Top Banner
THE NATURE OF GEOMETRY Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. 7
28

THE NATURE OF GEOMETRY Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. 7.

Dec 28, 2015

Download

Documents

Lillian Blake
Welcome message from author
This document is posted to help you gain knowledge. Please leave a comment to let me know what you think about it! Share it to your friends and learn new things together.
Transcript
Page 1: THE NATURE OF GEOMETRY Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. 7.

THE NATURE OF GEOMETRY

Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.

7

Page 2: THE NATURE OF GEOMETRY Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. 7.

Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.

7.1 Geometry

Page 3: THE NATURE OF GEOMETRY Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. 7.

3

Greek (Euclidean) Geometry

Page 4: THE NATURE OF GEOMETRY Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. 7.

4

Greek (Euclidean) Geometry

Geometry involves points and sets of points called lines, planes, and surfaces. Certain concepts in geometry are called undefined terms.

For example, what is a line? Is it a set of points? Any set of points? What is a point?

1. A point is something that has no length, width, or thickness.

2. A point is a location in space.

Page 5: THE NATURE OF GEOMETRY Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. 7.

5

Greek (Euclidean) Geometry

Certainly these are not satisfactory definitions because they involve other terms that are not defined. We will therefore take the terms point, line, and plane as undefined.

Geometry can be separated into two categories:

1. Traditional (which is the geometry of Euclid)

2. Transformational (which is more algebraic than the traditional approach)

Page 6: THE NATURE OF GEOMETRY Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. 7.

6

Greek (Euclidean) Geometry

When Euclid was formalizing traditional geometry, he based it on five postulates, which have come to be known as Euclid’s postulates.

A postulate or axiom is a statement accepted without proof. In mathematics, a result that is proved on the basis of some agreed-upon postulates is called a theorem.

Page 7: THE NATURE OF GEOMETRY Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. 7.

7

Greek (Euclidean) Geometry

The first four of these postulates were obvious and noncontroversial, but the fifth one was different.

This fifth postulate looked more like a theorem than a postulate.

Page 8: THE NATURE OF GEOMETRY Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. 7.

8

Greek (Euclidean) Geometry

It was much more difficult to understand than the other four postulates, and for more than 20 centuries mathematicians tried to derive it from the other postulates or to replace it by a more acceptable equivalent.

Two straight lines in the same plane are said to be parallel if they do not intersect.

Today we can either accept the fifth postulate as a postulate (without proof) or deny it. If it is denied, it turns out that no contradiction results; in fact, if it is not accepted, other geometries called non-Euclidean geometries result.

Page 9: THE NATURE OF GEOMETRY Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. 7.

9

Greek (Euclidean) Geometry

If it is accepted, then the geometry that results is consistent with our everyday experiences and is called Euclidean geometry.

Let’s look at each of Euclid’s postulates. The first one says that a straight line can be drawn from any point to any other point.

To connect two points, you need a device called a straightedge (a device that we assume has no markings on it; you will use a ruler, but not to measure, when you are treating it as a straightedge).

Page 10: THE NATURE OF GEOMETRY Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. 7.

10

Greek (Euclidean) Geometry

The portion of the line that connects points A and B in Figure 7.3 is called a line segment.

We write AB (or BA). We contrast this notation with , which is used to name the line passing through the points A and B. We use the symbol |AB| for the length of segment AB.

Portions of lines

Figure 7.3

Page 11: THE NATURE OF GEOMETRY Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. 7.

11

Greek (Euclidean) Geometry

The second postulate says that we can draw a straight line. This seems straightforward and obvious, but we should point out that we will indicate a line by putting arrows on each end.

If we consider a point on a line, that point separates the line into parts: two half-lines and the point itself. If the arrow points in only one direction, the figure is called a ray.

Page 12: THE NATURE OF GEOMETRY Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. 7.

12

Greek (Euclidean) Geometry

We write AB (or BA) for the ray with endpoint A passing through B. These definitions are illustrated in Figure 7.3.

To construct a line segment of length equal to the length ofa given line segment, we need a device called a compass.

Figure 7.3

Portions of lines

Page 13: THE NATURE OF GEOMETRY Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. 7.

13

Greek (Euclidean) Geometry

Figure 7.4 shows a compass, which is used to mark off andduplicate lengths, but not to measure them.

A compass

Figure 7.4

Page 14: THE NATURE OF GEOMETRY Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. 7.

14

Greek (Euclidean) Geometry

If objects have exactly the same size and shape, they are called congruent. We can use a straightedge and compass to construct a figure so that it meets certain requirements.

To construct a line segment congruent to a given line segment, copy a segment AB on any line .

Page 15: THE NATURE OF GEOMETRY Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. 7.

15

Greek (Euclidean) Geometry

First fix the compass so that the pointer is on point A and the pencil is on B, as shown in Figure 7.5a.

Constructing a line segment

Figure 7.5 (a)

Page 16: THE NATURE OF GEOMETRY Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. 7.

16

Greek (Euclidean) Geometry

Then, on line , choose a point C. Next, without changing the compass setting, place the pointer on C and strike an arc at D, as shown in Figure 7.5b.

Constructing a line segment

Figure 7.5(b)

Page 17: THE NATURE OF GEOMETRY Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. 7.

17

Greek (Euclidean) Geometry

Euclid’s third postulate leads us to a second construction. The task is to construct a circle, given its center and radius. These steps are summarized in Figure 7.6.

c. Hold the pointer at point O and move the pencil end to draw the circle.

Construction of a circle

Figure 7.6

b. Set the legs of the compass on the ends of radius AB; move the pointer to point O without changing the setting.

a. Given, a point and a radius of length |AB|.

Page 18: THE NATURE OF GEOMETRY Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. 7.

18

Greek (Euclidean) Geometry

The fourth postulate is used when we consider angles.

The final construction of this section will demonstrate the fifth postulate. The task is to construct a line through a point P parallel to a given line , as shown in Figure 7.7a.

Given line

Construction of a line parallel to a given line through a given point

Figure 7.7 (a)

Page 19: THE NATURE OF GEOMETRY Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. 7.

19

Greek (Euclidean) Geometry

First, draw any line through P that intersects , at a point A, as shown in Figure 7.7b.

Construction of a line parallel to a given line through a given point

Figure 7.7 (b)

Draw line

Page 20: THE NATURE OF GEOMETRY Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. 7.

20

Greek (Euclidean) Geometry

Now draw an arc with the pointer at A and radius AP, and label the point of intersection of the arc and the line X, as shown in Figure 7.7c.

Construction of a line parallel to a given line through a given point

Figure 7.7 (c)

Strike arc

Page 21: THE NATURE OF GEOMETRY Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. 7.

21

Greek (Euclidean) Geometry

With the same opening of the compass, draw an arc first with the pointer at P and then with the pointer at X. Their point of intersection will determine a point Y (Figure 7.7d).Draw the line through both P and Y. This line is parallel to .

Construction of a line parallel to a given line through a given point

Figure 7.7 (d)

Determine point Y

Page 22: THE NATURE OF GEOMETRY Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. 7.

22

Transformational Geometry

Page 23: THE NATURE OF GEOMETRY Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. 7.

23

Transformational Geometry

Transformational geometry deals with the study of transformations. A transformation is the passage from one geometric figure to another by means of reflections, translations, rotations, contractions, or dilations. For example, given a line L and a point P, as shown in Figure 7.8, we call the point P the reflection of P about the line L if PP is perpendicular to L and is also bisected by L.

A reflection

Figure 7.8

Page 24: THE NATURE OF GEOMETRY Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. 7.

24

Transformational Geometry

Each point in the plane has exactly one reflection point corresponding to a given line L. A reflection is called a reflection transformation, and the line of reflection is called the line of symmetry.

Page 25: THE NATURE OF GEOMETRY Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. 7.

25

Transformational Geometry

The easiest way to describe a line symmetry is to say that if you fold a paper along its line of symmetry, then the figure will fold onto itself to form a perfect match, as shown inFigure 7.9.

Line symmetry on the maple leaf of Canada

Figure 7.9

Page 26: THE NATURE OF GEOMETRY Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. 7.

26

Transformational Geometry

Other transformations include translations, rotations, dilations, and contractions, which are illustrated in Figure 7.11.

Transformations of a fixed geometric figure

Figure 7.11

Page 27: THE NATURE OF GEOMETRY Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. 7.

27

Similarity

Page 28: THE NATURE OF GEOMETRY Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. 7.

28

Similarity

Geometry is also concerned with the study of the relationships between geometric figures. A primary relationship is that of congruence. A second relationship is called similarity.

Two figures are said to be similar if they have the same shape, although not necessarily the same size.