22  

regrettable  ‘decline  of  the  rule  of  law’,  due  to  the  rise  of  ‘social  constructivism’  and  socialism.  

In  short,  there  are  several  elements  in  Hayek’s  account  that  resonate  with  what  we  have  seen  so   far  as   central   elements  of   the  LFS  approach   to   law:   firstly,   the   claim  that  there  should  be  proximity  of  law  and  spontaneously  grown  systems  of  norms  of  a  society;  secondly,  the  substantive  definition  of  ‘good’  or  ‘valid’  law  in  terms  of  the  extent  to  which  it  is  conducive  to  economic  activity  and  market  exchanges.  Thirdly,  the  relative  narrow  definition  of  legal  rules  as  protections  of  individual  rights  from  both   other   individuals   and   the   state   (cf.   Djankov   et   al.   2003).   Fourthly,   the  implication   of   Hayek’s   theory   of   law   is   that   decentralised   political   systems   will  produce   better   outcomes   than   centralised   systems,   because   they   draw   more   on  local  knowledge  and  limit  state  interference  (cf.  especially  Glaeser  &  Shleifer  2002  [LO]  and  Mahoney  2001).  However,  there  are  also  aspects  regarding  which  the  LFS  seems   to   depart   from   Hayek,   notably   regarding   the   instrumental   use   of   law   to  achieve   specific   goals.   This   latter   point   is   also   related   to   the   question   the   paper  turns  to  now,  i.e.  how  exactly  does  law  change  economic  actors’  behaviour?  

2.5  How  does  law  impact  on  economic  actors’  behaviours?  

So  far  we  have  discussed  the  broad  issues  of  the  general  role  of  law  in  the  economy  and  the  question  of  the  quality  of  law.  However,  if  we  define  law  as  a  mechanism  of  social  control  that  works  by  influencing  actors’  behaviours,  it  would  seem  crucial  to  look  at  the  ways  in  which  law  achieves  changes  in  actors’  behaviours.  This  section  analysis  the  LFS  literature  regarding  this  aspect.    

The  main  observation  based  on  the  LFS  literature  is  that  it  has  not  much  to  say  at  all  about   this   point.   Indeed,  while   there   are   some  broad   references   to   the   incentives  that   law   creates   for   different   actors,   which   influences   their   behaviour   (cf.   LLSV  1997,   1998),   there   is   no   explicit   discussion   of   how   exactly   law   impacts   economic  actors.  One  important  point  to  note,  however,  is  the  very  strong  focus  of  much  of  the  LFS  on  the  enforcement  of   law.   Indeed,  Milhaupt  &  Pistor  (2008:  5)  summarises  –  certainly   in   a   somewhat   caricatural   way   –   the   LFS   as   being   summarised   in   the  simple   equation   “good   law   +   good   enforcement   =   good   economic   outcomes“.   The  idea  that  law  is  only  law  if  it  is  properly  enforce  was  present  in  the  LFS  studies  from  the  beginning.  Yet,  the  question  of  enforcement  has  progressively  taken  on  a  more  important   place.   Shleifer   (2005:   442)   even   calls   his   approach   to   regulation   an  “enforcement   theory   of   regulation”   in   the   sense   that   it   is   the   problem   of  enforcement   that  determines   the   choice  of   the  optimal   system  of   social   control  of  the   economy   (a   litigation-­‐based   court   system   or   public   regulation).   The   focus   on  enforcement   hints   at   an   important   underlying   assumption,   i.e.   that   law   is  mainly  being   followed   by   actors,   because   thy   fear   the   consequences   of   non-­‐compliance.  This   is   the   realist   and   strong   positivist   view   of   law,   that   is   sometimes   called   the  command-­‐  or  coercive  theory  of  law.  

Page 23: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  23  

The   LFS   has   indeed   increasingly   shifted   from   studying   the   content   and   nature   of  legal   rules   ‘on   the  books’   towards  asking  questions  about   the  application  of   these  rules  by  judges;  including  their  decisional  biases  (notably  Niblett  et  al.  2010).  This  ‘legal  realist  turn’  of  the  LFS  can  be  traced  back  at  least  to  2007  and  in  particular  to  the  joint  work  of  Andrei  Shleifer  with  Nicola  Gennaoile  (Gennaioli  &  Shleifer  2007a,  2007b,  but  also  Balas  et  al.  2009,  Niblett  et  al.  2010,  Gennaioli  et  al.  2014).  These  papers  explicitly  adopt  a  legal  realist  view,  which  argues  that  law  is  what  the  judge  says  it  is.  This  realist  stance  and  the  focus  on  law  enforcement  reveals  an  underlying  concept   of   law  which   realism   shares  with   strong   positivism,   that   the   only   reason  actors   follow   legal   rules,   is   because   legal   rules   are   commands   backed   up   with  threats  of  punishment.   If   the  punishment  were  not   credible,  we  would  not   expect  laws   to  matter   for   economic   actors.   Enforcement   through   courts   and   punishment  thus  becomes  a  crucial  element  of   laws.  Shleifer  &  Wolfenzon  (2002),  for  instance,  explicitly   refer   to   Becker’s   (1968)   model   of   ‘Crime   and   Punishment’   as   basis   for  their  economic  model.  They  define  the  quality  of  investor  protection  not  through  a  list   of   legal   shareholder   rights,   but   as   “likelihood   that   the   entrepreneur   is   caught  and   fined   for   expropriating   from   shareholders:”   (Shleifer   &  Wolfenzon   2002:   4).  This  statement  is  remarkably  close  to  Oliver  Wendell  Holmes’s  “prediction  theory  of  law”   according   to   which   law   should   be   defined   simply   as   the   prediction   of   how  courts   will   decide   and   what   the   likelihood   of   punishment   will   be.   This,   was,  according   to   Holmes   (1897)   the   point   of   view   that   the   ‘bad   man’   would   take  towards   the   law,   i.e.   all   the   ‘bad  man’   cares   about   when  making   decisions   is   the  likelihood   of   being   caught   when   infringing   the   law.   This   is   Holmes’s   legal   realist  stance,   but   it   also   comforms   with   Austin’s   positivist   idea   that   the   threat   of  punishment   is   a   defining   characteristic   of   law.   Defining   law   in   this   way   implies  hence  basing  it  on  a  pessimistic  anthropology  where  actors  do  not  follow  the  law  for  the  sake  of  following  it,  but  to  avoid  punishment.  It  is  in  this  respect  that  Holmes’s  view  seems  compatible  with  the  LFS’s  focus  on  the  fear  of  punishment.  Indeed,  the  underlying  conception  of  actors  as  a  homo  oeconomicus  whose  pursuit  of  maximal  utility   is  not   responsive   to  norms  and  duties,  but  only  by  cost-­‐benefit   calculations  and  incentives,  may  explain  why  the  LFS  is  quite  naturally  drawn  to  a  realist  view  of  law.  To  some  extent,  however,  this  contradicts  the  previously  established  proximity  of   the   LFS   with   Hayek’s   concept   of   law,   who   was   –   as   mentioned   above   –   very  critical  of  the  pragmatist  philosophy  to  which  O.  W.  Holmes  was  close.  

It  is  precisely  this  pessimistic  view  of  human  beings  that  have  led  the  LFS  scholars  to   increasingly   focus   on   the   role   of   judges.   Indeed,   contrary   to   Coasians   such   as  Stigler   (1964)   or   Easterbrook   and   Fischel   (1991)  who  were   optimistic   about   the  sufficiency  of  private  contracts  and  their  enforcement   in  courts  of   law  for  efficient  outcomes,  the  LFS  applies  the  homo  oeconomicus  model  to  judges  as  well  and  asks  ‘why  should  we  expect  judges  to  invest  the  necessary  effort  in  order  to  understand  complex  contracts?’  (see  Glaeser  et  al.  2001,  Glaeser  &  Shleifer  2002,  Shleifer  2005).  It  is  the  application  of  the  homo  oeconomicus  concept  to  not  just  litigants,  but  judges,  

Page 24: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  24  

that   leads  the  LFS  to  consider   the  role  of   judges  to  be  crucial  and  that  make  them  less   optimistic   about   courts   and   the   optimality   of   a   litigation-­‐based   systems   than  other  L&E  scholars  associated  with  the  Chicago  School  of  Economics  (Shleifer  2005;  Djankov  et  al.  2003b).  

In   this   respect,   the   realist   approach   adopted   in   recent   years   by   the   LFS   certainly  makes   a   contribution   to   the   literature   to   the   extent   that   it   challenges   more  optimistic  economic  accounts  of  the  role  of  courts  and  judge-­‐made  law,  which  may  overestimate  the  efficiency  of  such  systems.  However,  this  has  also  had  the  effect  of  diverting   attention   from   the   fact   that   law   does   not   impact   actors   only  when   it   is  being  enforced  in  a  court  of  law.  Indeed,  that  was  Hart’s  (1961)  famous  objection  to  Holmes’   bad  man   argument:   ‘Why’   –   he   asked   –   ‘should   not   law  be   equally   if   not  more  concerned  with  the  ‘puzzled  man’  or  ‘ignorant  man’  who  is  willing  to  do  what  is   required,   if   only  he   can  be   told  what   it   is?’   (Hart  2012[1961]:  40)   Indeed,  Hart  observed   that   the  majority   of   people   do   not   get   in   conflict  with   the   law   and  may  hold  the  view  that   it   is   their  duty   to  obey  the   law  for   the  sake  of  obeying  the   law,  rather  than  as  the  result  of  a  conscious  calculation  of  costs  and  benefits  associated  with  the   likelihood  of  punishment.  On  this  account,   it   is  by  no  means  obvious  that  the  threat  of  punishment  and  the  likelihood  of  enforcement  are  the  only  or  even  the  main   mechanism   through   which   law   deploys   its   effect   on   the   economy.   We   will  come  back  to  this  criticism  of  the  command  theory  of  law  in  section  3.    

In   sum   then,   while   the   LFS   diverges   from   other   branches   of   neo-­‐institutionalist  economics  in  the  importance  it  ascribes  to  laws  and  regulations,  very  few  papers  in  the   LFS   tradition   explicitly   state   what   concept   of   law   the   studies   are   based   on.  Nevertheless,   a   few   regularities   emerge   from   the   above   review   of   the   core  contributions   to   this   literature.  Firstly,   the  LFS  rejects   legal  positivism   in   terms  of  the  validity  of   laws  as   emanating  purely   from   the  will   of   a   sovereign.   Instead,   the  LFS  adheres  to  the  view  that  laws  need  to  fulfil  certain  substantive  criteria  for  it  to  be  qualified  as  a  ‘good’  or  ‘quality’  law.  Conversely,  not  everything  that  is  enshrined  in  the  law  can  be  considered  as  proper  legal  rules.  This  hints  at  a  non-­‐positivist  view  of  law,  which  can  most  closely  be  associated  with  a  Hayekian  evolutionary-­‐,  rather  than  a  natural  law  view.5  ‘Good  law’  lives  up  to  the  criteria  of  protecting  individual  (property)  rights,  favouring  trade,  but  also  is  close  to  a  community’s  own  standards.    

At  the  same,  time  in  terms  of  the  way  in  which  law  affects  economic  actors,  the  LFS  does  adopt  a  view  that  seems  close  to  Austinian  positivism,  or  Holmseian  realism,  that  defines  laws  as  orders  backed  up  by  the  threat  of  punishment  or  as  probability  of  punishment.  Indeed,  fear  for  punishment  and  the  incentives  thus  created  seem  to  be   the   only   reason   why   actors   in   the   LFS   conception   would   obey   the   law.   This  makes  the  LFS  conception  of  law  compatible  with  modern  economic  theories  about  rationality  and  motivation,  in  particular  with  Becker’s  (1968)  work.                                                                                                                              5  Hayek  saw  indeed  his  spontaneous  evolution  theory  of  law  as  a  third  way  of  explaining  law  beyond  positivism  and  natural  law  doctrines  (Hayek  2013[1982]:  223).  

Page 25: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  25  

Secondly,  despite   these  quite   clear  positions  on  positivism  and  realism,   the  LFS   is  much   less   clear   on   the   precise  way   in  which   law  deploys   its   impact   on   economic  outcomes.   In   the  earlier  LFS  studies,   this  question   is   largely   treated   implicitly  and  reduced  to  questions  of  incentives  created  by  effective  protection  of  property  rights  or  the  absence  thereof.  Well-­‐protected  property  rights  create  positive  incentives  to  invest,  lack  of  protection  creates  negative  incentives  to  abstain  from  investing.  Very  little  is  said  about  how  law  affects  the  main  target  of  legal  rules  however  –  Holmes’s  proverbial   ‘bad  man’,  or  the   ‘insiders’  who  are  the  ones  doing  the  expropriating  in  the   LFS   framework.   Here   the   LFS   has   strongly   focused   on   the   question   of  effectiveness   of   law   enforcement   and   the   incentives   this   creates   for   potential  wrongdoers  in  terms  of  fear  for  punishment.    

Judicial   decision-­‐making   is   indeed   a   focal   point   of   analysis   and   the   application  by  judges  of  broad  legal  principles,  as  opposed  to  ‘bright-­‐line  legal  rules’,  is  considered  a  key  advantage  of  common  law  systems  over  civil  law  ones.  Increasingly,  however,  the  LFS  has  moved   to  a  more  pessimistic,   explicitly   legal   realist,  understanding  of  the   role   of   courts   that   analysis   judicial   decisions   in   similar   terms   as   any   other  opportunistic,  selfish  actor  using  the  tools  of  modern  economic  theories  of  rational  behaviours.  This  has  led  the  LFS  to  challenge  more  optimistic  accounts  of  courts.  It  has   also   led   the   LFS   to   adopt   an   adversarial   view   of   law,  where   it   is   assumed   to  deploy   its   effect  main   in   cases  where   it   is   enacted   through   lawsuits.  Various   legal  scholars,  however,  have  pointed  out  that  law  suits  and  punishment  are  law’s  plan  B  (Greene  2012,  2015),  while  plan  A  is  to  rely  on  people  following  the  low  for  reasons  other  than  (the  threat  of)  punishment.  Such  less  dramatic  functions  of  law,  however,  are  largely  neglected  by  the  LFS.  

Finally,  it  should  be  noted  that  in  a  parallel  development  of  the  LFS,  there  has  been  a  considerable   shift   away   from   the   focus   on   law   as   key   explanatory   variable.   This  change  can  be  illustrated  in  the  various  conceptions  of  institutions  that  can  be  found  in  the  LFS  literature.  Early  work  often  referred  to  North  (1981,  1991)  definition  of  institutions  as  humanly  designed  constraints  and  ‘rules  of  the  game’.  In  these  early  studies,  laws  were  essentially  equated  with  institutions.  Over  time,  however,  and  to  an  important  part  driven  by  the  increasing  importance  of  the  ‘legal  origin’  variable,  the  LFST  started  to  use  the  term  institution  in  quite  a  different  way.  For  one,  certain  studies  turned  to  use  the  term  ‘regulation’  instead  of  laws,  which  may  imply  that  the  type  of   ‘rules’  under  examination  has  broadened  from  legislature-­‐  and  judge-­‐made  law  to  include  administrative  acts  made  by  ‘governments’  and  regulatory  agencies.  This   may   also   explain   why   the   object   of   investigation   has   increasingly   become  broader   moving   from   company   law   narrowly   defined,   to   ‘regulation’   and   then  policies  and   the  characteristics  of   the  polity.  This   change  has,   in   turn,   led   to  quite  strong  qualification  of  the  initial  claims  about  the  importance  of  institutional  factors  in  determining  economic  outcomes.  Thus,  Glaeser  et  al.  (2004)  argue  that  policies  of  investment  in  human  capital  are  a  more  important  driver  of  economic  development  than   institutions.   Indeed   ‘good’   policies   are   often   adapted   by   dictatorial   regimes,  

Page 26: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  26  

and  ‘good  institutions’  follow  afterwards  (Glaeser  et  al.  2004:  271).  More  generally,  the   focus   on   and   redefinition   of   ‘legal   origin’   has   led   to   a   shift   away   from   the  substantive  nature  of  the  legal  rules  under  investigation  towards  more  fundamental  features   of   different   countries’   legal   and   political   systems.   Legal   origin   was   first  simply  meant   to  mean   the   ‘historical   grounding’   of   a   legal   system   in   one   of   four  mother   systems.  But   it   then  became  a  proxy   for   a   ‘regulatory   style’   and  a   style  of  social   control   over   economic   life   and   other   areas.   At   one   stage,   this   was   simply  equated   with   the   extent   of   state   intervention   in   different   countries,   and   the  argument   soon   became   that   Anglo-­‐Saxon   countries   are   inherently   superior   to  others.  But  more  recent  studies  attempted  to  elucidate  the  source  of  this  superiority  more  concretely  by  investigating  constitutional  features  of  different  countries,  most  notably  judicial  independence  and  constitutional  review  (La  Porta  et  al.  2004).  Here,  then,   the   focus  has   shifted  quite   radically   from   the   content  of   the   laws  protecting  rights   in   the   1990s   to   features   of   the   political   system,   as   defined   by   a   country’s  constitution.   One   could   argue,   therefore,   that  more   recent   scholarship   in   the   LFS  tradition  has  very  little  to  do  with  law  indeed.  

This   latter   development   is   regrettable,   because   it   attempts   to   avoid   difficult  questions   raised   by   the   initially   confident   statement   “law   matters!”   not   by  attempting   to   answer   the   question   “how   does   law   matter?”,   but   by   avoiding   the  debate   altogether,   shifting   the   focus   onto  more   fundamental   features   of   different  countries.  This  paper  attempts   to  show   it   is  worthwhile   to  persist   in   investigating  whether/how  law  matters.  The  next  section  develops  a  framework  that  can  enrich  the  LFS  concept  of  law  in  order  to  make  the  theory  both  analytically  and  empirically  stronger.  

 

3.  What  Links  Law  to  Practices?  A  Comprehensive  Framework  for  the  Analysis  of  Law  and  the  Economy  

The  extensive   literature   review  revealed   that   the  LFS   follows   legal  positivism  and  realism   regarding   the   key   question   of   how   law   deploys   its   impact   on   economic  activity.  While  the  question  is  not  often  explicitly  addressed  in  the  LFS  literature,  it  seems  clear  that  the  focus  is  on  the  creation  of  negative  incentives  for  wrongdoers  via  the  threat  of  punishment.  This  view  comes  close  to  the  ‘coercive  view’  of  law  and  also  explains  the  LFS’s  strong  focus  on  judge-­‐made  law  and  the  role  of  courts.    

This  section  turns  to  discussing  the  coercive  view  of  law  in  more  detail  in  order  to  present  various  objections  and  to  further  develop  the  conceptual  link  between  law  and  economic  activity/behaviours  based  on  alternative  views.  

3.1.  Threat,  Coercion,  and  Punishment:  Law’s  “plan  A”  or  “plan  B”?  

Page 27: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  27  

The  command-­‐,   imperative-­‐  or  coercive   theory  of   law   is  primarily  associated  with  John  Austin,  Hans  Kelsen,  and  other  so-­‐called  ‘strong  legal  positivists’,  but  it  is  also  close   to   some   realist   accounts.   The   focus   is   on   the   coercive   effect   of   law,   as   a  command   issued  by  a   sovereign  and  enforced   through   (the   threat  of)  punishment  (see   Green   2012,   Schauer   2014).   Similarly,   the   legal   realist   Oliver   W.   Holmes  famously  used  the  notion  of  the  ‘bad  man’,  as  the  addressee  of  laws  and  considered  that  his   incentives   to   avoid   ‘doing  bad’  derived   from   fear  of   costs   associated  with  doing  so  (Green  2012:  xxxi).  Holmes  (1897:  459)  wrote:    

‘If  you  want  to  know  the  law  and  nothing  else,  you  must  look  at  it  as  a  bad  man,  who  cares  only  for  the  material  consequences  which  such  knowledge  enables  him  to  predict.’  

The  coercive  view  of  law  has  been  subject  to  a  great  deal  of  criticism  over  the  years.  Already  Hart  (1961)  argued  that  the  fear  of  punishment  was  not  the  reason  why  the  average  citizen  obeys  the  law.  Indeed,  officials  and  law-­‐abiding  citizens  do  so  out  of  a   moral   conviction   that   laws   ought   to   be   obeyed   more   than   for   fear   of   negative  consequences.   The   debate   has   not   abated   until   today.   In   a   recent   book-­‐length  defence  of   the  coercive  view,  Schauer  (2014)  accuses  authors  such  as  Hart  (1961)  and   Green   (2012)   to   marginalise   the   inherently   coercive   nature   of   law.   Very  schematically,   Schauer   (2014)  argues   that   the  use  or   threat  of   coercion  or   force  –  the   two   terms   are   used   interchangeably   –   is  what  makes   law   achieve   its   primary  purpose,   which   is   to   guide   action   by   making   us   do   things   that   we   would   not  otherwise   do.   Green   (2015)   rejects   this   view   arguing   that   ‘the   force   of   law’   is  certainly   to  an   important  extent  grounded   in   the  use  of   coercion,  but  also  –   if  not  more  –   in   the   imposition  of  duties   and   the  exercise  of  power.  While   coercion  and  power  need  to  be  distinguished  from  each  other,  they  are  also  different  from  duties,  which  are  not  based  on  the  use  or  threat  of  physical  force  or  on  influence  through  power,  but  on  the  creation  of  normative  expectations  to  which  subjects  are  expected  to   conform   (Green   2015:   3).   Green   (2015)   considers   indeed   that   the   creation   of  normative  duties  –  not  coercion  or  power  –  is  the  primary  way  in  which  law  guides  subjects’   actions,   or   –   in   Green’s   (2015:7)   words   –   it   is   law’s   ‘Plan   A’.   Hart,   too  believed  that  ‘[t]he  principal  functions  of  the  law  as  a  means  of  social  control  are  not  to   be   seen   in   private   litigation   or   prosecutions,   which   represent   vital   but   still  ancillary  provisions  for  the  failures  of  the  system.  It  is  to  be  seen  in  the  diverse  ways  in  which   the   law   is   used   to   control,   to   guide,   and   to   plan   life   out   of   court’   (Hart  [1961]2012:  40;  emphasis  added).  On  this  view,  then,   the  normative  aspect  of   law  (imposing  a  duty  and  motivating  actors  to  follow  a  norm)  is  more  important  than  its  coercive   function   (threatening  actors  with   the  use  of   sanctions,   including  physical  force).  Green's  (2015)  concept  of  law  like  Hart’s  (1961)  implies  that  law  is  'coercive  if  necessary,  but  not  necessarily  coercive'.  

The  notion  of  moral  duties   imposed  by   legal   rules   raises  another   important   issue,  i.e.  the  one  of  what  rules  a  legal  system  is  made  up  of.  Green  (2015:  6)  acknowledges  

Page 28: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  28  

that   law   is   not   composed   on   duty-­‐imposing   rules   alone,   but   ‘will   also   have   other  sorts  of   rules,   including   rules   that   confer   rights,   grant  permissions,   create  powers  and   so   forth’.   Yet,   according   to   Green   (2015)   they   do   constitute   the   fundamental  unit  of  a  legal  system,  because  all  legal  rules  can  ultimately  be  expressed  in  terms  of  duties.   Thus,   permissions   are   rules   about   the   cancellation   of   a   duty;   powers   are  rules  about  the  capacity  to  create,  waive,  or  modify  duties.  

Green’s  focus  on  duties  is  broadly  in  line  with  legal  positivism  whose  view  that  legal  rules  are  ‘commands’  can  be  seen  as  compatible  with  the  duty-­‐imposing  legal  rules.  The   contrast   is   starker   here   with   Hayek’s   assertion   that   ‘real   law’   is   defined   by  negative  norms  of  proper  conduct.  Indeed,  Hayek  (1982)  stressed  the  unity  of  true  legal  rules,  as  being  merely  negative  in  nature,  i.e.  they  protect  individuals’  rights  by  prohibiting   others   from   infringing   on   them.   As   such,   they   do   not   impose   any  particular  duty  beyond  abstaining  from  certain  actions.  

Yet,   Green’s   duty-­‐imposing   conception   of   legal   rules   does   contrast   with   legal  positivism  not  because  of  the  notion  of  duty  as  such,  but  in  terms  of  the  motivation  for  subjects   to   follow  rules.  The  command   theory  views  duties  as  orders  either   to  judges  about  the  conditional  use  of  coercion  (‘punish  if  a  person  does/does  not  do  X’)  (as  per  Kelsen),  or  to  subjects  directly  (as  per  Holmes  or  Austin).  In  either  case,  the  ultimate  motivation  has  to  do  with  the  fear  of  sanction,  while  Green’s  conception  –   following  Hart   –   focuses   on  moral   behaviours   of   the   addressees   of   law.   Indeed,  Kelsen   even   famously   declared   that   enabling   or   power-­‐conferring   rules   are   only  fragments  of   rules,  and   that  properly  understood,  duty-­‐imposing  rules   too  rely  on  the  threat  of  force  (Green  2015:  9).  

But  even   this  view  of   law  being  composed  of  both  negative  rules  as  well  as  moral  duty-­‐imposing   rules   may   be   too   narrow.   Indeed,   Hart   (1961)   himself   criticised  Austin   for   only   considering   the   duty-­‐imposing   aspect   of   law,   which   may   be   an  accurate   description   of   criminal   law,   but   not   necessarily   other   types   of   law.  According   to   Hart   (1961),   Austin   forgets   the   power-­‐conferring   aspects   of   law,  whose   primary   effect   on   actors   is   not   to   impose   restrictions   to   their   behaviour  under  the  threat  of  sanctions,  but  to  enable  actors  to  do  certain  things  they  would  not  be  able   to  do  without   the   law.  These   include   for   instance,  entering  a  contract,  establishing   a   company,   issuing   certain   types   of   securities   etc.   Therefore,   rather  than  a  purely  constraining  force,   law  also  has  enabling  and  coordinating  effects  on  economic   actors   by   providing   not   so  much   prohibitions   but   guidelines   as   to   how  certain  activities  should  be  undertaken  (Milhaupt  &  Pistor  2008).  In  this  sense,  law  has   a   constitutive   effect:   Like   the   rules   of   football   do  not   just   regulate   the   corner  kick,   but   actually   create   it   in   the   first   place,   so   law   does   not   just   regulate   the  economic  ‘game’,  but  in  actual  fact  fundamentally  shapes  the  economy  through  the  rules   and   institutions   that   it   puts   at   actors’   disposal   (Deakin   et   al.   2015,   Schauer  2009).6  

                                                                                                                         6  The  neglect  of  law’s  enabling  effect,  has  a  direct  correspondence  in  institutional  scholarship  more  broadly:  Jackson  and  Deeg  (2008)  observe  that  much  of  institutional  scholarship  in  the  management  

Page 29: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  29  

Nevertheless,  advocates  of  the  coercive  view  argue  that  even  enabling  rules  have  a  coercive   impact   on   the   subjects   of   law   in   the   sense   that   they   create   a   legal  institution   that  subjects  are  now  expected   to  use   instead  of  non-­‐legal  alternatives.  The  non-­‐legal   alternatives  are   thus   crowded  out   in   coercive   fashion  by   the   law   in  question  (Schauer  2014;  a  contrario  Green  2015).    

Schauer’s  (2014)  criticism  of  Hart  and  Green  is  essentially  a  pragmatist  one,  which  crucially  hinges  on  the  notion  that  the  conceptual  statement  that  law  may  indeed  –  theoretically  –  be  able  to  function  without  the  use  of  coercion,  human  nature  is  such  that  in  practice  no  legal  system  in  the  world  can  dispense  of  the  coercive  side  of  law.  Green  (2015)  convincingly  shows  that  neither  himself  nor  Hart  would  contest  that  claim,  but  contrary   to  Schauer,   they  consider   that   the  conceptual  analysis  of   law’s  nature   is   important.   Schauer   (2014)   on   the   other   hand   considers   in   a   true  pragmatist’s  fashion  that  all  that  matters  is  what  law  is  like  in  reality,  not  what  it  is  like   in   theory.   In   Green’s   (2015:   24)   summary   of   Schauer’s   position   ‘Conceptual  truths   about   law,   if   there   are   any,   matter   less   than   contingent,   empirical  truths  about   the   law  we  have.'  Again,  Schauer’s  conception   is  very  close   to  Holmes’s  and  other   legal   realists’   view.  What   matters   to   the   pragmatist   is   what   the   judges   do,  which   implies   that   law  becomes  merely  a  prediction  of   the  use  of   coercion  by   the  judge  and  a  corresponding  evaluation  by  the  subject  –  the  bad  man  –  of  the  material  consequences  of  infractions.    

The   proximity   of   the   realist   and   ultimately   pragmatic   conception   of   law   with  modern  day  economics,  both  regarding  its  underlying  anthropology  (compare  ‘bad  man’   and   homo   oeconomicus)   and   the   focus   on   empirical   prediction   as   main  criterion  for  validity  (cf.  Schnyder  2012CGI)   is  striking.  The  coercive  view  reduces  obedience  essentially  to  an  economic  matter.  Green  (2015:  7)  states  that  ‘sanctions  are   subject   to   the   ordinary   economy   of   threats,   costs   against   benefits’   and   lack  therefore   the   ‘binding,   categorical   force’   that   duties   claim   to   have.   As   a   result,  coercive   sanctions   cannot   explain   the  normative   character   of   law.  Conversely,   the  purely  economic  nature  of  ‘motivation  by  threat’  may  explain  the  focus  on  coercion  and   on   the   protective   function   that   the   LFS   provides:   given   that   homo   sapiens   is  defined  as  a  homo  oeconomicus,  any  impact  of  law  that  relies  on  an  appeal  to  actors’  moral,  emotional,  or   social   sense  does  not  make  sense   in   this   framework.  Modern  economic   theory   in   the   wake   of   the   rise   of   the   Chicago   School   and   the   homo  oeconomicus   model   of   human   behaviour,   turned   the   behaviour   of   Holmes’s   ‘bad  man’  –  a  concept  that  also  presupposed  the  existence  of  the  ‘good  man’  –  from  the  exception  into  the  norm  of  human  behaviour.  Deception,  cheating,  lying  become  the  natural  behaviours  not  behaviours  associated  with  ‘bad  people’  who  should  be  the  law’s   main   concern   (see   Williamson   1985).   This   one-­‐dimensional   anthropology,  focused  on  the  deceitful  nature  of  human  beings,  may  be  the  main  explanation  for  the   narrow   focus   of   LFS   on   the   fear   of   punishment   and   the   complete   absence   of  discussion   of   other   functions   of   law.   Indeed,   as   Coffee   (2001:   2165)   puts   it:   “In   a  world  in  which  all  actors  are  assumed  to  be  amoral  and  to  be  deterred  only  by  the  prospect  of  sanctions,  this  [i.e.  the  focus  on  positive  law  and  its  enforcement]  might  exhaust  the  possible  explanations  [of  human  behaviour]”.  

                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                         tradition  sees  institutions  purely  as  a  constraints  on  economic  actors,  neglecting,  thus,  the  enabling  effect  some  institutions  can  have  on  actors.  

Page 30: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  30  

Legal   theorists   who   do   not   buy   into   the   model   of   homo   oeconomicus,   however  suggest  that  the  ‘coercive  function’  of  law  with  its  focus  on  constraints  and  sanctions  may  be   too   limitative   to  explain   the  effect   that   law  has  on  economic  activity.  How  then  would   we   expect   law   to  matter   for   economic   activity?   Two   answers   to   this  question   can   be   found   in   the   literature:   firstly,   incentives   and   secondly   the  expressive  function  of  law.  Indeed,  Green  (2012:  xxxii)  states  that  ‘[c]oercion  is  the  hard   edge   of   the   law’s   power;   the   incentivizing   and   expressive   character   of   legal  norms  belongs  to  its  soft  edge.’  

Regarding  the  first  one  of  these  two  additional  mechanisms  –   incentives  –  the  LFS  conceptualisation  of  law  does  acknowledge  their  importance,  although  they  are  only  considered  in  relation  with  the  threat  of  coercion.  Thus,  as  mentioned  in  section  2,  the   link   between   legal   shareholder   protection   and   ownership   concentration   is  explicitly   conceptualised   based   on   incentives:   Increasing   protection   of   property  rights  means   that   investors   do   not   have   to   fear   expropriation   by   insiders,   which  incentivises   shareholders   to   abandon   large   controlling   stakes   in   favour   of   more  diversified  portfolios  with  minority  positions   in  many  firms.  Also,   the  more  recent  LFS  studies  –   in  particular   those   in   the   legal  realist  paradigm  –  closely   look  at   the  incentives   that   judges   have   to   either   favour   shareholders   or   their   own   career  interests  (Glaeser  et  al.  2001).   Incentives  do  come  in  as  a  behavioural  mechanism,  based  on  the  economic  analysis  of  human  behaviour.  But  the  LFS  does  not  consider  incentives   as   a   direct   means   for   law   to   influence   behaviours.   Indeed,   law   can  actively  create  incentives  –  other  than  threat  of  punishment  –,  e.g.  by  increasing  the  costs   of   certain   types   of   behaviours   through   legal   rules   (e.g.   smoking)   (cf.   Green  2012).   LFS   neglects   this   aspect   of   law.   Here,   however,   I   will   focus   on   another  omission,  which  is  the  ‘expressive  character  of  legal  norms’.      

3.2  The  expressive  and  normative  view  of  law  

Law’s  effect  on  actors  may  to  an  important  degree  stem  from  the  fact  that  it  signals  to   the   addressees   of   law  what   appropriate   behaviour   is.   This   hints   at   the   crucial  question  of  the  moral  aspects  of  legal  rules  and  the  link  between  law  and  morality.      The   relationship   between   law   and  morality   has   been   central   to  many   debates   in  legal  theory.  A  key  issue  that  has  opposed  legal  positivists  to  other  legal  theories  is  whether  laws  do  or  should  reflect  certain  moral  norms  to  be  considered  valid.  Lon  Fuller  (1964)  famously  argued  against  Hart’s  positivism,  that  law  needed  to  follow  certain   –   procedural   –   principles   of   ‘internal   morality’   in   order   to   be   considered  valid   law.  Hart   (1961),   on   the   other   hand,   saw   law   and  morals   as   rather   distinct,  although  his  positivism  does  allow  for  moral  norms  to  be  built  in  the  legal  system,  as  the  fundament  of   the  so  called  Rule  of  Recognition  upon  which  a   legal  system’s  validity  is  based.  By  and  large  though,  law  and  morals  are  not  necessarily  equal  and  legality   can   –   according   to   Hart   –   indeed   be   used   for   immoral   purposes   (Green  2008).    The  debate  about  the  separation  of   law  and  morals  has  also  a  more  practical  side,  which   was   mentioned   above:   i.e.   to   what   extent   law   should   correspond   with   a  

Page 31: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  31  

society’s  moral  rules  in  order  to  facilitate  rule-­‐following  and  enforcement.  The  LFS  seems   to   favour   a   close   correspondence   between   the   two.   This   corresponds  with  certain  theories  in  legal  scholarship,  which  considers  that  the   ‘moral  credibility’  of  law  is  enhanced  when  it  closely  corresponds  with  a  society’s  moral  standards.  This  in   turn   is   important   for   law   to   acquire   what   Green   (2013)   calls   a   ‘Weberian  legitimicay’  of  being  accepted  as  binding.    However,   there   is   an   additional   dimension   to   the   question   of   law   and   morality,  which  becomes   relevant   here,   as   it   specifies   an   additional   channel   through  which  law  influences  economic  activity.  This  additional  channel  is  precisely  the  expressive  function   of   law   and   relates   to   the   question   whether   law   can   (and   should)   shape  social  morality.  Some  legal  theorists  have  indeed  asked  the  opposite  question  to  the  one  ‘to  what  extent  should  law  reflect  a  society’s  morality?’  namely  ‘to  what  extent  can  and  should   law  shape  the  morality  of  a  society.’  Green  (2013)  argues  that   law  impacts   not   just   people’s   incentives,   but   also   how   they   perceive   and   normatively  evaluate   different   behaviours.   At   first   glance,   this   contradicts   more   classical  definitions   of   morality,   such   as   the   one   of   H.   L.   A.   Hart   (1961),   which   explicitly  distinguishes  morality  from  law  by  the  fact  that  it  is  ‘immune’,  to  deliberate  changed  (cf.  Green  2013:  477).  However,  while  Green  (2013)  accepts  the  view  that  there  are  in  the  domain  of  morality  no  rules  for  changing  the  rules  –  Hart’s  ‘secondary  rules’  the  existence  of  which  define  a  legal  system  –,  he  considers  that  intentional  actions  –  such   as   legislation   –   can   gradually   shift   norms   or   ‘help   create   new   meanings   of  certain   acts’   (p.483).   The   prime   example   Green   provides   is   the   criminalisation   of  certain  acts.  In  his  own  terms:    

 "The  creation  of  crimes  normally  aims  to  make  people  accept,  or  to  take  more  seriously   than   they  already  do,   the   idea   that   the  relevant  delict   is  not  merely  prohibited  or  officially  disapproved,  but  wrong.  (Green  2013:  483).    

 Conversely,   decriminalisation   of   certain   acts   –   e.g.   homosexual   relationships   –   is  likely   to   lead   to   changes   in   a   society’s   attitudes   towards   such   acts:   "It   is   widely  conceded   that   criminalization   can   stigmatize   an   activity;   why   doubt   that  decriminalization  can  do  the  opposite?"  (Green  2013:  486).  Similarly,  Robinson  and  Darley  (2007:  28)  argue  based  on  empirical  research  that  “[c]riminal  law  is  perhaps  unique   in   its   ability   to   inform,   shape,   and   reinforce   social   and  moral   norms   on   a  society-­‐wide   level."  On   this   account   then,   law   may   be   able   to   influence   the   way  people   behave   not   just   through   the   threats   it  makes   or   through   the   incentives   it  creates,  but  also  through  the  moral  norms  of  appropriatness  of  certain  acts   that   it  signals.    To  be  sure,  this  may  be  a  position  that  is  difficult  to  accept  for  scholars  who  ground  their   understanding   of   human   behaviour   in   a   purely   rationalistic   model   of   man.  Indeed,  Green  (2013:  481)  states  that   '[t]he   idea  that   law  might  change  the  hearts  and  minds   of   its   subjects,   and   not  merely   incentivize   their   conduct,   is   sometimes  met   with   derision’7   (2013:   481).   And   it   would   seem   that   the   LFS   is   sufficiently  

                                                                                                                         7  He  adds,  ‘[o]r  at  any  rate  it  is  when  people  have  in  mind  changes  for  the  better;  is  seems  easier  for  them  to  believe  that  law  can  change  attitudes  for  the  worse.)'  (2013:  481).  

Page 32: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  32  

strongly  grounded  in  the  homo  oeconomicus  model  of  human  nature  to  explain  why  no  mechanisms  beyond  punishment  and  incentives  are  considered  to  explain  law’s  impact  on  economic  actors.  Yet,   as  Coffee   (2001:  2165)   stated   “But   an  alternative  set   of   explanations   [to   explaining   differences   in   actors’   behaviour   through  differences   in   legal   incentives   and   enforcement]   emerges   if  we   postulate   that   the  principal   actors   in   corporate   governance   may   internalize   norms   and   act   in  accordance  with  them.”  One  such  alternative  explanation  is  precisely  that  law  may  signal  what  appropriate  behaviour  is  and  that  actors  should  conform  with  it.  This  is  what   Sunstein   (1996)   called   the   expressive   function   of   law.   Milhaupt   &   Pistor  (2008:   34)   contend   that   “[o]ften,   the   signals   sent   by   law  may   be  more   potent   or  novel  than  the  legal  provisions  themselves”.    An   important   implication   of   this   view   is   that   the   law  may   deploy   its   effect   quite  independently  of  the  question  whether  the  law  is  actually  enforced  or  not  (Deakin  et  al.   2015).  This   effect  may   explain,   for   instance,  why   certain   types  of   international  law  are  adopted  although  it  is  well  known  from  the  beginning  that  enforcement  will  depend   on   states   being  willing   to   forgo   some   of   their   sovereignty.   In   spite   of   the  limited  means  of  enforcement,  international  law  may  still  develop  an  effect  merely  by  signalling   to  actors  what  sorts  of  behaviours  are  acceptable.  The  addressees  of  international  law  may  adapt  their  behaviours  not  for  fear  of  punishment  –  as  per  the  command  theory  of   law  –  but  out  of  a  sense  of  moral  obligation  or  a  concern  with  legitimacy.   This   perspective   can   be   called   the   ‘normative-­‐‘,   ‘expressive-­‐‘,   or  ‘signalling   function  of   law’.   It   is   increasingly  well  supported  by  empirical  evidence  notably  from  experimental  research.    4.  Empirical  Implications:  Investigating  law  and  economic  outcomes  

The  preceding  discussion  shows  that  the  link  between  law  and  economic  outcomes  may  be  far  more  complex  than  the  LFS  suggests.  Law  can  perform  various  functions  and   hence   be   associated   with   various   different   ways   of   how   it   affects   firm-­‐level  practices   and   through   them   overall   economic   outcomes.   Moreover,   the   different  purposes  and  functions  of  law  are  not  mutually  exclusive,  but  the  same  law  can  have  several  or  all  of  these  effects  at  the  same  time  (Green  2012,  Milhaupt  &  Pistor  2008).    

What   does   appear   clearly,   however,   is   that   the   different   functions   of   law   and  channels  through  which  they  affect  firm  behaviours  have  far-­‐reaching  implications  for  empirical  research  in  this  area.  If  the  expected  mechanism  that  links  law  to  firm-­‐level  outcomes  is  fear  for  punishment,  we  would  have  different  hypotheses  of  how  companies   react   to   a   new   law   than   if   the   main   mechanism   were   the   normative  signals   emanating   from   the   law.   This   section   briefly   sketches   out   some   of   the  implications   of   the   discussion   and   develops   several   propositions   to   refine   the  investigating   into   the   link   between   law   and   corporate   governance   in   empirical  research.    

There  may  be  fundamentally  new  ways  of  investigating  the  link  between  company  law   and   corporate   governance   outcomes   in   order   to   test   for   some   of   the  complexities   of   the   complexities   of   the   theoretical   relationships   between   the   two.  

Page 33: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  33  

For   instance,   the   discussion   of   the   normative   view   and   the   link   between   legal  change  and  changes  in  moral  norms  may  best  be  investigated  based  on  individual-­‐level  surveys  of  normative  attitudes   towards  certain  practices  or  similar  methods.  Here,  we  limit  the  discussion  to  the  most  widely  used  kind  of  data  in  this  field,   i.e.  country-­‐level   measures   of   the   legal   environment   (such   as   LLSV’s   ADRI)   and  country-­‐   or   firm-­‐level  measures   of   corporate   governance   outcomes   and  practices.  This  allows  us  to  derive  concrete  testable  hypotheses  for  empirical  research.  

The   first  concept  of   law  discussed  above  was   the  command  theory,  which  expects  companies  to  react  to  legal  change  for  fear  of  judicial  repercussions,  i.e.  lawsuits  and  fines.   This   view   would   postulate   a   relative   limited   impact   of   law   on   corporate  practices,   i.e.  only  when  a  specific  practice   is  directly   targeted  by   the   legal  change  would  we  expect  a  company  to  react.  Consequently,  if  this  were  the  only,  or  even  the  main  effect  of   legal  rules  on  corporate  practices,  empirical  studies  should  focus  on  investigating   the   direct   correspondence   between   legal   variables   and   firm-­‐level  variables,  e.g.   the  prohibition  of  dual  class  shares   in  the   law  and  their  existence  at  firm   level.   A   longitudinal   study   could   then   investigate  whether   a   given   corporate  practice  changed  before  or  after  the  relevant  legal  rule  changed,  which  would  allow  it   to   draw   conclusions   regarding   the   impact   of   law   on   corporate   governance  practices.   Surprisingly,   however,   very   few   studies   adopt   this   empirical   strategy  corresponding   to   their   implicit   conceptualisation   of   legal   rules,   as   coercive   and  authoritative  orders.  LLSV’s  (e.g.  1997)  studies  use  the  legal  measure  as  a  broader  proxy   for   the   legal   environment   and   are   interested   in   broader   outcome   variables  (ownership   structures)   rather   than   corresponding   mechanisms   at   the   firm-­‐level.  Other   studies   who   investigate   the   role   of   law   in   corporate   governance   too   use  LLSV’s   measure   without   investigating   the   corresponding   corporate   governance  practices   at   the   firm   level,   but   unrelated   features   of   a   company’s   corporate  governance  system.    

As  an  example,  Cuomo  et  al.  (2012)  in  a  study  investigating  explicitly  the  impact  of  legal  change  on  corporate  change  in  Italy  use  the  Anti-­‐Director  Rights  Index  (ADRI)  developed   by   La   Porta   et   al.   (1997,   1998),   a   revised   version   of   the   ADRI   that  corrects   certain   coding   errors   (Djankov   et   al.   2008)   and   a   new   Anti-­‐Self-­‐dealing  index   (ASDI)   also   developed   by   Djankov   et   al.   (2008).   They   also   use   for   certain  analyses  the  CBR  Shareholder  Protection  Index  (SPI)  (Siems  et  al.  2009).  These  are  aggregate   measures   of   legal   MSP   at   the   country   level,   which   were   developed   in  comparative  studies  and  do  not  necessarily  capture  all  aspects  of  the  Draghi  law  and  other   legal   reforms   that   have   taken   place   in   Italy.8   More   importantly,   these  measures  do  not  necessarily  focus  on  the  same  aspects  of  corporate  governance  that  Cuomo  et   al.   (2012)  use   as  dependent   firm-­‐level   variables.   The  ADRI   for   instance  

                                                                                                                         8  However,  arguably  Mario  Draghi  –  the  main  sponsor  of  the  Draghi  law  –  was  himself  strongly  influenced  by  the  ADRI.  One  could  hence  expect  that  the  changes  brought  about  by  that  law  is  actually  captured  very  well  by  this  index.  Or  rather  conversely:  the  law  reflects  the  ADRI.  

Page 34: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  34  

does  not  contain  any  measures  for  ownership  structures,  the  existence  of  pyramid  structures   or   syndicate   agreements   among   shareholders,   which   are   the   control-­‐enhancing  mechanisms  (CEM)   investigated  by  Cuomo  et  al.   (2012).  An   increase   in  the  ADRI  does  hence  not  directly  affect  any  of  the  firm-­‐level  practices  investigated  by   Cuomo   et   al.   (2012).9   To   be   sure,   this   is   not   necessarily   an   absurd   way   of  proceeding.  However,  it  reveals  an  inconsistency  between  the  implicit  assumptions  about   how   law   is   expected   to   matter   (the   coercive   view)   and   the   empirical  procedure  used  to  test  whether  law  matters.    

If  we  do  take  the  coercive  view  of  law  seriously,  we  would  have  to  test  the  following  proposition:  

P1:  Controlling  for  other  factors,  an  increase  in  legal  shareholder  protection  will  only  lead  to  an  increase  in  the  degree  of  shareholder-­‐orientation  in  those  practices  that  are  directly  targeted  by  the  reform.  

From   the   normative   perspective,   on   the   other   hand,   we   would   expect   that   legal  reform  may  impact  corporate  governance  practices  at  the  firm  level  even  if  a  given  practice  is  not  explicitly  targeted  by  the  legal  reform.  The  legal  change  may  signal  in  broad   terms   that   the   norm   of   ‘shareholder   value’   is   considered   appropriate,   or   it  may   be   perceived   as   signalling   that   the   state   or   judges  will   not   tolerate   practices  that  are  detrimental  to  shareholders.  In  this  case,    

P2:   An   increase   in   legal   shareholder   protection   is   associated   with   an   increase   in  shareholder-­‐orientated  practices,  regardless  of  the  correspondence  of  legal  provisions  with  corporate  practices.  

A   third  possibility   is   that   law  matters  not   so  much   through   its   coercive   force,  nor  through  the  normative  signals  it  sends,  but  rather  through  broader  incentives  that  it  creates  for  companies.  Again,  the  empirical  study  by  Cuomo  et  al.  (2012)  constitutes  a  good  example  that  refers  to  such  an  incentive  mechanism:  the  authors  argue  that  the  reason  why  we  would  expect  higher  levels  of  minority  shareholder  protection  in  the   law   to   affect   control   enhancing   mechanisms,   is   that   better   laws   reduce   the  amount  of  private  benefits  of   control   that   insiders   can  extract   from   the   firm.  This  reduces   the   incentives   to   stick   with   such   corporate   governance   mechanisms.   In  order   to   distinguish   this   incentive   perspective   from   the   signalling   or   normative  perspective   we   can   formulate   the   following   proposition   referring   to   the   level   of  PBCs:  

P3:  Legal  change  that  is  not  directly  target  at  a  given  corporate  practice  will  have  a  stronger   impact   on   corporate   change   in   countries   where   PBCs   are   higher   than   in  others.  

                                                                                                                         9  The  six  variables  included  in  the  ADRI  are  ‘Proxy  by  mail  allowed’,  ‘Shares  not  blocked  before  AGM’,  ‘Cumulative  voting  /  Proportional  representation’,  ‘Oppressed  minority  rights’,  ‘Pre-­‐emptive  rights  to  new  issues’,  ‘percentage  of  shareholders  needed  to  call  extraordinary  AGM’  (La  Porta  et  al.  1997).  

Page 35: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  35  

The  operationalisation  of  these  propositions  into  testable  hypothesis  is  certainly  not  easy.  Indeed,  the  granularity  of  data  needed  in  order  to  investigate  the  quite  subtle  differences   among   the   mechanisms   that   these   propositions   postulate   may   be   a  practical   challenge.  Nevertheless,   they  do  constitute  a  guideline   for   researchers   in  designing   more   rigorous   tests   of   the   impact   of   law   on   corporate   governance  outcomes  than  is  often  the  case  currently.  

5.  Conclusion  

This   paper   revisited   the   Law  and  Finance   School   literature   in   order   to   determine  what  concept  of  law  can  be  explicitly  and  implicitly  found  in  the  core  studies  in  this  field.  The   surprising   conclusion  of   the   literature   review  was   that  LFS   actually  has  very   little   to   say   about   how   exactly   law   is   expected   to   matter   for   economic  outcomes.  Indeed,  the  LFS  seems  mainly  to  be  an  attempt  to  apply  economic  theory  and  econometric  methods  to  legal  phenomena  rather  than  the  other  way  round.  The  legal   theory   underlying   LFS   is   tentative,   underdeveloped,   and   at   times  contradictory.  The   field  has   increasingly  moved  away   from  the  key  claim  that   it   is  indeed   law   that  matters.   Rather,   broad   cultural   and  political   factors   have   become  more   important   than   actual   substantive   legal   features   in   explaining   corporate  governance  outcomes.  This  paper  has  argued  that  taking  legal  theory  seriously  is  an  important  step  if  we  want  to  take  the  content  that  ‘law  matters’  seriously.  

Implicitly  and  –  more  rarely–  explicitly,  the  LFS  literature  suggests  that  law  mainly  matters   through   its   function   of   protecting   property   rights   as   well   as   creating  incentives  and   that   it  deploys   its  effect  on  economic  actors   through   the   threats  of  punishment   that   stem   from   the   enforcement   of   law.   Indeed,   the   importance  associated   to   enforcement   issues   in   the   LFS   literature   hints   at   the   underlying  command  theory  of  law:  the  main  reason  why  firms  would  follow  laws  is  the  fear  of  punishment.  

The  paper  then  discussed  alternative  theories  and  attempted  to  go  beyond  the  basic  functions   of   property   rights   protection   and   incentive   creation.   It   argued   that   the  moral  or  normative  role  of  law  has  been  neglected  in  the  LFS  literature.  If,  as  legal  scholarship   suggests,   laws   impact   behaviours   not   only   through   threats   and  incentives,   but   also   through   normative   signals,   existing   tests   of   the   law   matters  hypothesis  may  be  flawed,  as  they  do  not  capture  all  the  potential  impacts  law  has  on  corporate  practices.   Indeed,   the  neglect  of  certain  functions  and  impacts  of   law  on   economic   outcomes  may   affect   the   accuracy   and   validity   of   empirical   findings  from  studies  in  this  area.  In  other  words,  in  order  to  answer  accurately  the  question  ‘does  law  matter?’  this  paper  suggests  that  we  first  need  to  tackle  the  question  ‘how  do  we  expect  law  to  matter?’  It  is  hoped  that  the  paper  provides  a  useful  first  step  in  guiding   empirical   research   into   these   questions   into   new,   more   promising  directions.  

 

Page 36: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  36  

   

Page 37: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  37  

References:  

Aguilera,   R.   and   Jackson,   G.   (2003).   "The   Cross-­‐National   Diversity   of   Corporate  Governance:  Dimensions  and  Determinants,"  Academy  of  Management  Review  28(3):  447-­‐465.  

 Armour,  J.,  Deakin  S.,  Sarkar  P.,  Siems  M.,  and  Singh  A.  (2009a).  "How  do  legal  rules  

evolve?   Evidence   from   a   cross-­‐country   comparison   of   shareholder,   creditor  and  worker  protection."  CBR  Working  Paper  382.  

 Armour,  J.  Deakin  S.,  Sarkar  P.,  Siems  M.,  and  Singh  A.  (2007).  “Shareholder  

protection  and  stock  market  development:  an  empirical  test  of  the  legal  origin  hypothesis,”  Journal  of  Empirical  Legal  Studies,  6(2):  343-­‐380.  

 Austin,  J.  (1832).  The  Province  of  Jurisprudence  Determined.  London:  John  Murray.    Beck  T.,  Demirgüc-­‐Kunt  A.  and  Levine  R.  (2003a).  “Law  and  finance:  why  does  legal  

origin  matter?,”  Journal  of  Comparative  Economics,  31:  653-­‐675.    Becker,  G.  (1968).  “Crime  and  Punishment:  An  Economic  Approach,”  Journal  of  

Political  Economy,  76(2):  169-­‐217.    Berkowitz,   D.,   et   al.   (2003).   "Economic   development,   legality,   and   the   transplant  

effect."  European  Economic  Review  47:  165-­‐195.    Cheffins,  B.  R.  (2001).  "Does  Law  Matter?  The  Separation  of  Ownership  and  Control  

in  the  United  Kingdom."  Journal  of  Legal  Studies  30.    Chemmanur,   T.   J.   and   P.   Fulghieri   (2006).   "Competition   and   cooperation   among  

exchanges:  a  theory  of  cross-­‐listing  and  endogenous  listing  standards."  Journal  of  Financial  Economics  82:  455-­‐489.  

 Chong,   A.,   R.   La   Porta,   F.   Lopez-­‐de-­‐Silanes,   A.   Shleifer.   2014.   "Letter   Grading  

Government   Efficiency,”   Journal   of   the   European   Economics   Association,  12(2):  277-­‐299.  

 Claessens,   S.   and   L.   Laeven   (2003).   "Financial   Development,   Property   Rights,   and  

Growth."  the  Journal  of  Finance  58(6):  2401-­‐2436.    Commons,  J.  (1924)  Legal  Foundations  of  Capitalism  (New  York:  Macmillan).    Coase,  R.  (1960).  “The  Problem  of  Social  Cost,”  Journal  of  Law  and  Economics,  3:  1–

44,    Coffee,   J.   C.   (2000).   "The   Rise   of   Dispersed   Ownership:   The   Role   of   Law   in   the  

Separation  of  Ownership  and  Control."  Columbia  Law  and  Economics  Working  Paper  182:  1-­‐95.  

 

Page 38: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  38  

Coffee,   J.   (2001).   “Do   Norms   Matter?   A   Cross-­‐country   Evaluation,”   University   of  Pennsylvania  Law  Review,  149:  2151-­‐2177.  

   Cuomo,  F.,  et  al.  (2012).  "The  effects  of  legal  reforms  on  the  ownerhsip  strucutre  of  

listed  companies."  Industrial  and  Corporate  Change  22(2):  427-­‐458.    Dam,   Kenneth.   (2006)   The   Law-­‐Growth   Nexus:   The   Rule   of   Law   and   Economic  

Development,  Washington  DC:  Brookings  Institution  Press.    Damaska,   M.   (1986).   The   Faces   of   Justice   and   State   Authority:   A   Comparative  

Approach  to  the  Legal  Process,  New  Haven,  Yale  University  Press.    Deakin,   S.,   Gindis,   D.,   Hodgson,   G.,   Huang,   K.   &   Pistor,   K.   (2015).   Legal  

Institutionalism:   Capitalism   and   the   Constitutive   Role   of   Law.   CBR  Working  Paper,  1-­‐40.  

 Deakin,  S.,  et  al.   (2011).   "An  End  to  Consensus?  The  Selective   Impact  of  Corporate  

Law  Reform  on  Financial  Development."  CBR  Working  Paper  423:  1-­‐33.  Djankov,   S.   R.   La   Porta,   F.   Lopez-­‐de-­‐Silanes,   A.   Shleifer.   (2010).   “Disclosure   by  

Politicians’,  American  Economic  Journal:  Applied  Economics  2:179-­‐209.    Djankov,   S.,   et   al.   (2008).   "The   Law   and   Economics   of   Self-­‐Dealing."   Journal   of  

Financial  Economics  88(3):  430-­‐465.    Djankov,  Simeon,  Caralee  McLiesh,  and  Andrei  Shleifer.(2007).  “Private  Credit  in  

129  Countries”,  Journal  of  Financial  Economics  12  (2):  77-­‐99.    Djankov,  Simeon,  Rafael  La  Porta,  Florencio  Lopezde-­‐  Silanes,  and  Andrei  Shleifer.  

2003b.  “Courts.”  Quarterly  Journal  of  Economics  ,  118(2):  453–517.    Djankov,  Simeon,  Edward  L.  Glaeser,  Rafael  La  Porta,  Florencio  Lopez-­‐de-­‐Silanes,  

and  Andrei  Shleifer.  2003.  “The  New  Comparative  Economics.”  Journal  of  Comparative  Economics  ,  31(4):  595-­‐619.  

 Dworkin,  R.  1988.  Law's  Empire,  Harvard,  Harvard  University  Press.    Dworkin,  R.  1997[1977].  Taking  Rights  Seriously,  London,  Bloomsbury  Academic.    Easterbrook,   F.   &   Fischel,   D.   R.   1991.   The   Economic   Structure   of   Corporate   Law,  

Harvard,  Harvard  University  Press.    Espen   Eckbo,   B.   (2005).   Strong   insiders   invite  weak   governance.   Financial   Times.  

(19  May  2005),  London,  Pearson.    Fama,  E.  (1980).  “Agency  Problems  and  the  Theory  of  the  Firm”.  Journal  of  Politcal  

Economy,  88,  288-­‐307.    Finnis,  J.  (1980).  Natural  Law  and  Natural  Rights,  Oxford,  Oxford  University  Press.  

Page 39: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  39  

 Fuller,  L.  (1969).  The  Morality  of  Law,  Yale,  Yale  University  Press.    Furubotn,  E.  &  S.  Pejovich.  (1972).  “Property  Rights  and  Economic  Theory:  A  Survey  

of  Recent  Literature”.  Journal  of  Economic  Literature,  10,  1137-­‐62.    Gamble,  A.  (2013).  “Hayek  and  Liberty”,  Critical  Review  25(3-­‐4):  342-­‐363.    Gilson,   R.   J.   (2005).   "Controlling   Shareholders   and   Corporate   Governance:  

Complicating   the   Comparative   Taxonomy."   European   Corporate   Governance  Institute  Working  Paper  49:  1-­‐53.  

   Gilson,   R.   J.   (2004).   “Globalizing   corporate   governance:   convergence   of   form   or  

function.”   In   Convergence   or   Persistence   of   Corporate   Governance.   J.   N.  Gordon  and  M.  J.  Roe.  Cambridge,  Cambrige  University  Press:  128-­‐159.  

 Glaeser,  Edward  L.,  Rafael  La  Porta,  Florencio  Lopezde-­‐  Silanes,  and  Andrei  Shleifer.  

2004.  “Do  Institutions  Cause  Growth?”  Journal  of  Economic  Growth  ,  9(3):  271–303.  

 Glaeser,   E.   Scheinkman,   J.,   and   A.   Shleifer.   (2003).   “The   Injustice   of   Inequality”,  

Journal  of  Monetary  Economics  50:  199-­‐222.    Glaeser,  E.  &  A.  Shleifer.  (2003)  “The  Rise  of  the  Regulatory  State”,  Journal  of  

Economic  Literature  41  (2):  401-­‐425.  

Glaeser,  E.  &  A.  Shleifer.    2002.  “Legal  Origins”.  The  Quarterly  Journal  of  Economics,  117:  1193-­‐1229.  

 Gordon,  J.  N.  and  M.  J.  Roe,  Eds.  (2004).  Convergence  and  Persistence  in  Corporate  

Governance.  Cambridge,  Cambridge  Univ.  Press.    Gourevitch,  P.  A.  and  J.  Shinn  (2005).  Political  Power  &  Corporate  Control.  The  New  

Global   Politics   of   Corporate   Governance.   Princeton,   Princeton   University  Press.  

 Green,   L.   (2015).   “The   Forces   of   Law:  Duty,   Coercion   and  Power,”   Legal  Research  

Paper  Series.  University  of  Oxford,  12/2015:  1-­‐34.    Green,   L.   (2013).   “Should   Law   Improve   Morality?”   Criminal   Law   and   Philosophy,  

7:473-­‐494.    Green,  L.  (2012[1961]).  “Introduction”.  In:  HART,  H.  L.  A.  (ed.)  The  Concept  of  Law.  

Third  edition  ed.  Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press.    Grossman,  Sanford  J.,  and  Oliver  D.  Hart.  (1988).  “One  Share–One  Vote  and  the  

Market  for  Corporate  Control.”  Journal  of  Financial  Economics,  20(1–2):175–202.    

 

Page 40: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  40  

Hansmann,  H.  and  R.  Kraakman  (2004).  “The  End  of  History  for  Corporate  Law.“  In  Convergence  and  Persistence  in  Corporate  Governance.  J.  N.  Gordon  and  M.  J.  Roe.  Cambridge,  Cambridge  University  Press:  33-­‐68.  

 Hart,  Oliver  D.  1995.  Firms,  Contracts,  and  Financial  Structure.  Oxford  and  New  

York:  Oxford  University  Press,  Clarendon  Press.    Hart,  H.  (2012[1961]).  The  Concept  of  Law,  Oxford,  Oxford  University  Press.    Hay,  J.  &  Shleifer,  A.  (1998).  “Private  Enforcement  of  Public  Laws:  a  Theory  of  Legal  

Reform.”  American  Economic  Review  Papers  and  Proceedings,  88:  398-­‐403.    Hayek,  F.  (2013[1982]).  Law,  Legislation  and  Liberty,  London:  Routledge.    Hayek,   F.   (2011[1960]).   The   Constitution   of   Liberty.   The   definitive   edition,   (ed.  

Hamowy,   R.),   The   Collected   Works   of   F.   A.   Hayek   Volum   XVII.   Chicago:  University  of  Chicago  Press.  

 Holmes,  O.  (1897).  “The  Path  of  the  Law”,  Boston  Law  School  Magazine,  1(4):  1-­‐18.    Jackson,  G.  &  R.  Deeg.  (2008).  “Comparing  Capitalisms:  Understanding  institutional  

diversity  and  its  implications  for  international  business,”  Journal  of  International  Business  Studies,  39:  540-­‐561.  

 Jensen,  Michael  C.,  and  William  H.  Meckling.  1976.  “Theory  of  the  Firm:  Managerial  

Behavior,  Agency  Costs  and  Ownership  Structure,”  Journal  of  Financial  Economics,  3(4):  305–60.  

 Johnson,   S.,   R.   La   Porta,   F.   Lopez-­‐de-­‐Silanes,   A.   Shleifer.   (2000).   “Tunneling,”  

American  Economic  Review,  90(2):  22-­‐27.    Kelsen,  H.  1967.  The  Pure  Theory  of  Law.  Berkeley:  University  of  California  Press.    Lan,  L.  and  L.  Heracleous.  (2010).  “Rethinking  Agency  Theory:  The  View  from  Law”,  

Academy  of  Management  Review  35(2):  294-­‐314.    La   Porta,   R.,   F.   Lopez-­‐de-­‐Silanes,   A.   Shleifer   and   R.   Vishny.   (1997a).   "Legal  

Determinants  of  External  Finance."  the  Journal  of  Finance  52(3):  1131-­‐1150.    LLSV  (1997b).  “Trust  in  Large  Organizations,”  AEA  Papers  and  Proceedings,  87(2):  

333-­‐338.    LLSV  (1998).  "Law  and  Finance."  Journal  of  Political  Economy  106(6):  1113-­‐1155.    LLSV  (1999a).  "Corporate  Ownership  Around  the  World,"  Journal  of  Finance  54(2):  

471-­‐517    LLSV   (1999b).   "The   Quality   of   Government,"   Journal   of   Law,   Economics   and  

Organization,  15(1):  222-­‐279.  

Page 41: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  41  

 LLSV  (2000)  “Investor  protection  and  Corporate  Governance,”   Journal  of  Financial  

Economics,  58:3-­‐27.    LLS  (2006).  “What  Works  in  Securities  Laws?”  Journal  of  Finance,  61(1):  1-­‐32.    Larsson-­‐Olaison,  U.  2014.  Convergence  of  National  Corporate  Governance  Systems:  

Localizing  and  Fitting  the  Transplants.  Växjö:  Linnaeus  University  Press.    Levine,   R.   (1999).   “Law,   Finance,   and   Economic   Growth”,   Journal   of   Financial  

Intermediation,  8:  8-­‐35.    Lueck,  D.  &  Miceli,  T.  (2007).  “Property  Law.”  In:  Polinsky,  A.  M.  &  Shavell,  S.  (eds.)  

Handbook  of  Law  and  Economics.  Amsterdam:  North-­‐Holland.    Mahoney,   P.   (2001).   “The   Common   Law   and   Economic   Growth:   Hayek   Might   Be  

Right,”  The  Journal  of  Legal  Studies,  30(2):  503-­‐525    Milhaupt,  C.  J.  and  K.  Pistor  (2008).  Law  &  Capitalism:  What  Corporate  Crises  Reveal  

about  Legal  Systems  and  Economic  Development  around  the  World.  Chicago,  Chicago  University  Press.  

 Moore,   M.   1992.   Law   as   a   Functional   Kind.   In:   GEORGE,   R.   P.   (ed.)   Natural   Law  

Theory:  Contemporary  Essays.  Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press.    Ohnesorge,  J.  (2007).  "The  Rule  of  Law."  Annual  Review  of  Law  and  Social  Science  3:  

99-­‐114.    Ohnesorge,  J.  (2009).  “Legal  Origins  and  the  Tasks  of  Corporate  Law  in  Economic  

Development:  A  Preliminary  Exploration,”  Brigham  Young  University  Law  Review,  2009(6):  1619-­‐1634.  

 Pagano,   M.   and   P.   F.   Volpin   (2005).   "The   Political   Economy   of   Corporate  

Governance."  American  Economic  Review  95(4):  1005-­‐1030.    Perry,  S.  (2006).  "Hart  on  Social  Rules  and  the  Foundations  of  Law:  Liberating  the  

Internal  Point  of  View"  University  of  Pennsylvania  Law  School  Faculty  Scholarship.  (2006):  1107-­‐1209.  

 Posner,  Richard.  1973.  Economic  Analysis  of  Law.  Boston:  Little-­‐Brown.    Roe,  M.  and  J.  Siegel.  (2009)  “Finance  and  Politics:  A  Review  Essay  Based  on  

Kenneth  Dam’s  Analysis  of  Legal  Traditions  in  The  Law–Growth  Nexus”,  Journal  of  Economic  Literature,  47(3):  781-­‐800.  

 Sarat  A.  and  Kearns  T.,  (eds).  (1993),  Law  in  Everyday  Life.  Ann  Arbor:  University  of  

Michigan  Press.    

Page 42: TheConceptofLawin$‘LawandFinance’:$Towardsa$Comprehensive ... · ! 4! TheLaw!and!Finance!School!is!a!termthat!has!come!to!be!used!to!designate!an! approach!related!toaseries!of!influentialpapers!coFauthored!byLaPorta,LopezFdeF

  42  

Schnyder,  G.  (2012).  "Measuring  Corporate  Governance:  Lessons  from  the  'Bundles  Approach'."  Centre  for  Business  Research  Working  Paper  438:  1-­‐39.  

 Shleifer,   A.   (2005).   ““Understanding  Regulation,”   European   Financial  Management  

11  (4):  439-­‐451.    Shleifer,   A.   and   R.   W.   Vishny   (1997).   "A   Survey   of   Corporate   Governance."   the  

Journal  of  Finance  II(2):  737-­‐783.      Siems,  M.  M.,  et  al.  (2009).  CBR  Extended  Shareholder  Protection  Index.  Cambridge,  

Centre  for  Business  Research:  1-­‐105.      Siems,   M.   2007.   Reconciling   Law   &   Finance   and   Comparative   Law.   McGill   Law  

Journal,  52,  55-­‐81.    Siems,  M.  (2005).  What  Does  Not  Work  in  Comparing  Securities  Laws:  A  Critique  on  

La   Porta   et   al’s   Methodology,   International   Company   and   Commercial   Law  Review,  pp.300-­‐305.  

   Singh,   A.   (2011).   "Comparative   advantage,   industrial   policy   and   the  World   Bank:  

back  to  first  principles."  Policy  Studies  32(4):  447-­‐460.    Spamann,  H.  (2006).  "On  the  Insignificance  and/or  Endogeneity  of  La  Porta  et  al.'s  

'Anti-­‐Director  Rights  Index'  under  Consistent  Coding."  John  M.  Olin  Center  for  Law,  Economics,  and  Business  Fellows'  Discussion  Paper  Series  3/2006:  98.  

 Stigler,  George  J.,  “Public  Regulation  of  the  Securities  Market,”  Journal  of  Business,  

37:117–142.    Teubner,  G.  2001.  Legal   Irritants:  How  Unifying  Law  Ends  up   in  New  Divergences.  

In:   HALL,   P.   A.   &   SOSKICE,   D.   (eds.)  Varieties   of   Capitalism.   The   Institutional  Foundations  of  Comparative  Advantage.  Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press.  

 Teubner,  G.  (1983).  “Substantive  and  Reflexive  Elements  in  Modern  Law,”  Law  &  

Society  Review,  17(2):  239-­‐285.    Van  Oosterhout,  J.,  P.  Heugens,  and  M.  Kaptein  (2006).  “The  Internal  Morality  of  

Contracting:  Advancing  the  Contractualist  Endeavor  in  BusinessEthics”,  Academy  of  Management  Review,  31(3):  521-­‐539.    

 Zweigert,   K.  &  Kotz,  H.   1998.  An   Introduction   to   Comparative   Law,  Oxford,  Oxford  

University  Press.