Top Banner
Daniel “The Empedoclean Renaissance” 1 The Empedoclean Renaissance “In a deluge of water and fire, the volcano spits up only a single reminder of Empedocles his lead sandal.” Gilles Deleuze, The Logic of Sense. 1 Drew Daniel Introduction: Jumping Into the Fire Early modern studies has recently witnessed a striking resurgence of interest in Lucretius as a crucial figure for the dissemination of Epicurean atomism into the cultural bloodstream. Alison Brown, Catherine Wilson, Jonathan Goldberg, Stephen Greenblatt and Gerard Passannante have all contributed distinctive booklength studies that track this process and theorize Lucretian aftereffects, echoes and resonances in the theology, history, painting, and poetry of the period. 2 If there was ever a candidate for a “return of theory within early modernity”, then the return of the theory of atoms and void from medieval desuetude into the shocked, tantalized
35

The Empedoclean Renaissance

May 14, 2023

Download

Documents

Welcome message from author
This document is posted to help you gain knowledge. Please leave a comment to let me know what you think about it! Share it to your friends and learn new things together.
Transcript
Page 1: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     1  

 

The  Empedoclean  Renaissance  

 

“In  a  deluge  of  water  and  fire,  the  volcano  spits  up  only  a  single  

reminder  of  Empedocles-­‐  his  lead  sandal.”  

-­‐Gilles  Deleuze,  The  Logic  of  Sense.1    

 

Drew  Daniel  

 

Introduction:  Jumping  Into  the  Fire  

 

Early  modern  studies  has  recently  witnessed  a  striking  resurgence  of  interest  

in  Lucretius  as  a  crucial  figure  for  the  dissemination  of  Epicurean  atomism  into  the  

cultural  bloodstream.  Alison  Brown,  Catherine  Wilson,  Jonathan  Goldberg,  Stephen  

Greenblatt  and  Gerard  Passannante  have  all  contributed  distinctive  book-­‐length  

studies  that  track  this  process  and  theorize  Lucretian  aftereffects,  echoes  and  

resonances  in  the  theology,  history,  painting,  and  poetry  of  the  period.2    If  there  was  

ever  a  candidate  for  a  “return  of  theory  within  early  modernity”,  then  the  return  of  

the  theory  of  atoms  and  void  from  medieval  desuetude  into  the  shocked,  tantalized  

Page 2: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     2  

awareness  of  a  particularly  crucial  galaxy  of  early  modern  readers  from  Machiavelli  

to  Montaigne  to  Spenser  offers  a  case  in  point  of  the  uncannily  necromantic  return  

of  dead  ideas  to  virulent,  contagious  new  life.    

That  the  critical  constellation  of  a  “Lucretian  Renaissance”-­‐  to  use  

Passannante’s  luminous  title  phrase-­‐  has  taken  place  largely  under  the  rubric  of  

intellectual  history  rather  than  through  a  new  theorization  is  unsurprising,  for  the  

short  version  of  this  narrative  of  transmission  arrives  already  bottlenecked  through  

the  singularity  of  an  evental  date:  though  not  all  interested  parties  regard  1417  as  

the  decisive  moment  through  which  a  reborn  Lucretius  emerges  to  make  the  world  

modern,  there  is  a  sufficiently  general,  agreed  upon  consensus  that  this  is  so,  and  a  

broader  consensus  about  Lucretius  as  the  tissue  donor  whose  transplantation  of  a  

set  of  Ancient  Greek  philosophical  doctrines  into  hexameters  of  Latin  poetry  

brought  previously  unthinkable,  indeed  damnable  ideas  back  into  broader  

circulation  at  precisely  the  tipping  point  when,  in  a  more  temperate  and  receptive  

intellectual  soil,  a  brave  cognoscenti  was  primed  to  consider  certain  radical  

possibilities  anew:  that  the  world  is  assembled  out  of  atoms  and  void,  that  the  soul  

is  mortal,  that  death  is  simply  the  de-­‐composition  of  matter,  and  that  the  gods  are  

indifferent.  If  the  Lucretian  dissemination  of  Epicureanism  was  a  “return  of  theory”  

that  already  took  place  within  the  Renaissance,  then  the  recent  scholarly  desire  to  

re-­‐tell  this  already  familiar  story  over  the  last  five  years  could  then  be  termed  a  

“return  of  the  return  of  theory”.      

Page 3: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     3  

But  theory’s  return  has  been  a  return  as  history,  not  as  an  estranged,  altered,  

or  reconstituted  theory.  With  a  few  exceptions,  notably  Goldberg’s  methodological  

intervention  into  Lucretius’  utility  for  the  practice  of  queer  theory  and  

Passannante’s  methodological  intervention  into  the  utility  of  Lucretius  for  the  

practice  of  philology,  the  discussion  has  been  taken  up  with  historicist  re-­‐countings  

of  the  archive  of  transmission.  Indeed  if  temporality  itself  has  become  noticeably  

plastic  within  Jonathan  Gil  Harris’  recent  formulations  of  “the  polychronic”  and  

Alexander  Nagel’s  and  Christopher  Wood’s  formulation  of  the  “Anachronic  

Renaissance”,  there  is  something  strikingly,  insistently  normative  in  the  

chronological  framing  through  which  the  story  of  Lucretius’  return  has  returned.3    

Against  the  backdrop  of  this  “return  of  the  return”,  I  want  to  think  about-­‐  

and,  yes,  theorize  with,  what  does  not  return:  the  phenomena  of  loss,  destruction,  

negation,  and  death  that  haunt  the  historical  archive  of  materialist  philosophy  as  an  

occluded  component  of  these  positive  accounts  of  its  successful,  if  sub  rosa,  

dissemination.  And  I  want  to  think  about  and  theorize  upon  an  uncongenial  figure  

who  does  not  return  because  he  never  left,  a  figure  who  was  subject  to  both  the  pre-­‐

emptive  shattering  of  his  original  texts  and  the  widespread  adoption  of  the  essential  

insights  reflected  back  at  us  from  the  surviving  fragments  of  those  texts:  

Empedocles  of  Acragas  (circa  490-­‐  435  B.C.E.),  the  first  philosopher  to  posit  that  the  

material  of  the  universe  is  composed  entirely  out  of  earth,  air,  fire  and  water.    

Earlier  generations  of  scholarship  have  already  traced  the  dissemination  of  

Empedoclean  concepts  and  references  within  the  English  Renaissance:  an  early  

Page 4: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     4  

essay  by  Sacvan  Bercovitch  constructs  precisely  such  an  archive,  and  I  see  no  reason  

to  repeat  that  work.4  Rather,  I  hope  to  align  what  survives  of  Empedocles’  thought  

alongside  the  (mistaken)  accounts  of  his  death  as  suicide,  in  order  to  think  through  

the  consequences  of  the  Empedoclean  archive  that  are  not  historical  but  precisely  

affective.  That  is,  I  propose  a  recuperative  reading  of  the  metaphysical  pathos  of  

Empedocles’  death  as  a  campy  episode  of  “bad  history”,  a  false  history  of  self-­‐

cancelling  sublimity  attached  to  Empedocles.  Long  discredited  by  textual  scholars  

keen  to  pare  away  the  speculative  and  the  false,  I  want  to  stubbornly  reassert  the  

false  history’s  hermeneutic  value  for  theory  and  against  history.  For  the  false  

accounts  of  Empedocles  fiery  death,  like  the  false  account  of  Lucretius’  love  

melancholy  and  suicide  alleged  by  Jerome,  might  nonetheless  do  real  interpretive  

work  in  drawing  out,  and  critically  opening  to  speculation,  a  basic  set  of  questions:  

What  does  theory  feel  like?  What  are  the  emotional  consequences  of  a  materialist  

ontology?  What  does  it  feel  like  to  affectively  inhabit  the  belief  that  the  world  and  

the  people  within  it  are-­‐-­‐only—transient  assemblages  of  matter?    

For  the  readers  and  writers  of  early  modern  Europe,  the  most  conventional  

answer  to  this  question  came  from  a  homosexual  vegetarian  mystic  who  supposedly  

committed  suicide  by  jumping  into  a  volcano.  Empedocles  of  Acragas  remains  at  

once  hic  et  ubique  and,  by  virtue  of  the  disjunction  between  his  doctrinal  rise  and  

personal  plunge,  curiously  difficult  to  locate.    If  none  of  his  writings-­‐  amphibiously  

perched  between  poetry  and  philosophy-­‐  survive  intact  except  as  brutally  truncated,  

jolting  tags  of  quotation  within  other  writers,  his  core  contribution  to  the  history  of  

philosophy-­‐  the  ontological  doctrine  that  the  material  universe  is  composed  of  

Page 5: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     5  

varying  mixtures  of  the  four  elements  of  earth,  air,  fire  and  water,  sequenced  and  re-­‐

combined  by  the  forces  of  love  and  strife-­‐  suffered  not  fiery  annihilation  but  the  

watering  down  of  a  seemingly  ubiquitous  transmission.  Empedocles  was  

conventional  not  because,  like  Plato  or  Aristotle,  he  was  actively  being  translated,  

read  and  argued  about,  but  precisely  because  his  core  ideas  circulated  not  as  living  

arguments  but  as  dead  metaphors,  blurry  commonplaces,  and  elastic  conceits.  At  

once  miniaturized  into  a  conceptual  toy  and  distended  into  something  universally  

applicable,  the  elemental  doctrine  of  earth,  air,  fire  and  water  leapt  across  the  

boundaries  of  disciplines,  geographical  continents  and  theological  commitments  to  

lodge  itself  in  love  poems,  political  tracts,  sermons  and  lectures  with  equal  facility.  

Indeed,  Empedoclean  combinatorial  ontology  saturates  the  intellectual  history  of  

medieval  and  early  modern  Europe  with  such  quotidian  omnipresence  that  it  

becomes  curiously  difficult  to  localize  and  think  about  clearly.    

Yet  if  his  idea  was  everywhere,  the  man  responsible  was  not.  Inevitably,  the  

schema  came  un-­‐tethered  from  its  originator,  and,  except  among  the  unusually  

learned,  Empedocles  entered  a  murky  twilight  of  pseudo-­‐celebrity  reserved  for  

virtuous  or  vicious  pagans,  alternately  celebrated  for  his  poetic  and  philosophical  

achievements,  chided  for  his  numerous  eccentricities,  vilified  for  his  wilfull  act  of  

self-­‐murder.  Long  lost  aside  from  occasional  fragments  and  secondhard  paraphrase,  

his  texts  could  not  be  read  even  by  those  educated  enough  to  realize  that  they  had  

once  existed.  At  the  level  of  discursive  survival,  the  “fact”  of  the  famous  death  stood  

more  or  less  on  even  footing  with  the  recognition  of  the  void  left  by  the  lost  texts.    

Page 6: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     6  

In  the  methodological  context  of  a  continuing  consideration  of  the  “return  of  

theory“  in  early  modern  studies,  this  particular  stand-­‐off  between  philosophy  and  

intellectual  history  triggers  the  following  volcanic  eruption  of  yet  more  questions:  

What  analogical  resemblances  or  modes  of  kinship  link  earlier  conventions  of  ready-­‐

to-­‐hand  thought  with  the  circulation  of  sententious  and  formulaic  phrases,  saws  and  

positions  within  the  modern  circulation  of  contemporary  “theory”?  Can  an  anecdotal  

account  of  the  death  of  a  philosopher  function  as  a  critique  of  his  or  her  thought?  

Did  it  in  this  case?  What  was  the  relationship  between  the  widespread  adoption  of  

Empedoclean  ontology  and  the  archival  afterlife  of  this  (false)  suicidal  anecdote  

within  early  modernity?  Does  the  self-­‐conflicting  transmission  history  of  

Empedocles  place  his  thought  within  the  archive  of  suicidal  passion,  his  life  within  

the  compass  of  elemental  ontology,  or  both  realms  into  a  compromising  position  

with  each  other?  What  might  the  forcefield  of  relationships  and/or  disjunctions  

between  the  doctrine  and  the  death  tell  us  about  how  early  modern  people-­‐  

particularly  poets  and  dramatists  in  England-­‐  imagined  the  emotional  consequences  

of  materialist  philosophy?  And  how  might  the  representation  of  that  very  nexus  

within  English  literature  illuminate  underlying  conflicts  and  overlaps  between  two  

emergent  critical  orientations  within  early  modern  studies  today:  the  affective  turn  

and  the  new  materialisms?    

The  dissemination  of  the  mingled  streams  of  Empedoclean  ontology  and  

Empedoclean  suicidology  within  early  modern  English  literature  yields  a  self-­‐

differential  archive  which  can  be  sounded  for  local  answers  to  these  broader  

methodological  questions,  which  will  repeat  and  re-­‐combine  over  the  course  of  this  

Page 7: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     7  

essay  as  elemental  themes  and  variations.  That  said,  my  goal  is  not  to  generate  a  

historical  account  of  transmission  history,  but  to  consider  the  theoretical  question  

of  how  affect  and  ontology  variously  intertwine  in  Empedocles  and  within  early  

modernity,  and  to  ask  how  they  might  be  fashioned  into  a  new  critical  assemblage  at  

present.  In  order  for  that  to  happen,  the  twin  shadows  of  Empedocles  as  hyper-­‐

conventional  old  standby  and  suicidal  stranger  must  be  brought  out  anew  and  re-­‐

articulated.  Accordingly,  I  shall  first  revisit  the  fragments,  papyri,  and  testimony  of  

Empedocles  to  reassert  the  vitality  of  his  elemental  ontology,  and  then  flag  its  re-­‐

circulation  within  some  salient  tissue  specimens  of  early  modern  English  literature.    

 

 

 

Assembling  Empedocles  

Adapting  the  tetrad  as  an  idealized  four  part  form  from  Pythagorean  

doctrines  which  are  at  once  mathematical  and  mystical,  Empedocles  was  the  first  

philosopher  to  identify  earth,  air,  fire  and  water  as  the  four  distinct  kinds  of  material  

from  which  the  universe  itself  is  composed.  Though  his  work  or  works  of  

philosophical  poetry  are  largely  lost  and  now  survive  only  through  the  quotations  of  

other  authors  and  the  occasional  intact  papyrus,  a  corpus  of  discrete  fragments  has  

been  constructed  by  subsequent  generations  of  sometimes  fractious  textual  scholars  

into  an  evocative,  if  deeply  incomplete,  composite  of  its  own.5  Across  the  complex  

Page 8: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     8  

pathways  of  his  scholarly  dissemination,  the  name  Empedocles  thus  now  defines  

both  the  “author  function”  of  the  four  part  combinatorial  ontology  attributed  to  him,  

and  radiates  outwards  into  the  broader  speculative  web  which  loosely  binds  his  

scattered  utterances  together.  No  less  than  the  bodies  he  theorized,  Empedocles,  

too,  is  now  an  assemblage.    

If  this  was  a  kind  of  materialism,  what  kind  of  materialism  was  it?  Not,  it  

seems,  a  necessarily  proto-­‐secularizing  one.  In  Fragment  12/6,  Empedocles  

identifies  four  “roots”  from  which  the  earth  and  all  of  its  components  are  

constructed,  symbolically  invoking  each  “root”  with  a  distinct  god  or  goddess:  

First,  hear  of  the  four  roots  of  all  things,  

gleaming  Zeus  and  life-­‐bringing  Hera  and  Aidoneus  

and  Nestis,  who  moistens  with  tears  the  spring  of  mortals.6    

Regardless  of  how  we  evaluate  the  role  of  deities  within  this  fragment,  one  must  not  

mistake  Empedocles’  doctrine  for  the  simple  insistence  that  earth,  air,  fire  and  water  

are  “all  there  is.”  Going  beyond  those  four  “roots”  (he  does  not  use  the  word  

element),  Empedocles  also  posits  two  additional  forces:  Love  and  Strife,  forces  

which  respectively  bond  together  the  roots  into  temporary  forms  or  work  to  

dissolve  those  bonds  and  destroy  those  forms.  Weaving  these  four  roots  and  two  

forces  into  a  unified  ontological  history  of  the  universe,  Empedocles  bequeathed  to  

the  Western  philosophical  tradition  both  an  account  of  the  material  composition  of  

all  matter  and  a  vibrantly  poetic  account  of  the  affective  consequences  of  that  

Page 9: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     9  

material  compositional  doctrine:  the  assembled  fragments  imply  an  ethical  drama  of  

progressive  reincarnation  across  forms  in  which  ascension  to  “divinity”  is  held  out  

as  a  theoretical  ideal  placed  in  permanent  tension  with  a  dark  vision  of  the  ultimate  

fate  of  total  dissolution  shared  in  common  by  all  distinct,  local  forms.    

The  Empedocles  assembled  within  the  testimonies  gathered  together  by  

Diogenes  Laertius’  Lives  of  Eminent  Philosophers  constitutes  a  hyper-­‐vivid  

caricature:  Laertius’  mutually  contradictory  accounts  yield  a  synthetic  vision  of  the  

Sicilian  philosopher  resplendent  in  purple  robes,  gold  belt,  metal  sandals,  and  laurel  

wreath,  surrounded  by  boy  attendants,  declaring  his  own  godhead  in  a  gravely  and  

serious,  yet  pompous  and  ultimately  comical  voice.    In  Death  By  Philosophy,  Ava  

Chitwood  unpacks  the  archive  of  biographical  material  surrounding  Empedocles  

and  finds  in  most  of  its  most  memorable  components  a  kind  of  distorted  

transformation  of  philosophical  claims  made  in  his  vanished  texts:  “His  perceived  

character,  then,  is  little  more  than  a  parody  of  his  work.  His  god-­‐like  nature,  attitude  

and  appearance,  concretized  and  elaborated  in  the  anecdotal  examples  of  his  

actions,  character,  and  dress,  are  the  result  of  a  philosophical  statement  interpreted  

biographically.”7  This  sense  of  a  life  illicitly  back  projected  from  the  contours  of  the  

thought  carries  over  into  the  death  that  concludes  that  life,  for  in  the  biographical  

archive  on  the  subject  of  the  death  of  Empedocles,  various  accounts  proliferate,  but  

each  distinct  version  of  that  death  offers  some  greater  or  lesser  bid  for  a  suitability,  

an  art-­‐directed  aptness  in  which  a  given  philosopher’s  death  cannot  fail  to  function  

as  a  morbid  extension,  cautionary  tale,  or  retroactive  gloss  upon  their  philosophy.    

Page 10: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     10  

I  shall  consider  just  two  of  the  most  celebrated  and  widely  familiar  accounts  

of  Empedocles’  death  which  appear  in  Diogenes  Laertius’  Lives  of  Eminent  

Philosophers:  first,  the  apotheosis  of  his  mysterious  disappearance,  and  then  the  

suicidal  leap  into  Mount  Etna.  The  first  account  concerns  the  consequences  of  a  

nearly  necromantic  act  of  healing  in  which  a  woman  in  a  trance  is  restored  to  life:    

For  Heraclides,  relating  the  story  about  the  dead  woman,  how  Empedocles  got  great  glory  from  sending  away  a  dead  woman  restored  to  life,  says  that  he  celebrated  a  sacrifice  in  the  field  of  Pisianax,  and  that  some  of  his  friends  were  invited,  among  whom  was  Pausanias.  And  then,  after  the  banquet,  they  lay  down,  some  going  a  little  way  off,  and  some  lying  under  the  trees  close  by  in  the  field,  and  some  wherever  they  happened  to  choose.  But  Empedocles  himself  remained  in  the  place  where  he  had  been  sitting.  But  when  day  broke,  and  they  arose,  he  alone  was  not  found.  And  when  he  was  sought  for,  and  the  servants  were  examined  and  said  that  they  did  not  know,  one  of  them  said,  that  at  midnight  he  had  heard  a  loud  voice  calling  Empedocles;  and  that  then  he  himself  rose  up  and  saw  a  great  light  from  heaven,  but  nothing  else.  And  as  they  were  all  amazed  at  what  had  taken  place,  Pausanias  descended  and  sent  some  people  to  look  for  him;  but  afterwards  he  was  commanded  not  to  busy  himself  about  the  matter,  as  he  was  informed  that  what  had  happened  was  deserving  of  thankfulness,  and  that  they  behoved  to  sacrifice  to  Empedocles  as  to  one  who  had  become  a  God.8  

The  second  account,  briefer  yet  far  more  influential,  stages  a  fiery,  dramatic  act  of  

self-­‐cancellation  which  comes  complete  with  a  materialist  punchline:  

Hermippus  says  also,  that  a  woman  of  the  name  of  Panthea,  a  native  of  Agrigentum,  who  had  been  given  over  by  the  physicians,  was  cured  by  him,  and  that  it  was  on  this  account  that  he  celebrated  a  sacrifice;  and  that  the  guests  invited  were  about  eighty  in  number.  But  Hippobotus  says  that  he  rose  up  and  went  away  as  if  he  were  going  to  mount  Aetna;  and  that  when  he  arrived  at  the  crater  of  fire  he  leaped  in,  and  disappeared,  wishing  to  establish  a  belief  that  he  had  become  a  God.  But  afterwards  the  truth  was  detected  by  one  of  his  slippers  having  been  dropped.  For  he  used  to  wear  slippers  with  brazen  soles.9  

There  is  a  curious  sense  here  of  the  assimilation  of  the  materialist  framework  to  the  

narrative  itself:  there  are  no  gods  in  view,  only  presumptuous  mortals  who  wish  to  

Page 11: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     11  

persuade  other  mortals  to  believe  in  their  pretensions  to  godhead,  and  those  

pretensions  are  exposed  through  the  material  persistence  of  the  forensic  evidence  

of  a  single  charred  piece  of  footwear.  The  fact  of  the  slipper  is  doubly  humbling.  

Insofar  as  it  is  tied  to  the  literally  lowest  part  of  the  body,  the  foot,  the  malingering  

slipper  reveals  the  aspirational  philosopher  as  kindred  to  the  dark  lady  of  the  

sonnets:  when  we  walks,  his  feet  tread  upon  the  ground.    The  textual  production  of  

just  this  element  from  Empedocles’  celebrated  ensemble,  rather  than,  say,  his  crown  

or  belt,  suggests  the  rhetorical  thrust  of  a  humanizing  gesture,  recalling  Bataille’s  

remark  in  Documents  that  “The  big  toe  is  the  most  human  part  of  the  human  body,  

in  the  sense  that  no  other  element  is  so  differentiated  from  the  corresponding  

element  of  the  anthropoid  ape.”10  Read  in  this  light,  the  sandal’s  obstinate  status  as  a  

homely  remnant  of  human  living  belies  the  implicit  ascent  towards  divinity,  

suggesting  that  there  is  always  a  material  remainder,  and  that  the  transcendent  

schema  of  an  imagined  apotheosis  was  simply  a  manipulative  fantasy,  a  charade  of  

self-­‐transcendence  from  a  flawed,  grossly  embodied  figure  of  fun.    

  Noting  that  the  philosophy  is  used  to  generate  the  anecdotes  and  stories  

about  their  philosophical  authors,  Chitwood  regards  the  aptness  of  the  Etna  

narrative  of  fiery,  volcanic  suicide  as  the  completion  of  a  range  of  other  proposed  

scenarios  for  Empedocles’  death  scattered  across  the  archive  (which  include  

drowning,  hanging,  and  an  accidental  fall  while  getting  out  of  the  carriage):    

Empedocles’  disappearance  into  the  ether  gloriously  asserts  his  refutation  of  death  and  gives  new  force  to  his  theory  of  the  mutability  of  the  elements  and  the  soul’s  progression  in  transmigration.  His  apotheosis,  which  glorifies  the  philosopher  and  negates  the  vain  and  theatrical  gesture  of  the  Etna  

Page 12: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     12  

anecdotes,  completes  the  biographers  use  of  the  four  elements.  Empedocles  dies  by  water,  by  earth,  by  fire,  and  by  air;  his  elemental  death,  like  his  soul’s  progression,  is  complete.11    

Chitwood’s  sober  unpacking  of  the  aptness  of  the  classical  archive  establishes  a  

clear  historiographic  precedent  in  which  such  ars  moriendi  anecdotes  circulated,  but  

we  might  well  demur  from  its  reparative  tone.  The  failure  to  achieve  godhead  

implicit  in  the  sandal  is  not  meant  to  ratify  but  to  lampoon  material  philosophy  

through  the  production  of  a  lowest  common  denominator.    

In  a  celebrated  passage  from  The  Logic  of  Sense,  Gilles  Deleuze  theorizes  the  

implications  of  these  morbid  anecdotes  for  the  philosophy  against  which  they  are  

situated  in  a  manner  clearly  indebted  to  the  historical  precedent  set  by  Nietzsche’s  

remarks  upon  the  interpenetration  of  philosophical  and  biographical  discourses.  

Accordingly,  his  own  intervention  into  the  history  of  Pre-­‐Socratic  thought  is  

introduced  as  itself  an  untimely  continuation  of  the  Nietzschean  project:  

Nietzsche  had  at  his  disposal  a  method  of  his  own  invention.  We  should  not  be  satisfied  with  either  biography  or  bibliography;  we  must  reach  a  secret  point  where  the  anecdote  of  life  and  the  aphorism  of  thought  amount  to  one  and  the  same  thing.  [  .  .  ]  Diogenes  Laertius,  perhaps,  in  his  best  pages,  had  a  foreboding  of  this  method:  to  find  vital  Aphorisms  which  would  also  be  Anecdotes  of  thought-­‐  the  gesture  of  philosophers.  The  story  of  Empedocles  and  Etna,  for  example,  is  such  a  philosophical  anecdote.  It  is  as  good  as  the  death  of  Socrates,  but  the  point  is  precisely  that  it  operates  in  another  dimension.  The  pre-­‐Socratic  philosopher  does  not  leave  the  cave;  on  the  contrary,  he  thinks  that  we  are  not  involved  enough  or  sufficiently  engaged  therein.  [  .  .  ]  The  Pre-­‐Socratics  placed  thought  inside  the  caverns  and  life  in  the  deep.  They  sought  the  secret  of  water  and  fire.12    

 

Deleuze  thus  radically  sidesteps  the  force  of  Laertius’  pileup  of  mutually  

incompatible  but  collectively  discrediting  narratives  in  favor  of  a  singular  reading  of  

Page 13: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     13  

one  story  as  a  telling  myth;  Empedocles’  leap  into  the  magma  is  not  a  symptomatic  

disclosure  of  some  pathological  incapacity  felt  to  be  lurking  within  the  doctrine  but  

a  case  of  eminently  admirable  consistency  between  theory  and  practice.  Rather  than  

taking  this  particular  philosopher  “from  behind,”  Deleuze  becomes  in  this  sense  

credulous  with  regards  to  a  tale  whose  veracity  he  neither  affirms  nor  engages  on  a  

historical  level.  Empedocles  gesture  becomes  a  literal  descent  into  the  ontological  

depths.  Deleuze  goes  on  to  align  Platonic  ascents  to  the  heights  and  Empedoclean  

descents  into  the  depths  as  anecdotes  attached  to  a  fundamental  vertical  axis  of  

orientation;  both  Plato  and  Empedocles  are  then  contrasted  with  an  alternative  style  

for  philosophy,  which  Deleuze  associates  with  the  Cynics  and  Stoics,  and  

triangulates  through  the  terms  “perversion”,  “surface”  and  “mixture.”  Yet  the  

ontology  he  invokes,  one  in  which  “in  the  depths  of  bodies  everything  is  mixture”  

and  there  is  neither  high  nor  low  but  only  the  ceaseless  combination  and  re-­‐

combination  of  materials,  is  in  fact  one  which  is  most  compatible  with  the  

Empedoclean  doctrine.13  My  intention  here  is  not  to  quibble  with  Deleuze’s  project  

on  behalf  of  a  historicist  rapprochement  in  which  Stoics  are  shown  to  be  more  akin  

to  the  Pre-­‐Socratics  than  Deleuze  is  prepared  to  grant  (though  one  could  do  that,  

and  indeed  he  himself  acknowledges  this  closure  in  an  aside),  but  simply  to  build  off  

of  what  remains  unresolved  within  this  compressed  sketch:  how  might  the  

combinatorial  ontology  of  Empedocles  be  brought  into  relation  with  the  fiery  

anecdote  of  his  death?    

One  model  for  how  to  do  this  comes  from  his  fellow  philosopher/poet,  

Lucretius.  The  generative  braiding  of  Empedoclean  doctrine  into  the  lurid  tale  of  

Page 14: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     14  

Empedocles’  death  might  be  lurking  behind  Lucretius’  own  decision  in  De  Rerum  

Natura  1.714-­‐733  to  describe  Empedocles’  ontology  in  terms  of  the  Sicilian  

landscape,  and  to  identify  the  “root”  of  fire  with  the  physical  location  of  Mount  Etna  

itself.  Describing  the  entire  school  of  thought  that  posits  primary  elements,  and  then  

proceeding  to  those  who  posit  a  fourfold  of  roots,  Lucretius  identifies  Empedocles  as  

“primis”  in  taking  this  position:  

[Quorum  Agragantinus  cum  primis  Empedocles  est  

Insula  quem  triquetris  terrarum  gessit  in  oris,  

Quam  fluitans  circum  magnis  anfractibus  aequor  

Ionium  glaucis  aspargit  virus  ab  undis,  

Angustoque  fretu  rapidum  mare  dividit  undis  

Aeoliae  terrarum  oras  a  finibus  eius.  

Hic  est  vasta  Charybdis  et  hic  Aetnea  minantur  

Murmura  flammarum  rursum  se  colleigere  iras,  

Faucibus  eruptos  iterum  vis  ut  vomat  ignis  

Ad  caelumque  ferat  flammai  fulgura  rursum.]14    

Empedocles  of  Agrigentum  is  

First  among  these:  the  three-­‐coast  island  bore  him  

Fouch  which  the  wide-­‐whorled  Ionian  splashes  and  sprays  

The  brine  of  its  green  waves;  the  swift  sea  funnels  

Into  a  strait  and  divides  with  its  waves  the  limits  

Of  Sicily  from  the  Italian  shore.  

Here  is  the  gaping  Charybdis;  here  the  grumbling  of  Aetna  

Warns  that  once  more  its  fiery  wrath  will  mount  

And  spew  from  its  jaws  the  bursting  and  violent  flames,  

Page 15: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     15  

Flashing  its  lightning  to  the  sky  once  more.    

Many  and  various  wonders  does  this  place  

Offer,  they  say,  for  people  to  visit  and  see;  

A  fruitful  land,  well  fortified  with  men;  

Yet  this  man  is  its  greatest  excellence-­‐  

Most  wondrous,  holiest,  worthiest  to  be  loved.  

For  out  of  his  godlike  heart  he  brought  forth  song,  

Revealing  in  verse  such  brilliant  findings  that  

It  seemed  he  was  not  born  out  of  human  stock.15  

 

The  hagiographic  praise  within  this  Lucretius  passage  is  made  particularly  

compelling  given  its  context:  a  catalogue  of  the  errors  of  the  elemental  ontologists  

who  precede  Lucretius’  master  Epicurus.  It  is  noticeable  that  Lucretius’  text  here  

transmits  the  same  basic  combination  of  elements,  so  to  speak,  also  present  within  

Diogenes  Laertius’  archive,  but  strips  them  of  pejorative  implication:  here  we  have  

the  fires  of  Etna  and  a  claim  about  Empedocles  as  a  kind  of  demi-­‐god  or  semi-­‐divine  

being  placed  into  a  suggestive  proximity,  but  no  suicidal  scenario  is  directly  

represented,  nor  is  there  a  bronze  sandal  to  be  seen.  Lucretius’  curious  tenderness  

for  Empedocles,  and  his  clear  respect  for  the  precedent  that  he  set  is  thus  figured  

both  positively  in  the  celebration  of  his  example,  his  writing,  and  his  personal  

excellence,  and  negatively,  in  the  absence  of  shaming  details  concerning  suicide.    

 

Empedocles  in  Early  Modern  England  

Page 16: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     16  

 

If  Lucretius’  text  provided  one  possible  model  of  how  it  feels  to  emotionally  

inhabit  an  elemental  ontology,  a  model  at  once  scandalous  and  beguiling  to  its  early  

modern  recipients,  a  more  homely  yet  altogether  more  representative  example  of  

Empedoclean  feeling  is  provided  centuries  later  by  Nicholas  Breton’s  poem  “Of  the  

foure  elements”,  from  the  collection  Britton’s  Bowre  of  Delights  (1591).  Keen  to  

assert  Breton’s  utility  in  demonstrating  period-­‐wide  gearshifts  in  prosody,  C.  S.  

Lewis  minces  no  words  regarding  the  value  of  his  art:  “Breton,  then,  is  such  a  poet  as  

the  historian  (not  the  general  reader)  sighs  for:  a  textbook  case,  a  human  

thermometer.”16  A  perfect  mid-­‐point  on  Lewis’  long  march  from  Drab  to  Golden,  

Breton’s  very  predictability  makes  him  exquisitely  useful  in  tracking  the  historical  

dissemination  of  Idées  recues.  If  the  reasons  for  this  poem’s  contemporary  obscurity  

are  about  to  become  painfully  obvious  to  the  first  time  reader,  Breton’s  modest  

effort  nevertheless  merits  quotation  in  full  for  the  diligence  with  which  it  scours  

every  combinatorial  possibility  within  the  Empedoclean  fourfold  formula:  

Of  the  Foure  Elements:  

The  Aire  with  sweet  my  sences  do  delight,    

The  Earth  with  flowers  doth  glad  my  heauie  eie,    

The  Fire  with  warmth  reuiues  my  dying  spirit,    

The  Water  cooles  that  is  too  hote  and  drie:    

The  Aire,  the  Earth,  the  Water,  and  the  fire,    

All  doe  me  good,  what  can  I  more  desire.    

Page 17: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     17  

Oh  no,  the  Aire  infected  sore  I  finde,    

The  Earth,  her  flowers  do  wither  and  decay:    

The  Fire  so  hote  it  doth  inflame  the  minde,    

And  Water  washeth  white  and  all  away.    

The  Aire,  the  Earth,  Fire,  Water,  all  annoy  me,    

How  can  it  be  but  they  must  needes  destroy  me.    

Sweete  Aire  do  yet  a  while  thy  sweetnesse  holde,    

Earth,  let  thy  flowers  not  fall  away  in  prime:    

Fire  do  not  burne,  my  heart  is  not  a  colde,    

Water,  drie  vp  vntill  another  time,    

Or  Aire,  or  Earth,  Fire,  Water,  heare  my  prayer,    

Or  slaye  me  once,  Fire,  Water,  Earth,  or  Aire,    

Hearke  in  the  Aire  what  deadly  thunder  threateth,    

See  on  the  Earth  how  euerie  flower  falleth,    

Oh  with  the  Fire  how  euery  sinewe  sweateth.    

Oh  howe  the  Water  my  panting  heart  appalleth.    

The  Aire,  the  Earth,  Fire,  Water,  all  do  grieue  me.    

Heauens  shew  your  power  yet  some  way  to  relieue  me.    

This  is  not  Aire  that  euerie  creature  feedeth,    

Nor  this  the  Earth  where  euerie  flower  groweth:    

Nor  this  the  Fire,  that  cole  and  bauen  breedeth,    

Nor  this  the  Water,  that  both  ebth  and  floweth.    

Page 18: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     18  

These  Elements  are  in  a  worde  enclosed,    

Where  happie  heart  hath  heauenly  rest  reposed.17  

Breton’s  curio  of  justly  forgotten  verse  is  helpful  because  of  its  very  pitch  perfect  

mediocrity,  the  mundane  exemplarity  with  which  it  exercises  the  ready  to  hand  

conceit  of  the  four  elements.  

 Yet,  as  I  hope  to  show,  the  seemingly  everyday  can  come  to  seem  

surprisingly  odd  the  longer  one  looks  at  it.  The  speaker  of  Breton’s  poem  

experiences  the  body  as  a  mixture  of  elements  which  both  support  and  potentially  

destroy  life,  and  which  emerge  through  the  affective  register  that  those  

decomposable  elemental  combinations  give  rise  to:  a  volatile,  shifting  drama  of  

one’s  own  material  composition  as  an  affective  assemblage,  swooping  through    

treacherously  unstable  mood  swings  before  coming  to  rest  in  reassuring  fixity  of  the  

final  lines.  Ringing  changes  upon  his  quadratic  set  of  handbells,  Breton’s  dutiful  

doggerel  manifests  an  unusual  symptom  at  its  point  of  closure:  the  rondelay  of  

combination,  mixture  and  recombination  encouraged  by  thinking  somatic  

materiality  as  assemblage  triggers  a  cumulative  anxiety  that  can  only  be  shored  up  

through  the  last  ditch  evocation  of  a  linguistic  fantasy  of  divine  textuality  as  

“heavenly  rest.”  That  is,  Breton’s  poem  imagines  enclosure  in  an  enduring  logos  that  

would  be  somehow  exempt  from  these  dizzying  cycles  of  formation  and  destruction.  

In  miniature,  and  in  the  very  teeth  of  its  own  mediocre  execution,  Breton’s  poem  

stages  the  ambient  conflict  between  the  relentless  blizzard  of  elemental  

Page 19: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     19  

recombination  proposed  by  Empedoclean  ontology  and  the  apocalyptic  

reassurances  offered  by  Christian  temporality.    

If  Breton’s  poem  gives  us  a  turgid  but  trustworthy  test  case  of  what,  with  

apologies  to  Lovejoy,  we  might  call  metaphysical  bathos,  the  same  ontological  

tension  between  material  schema  and  affective  outcome  had  already  surfaced  one  

year  earlier  with  far  greater  power  on  the  popular  stage  in  the  opening  lines  of  a  

famous  speech  from  Christopher  Marlowe’s  Tamburlaine  the  Great,  Part  One:  

 

Nature,  that  fram’d  us  of  four  elements  

Warring  within  our  breasts  for  regiment  

Doth  teach  us  all  to  have  aspiring  minds.    

(2.7.18-­‐20)18  

 

I  have  arrested  this  Marlovian  set-­‐piece  in  mid  flight,  before  it  comes  to  rest  in  its  

celebrated  closing  evocation  of  the  “sweet  fruition  of  an  earthly  crown.”  I  hold  us  

there,  strung  out  across  the  divide  between  the  war  within  the  breast  and  the  

aspirations  within  the  mind,  not  because  of  any  aversion  to  the  intoxicating  

resonance  of  these  mighty  lines.  Rather,  I  hope  that,  when  set  against  the  context  of  

the  Empedoclean  archive,  we  might  think  again  about  the  very  conventionality  of  

the  received  idea  which  functions  as  the  bedrock  premise  upon  which  

Tamburlaine’s  emotionally  activated  breast  heaves  and  from  which  his  theoretically  

aspiring  mind  leaps.    

Page 20: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     20  

A  tempting  possibility  must  be  eliminated  first.  Though  his  play  will  go  on  to  

consider  with  sadistic  intensity  the  consequences  of  choleric  excess,  Marlowe  is  not,  

here,  discussing  the  humoral  psycho-­‐physiology  of  blood,  phlegm,  yellow  bile  or  

black  bile  at  the  level  of  individual  temperament  as  theorized  by  Hippocratic  

medicine  and  transferred  via  Galen  into  centuries  of  medical  practice.  The  claim,  

which  Tamburlaine  assumes  as  much  as  he  asserts,  is  simpler,  and  more  basic  than  

that,  and  reaches  further  back  historically  and  lower  down,  towards  a  foundational  

habit  of  thought  which  modulated  across  classical,  medieval  and  early  modern  

writings  with  wildly  variable  status,  valence  and  inflection:  Empedocles’  doctrine  of  

the  four  elements.    

In  these  lines,  Tamburlaine  dynamically  experiences  the  human  body  as  an  

elemental  assemblage,  materially  composed  of  earth,  air,  fire  and  water,  set  

eternally  in  conflict  with  itself.  This  theory  arrives  coupled  with  its  own  affective  

signature,  the  feeling-­‐of-­‐the-­‐theory:  war  within  the  breast  as  reflected  back  within  

the  mind.  If  this  pairing  of  wartorn  breasts  with  aspirational  minds  suggests  a  

wellworn  and  dubious  couplet  (body/mind),  it  hardly  bears  restating  that  the  early  

modern  period  constitutes  the  cradle  of  both  their  most  decisive  scission  

(Descartes)  and  their  most  absolute  fusion  (Spinoza).19  Heard  at  the  present  

moment,  Tamburlaine’s  articulation  of  how  it  feels  to  think  of  one’s  self  as  an  

elemental  assemblage  also  models  the  confluence  of  two  separate  strains  currently  

operative  within  the  humanities:  the  emerging  focus  upon  new  materialisms  and  

ontology  in  both  metaphysics  and  intellectual  history  on  the  one  hand,  and  the  now  

ascendant  status  of  affect  studies  within  a  broad  array  of  hermeneutic  disciplines  on  

Page 21: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     21  

the  other.  Warring  for  regiment  within  the  academy,  practitioners  in  the  new  

materialisms  and  participants  in  the  affective  turn  squabble  over  their  relationship  

to  a  particularly  contested  and  heterogeneous  field  of  intellectual  ancestors.    

One  might  expect,  given  the  ostensible  independence  of  philosophical  

argument  on  the  one  hand  and  empirical  science  on  the  other  from  any  pressing  

need  for  intellectual  historical  ratification,  that  both  trends  would  simply  insist  

upon  their  contemporary  explanatory  stakes;  yet  practitioners  of  both  the  new  

materialisms  and  affect  studies  have  a  not  inconsiderable  stake  in  the  

demonstration  of  an  illustrious  early  modern  origin  for  these  developments,  and  

tend  to  converge  upon  Spinoza  as  a  crucial  antecedent  figure.  Spinoza’s  Ethics  has  

understandably  constituted  the  most  familiar  locus  classicus  through  which  to  assert  

the  precise  overlap  of  these  separate  domains  within  the  early  modern  period,  a  still  

point  at  which  affect  studies  are  a  crucial  component  of  materialist  ontology  and  

materialist  ontology  is  expressively  affective.    

Tamburlaine’s  war  within  registers  at  a  somatic  and  yet  also  affective  level  

the  cyclic  oscillation  of  Love  and  Strife  as  twinned  principles  of  creation  and  

destruction,  of  what  in  the  Deleuzian  register  would  be  termed  the  forces  of  

territorialization  and  deterritorialization  at  work  within  the  universe  outside  the  

body  and  the  microcosm  within.  That  is,  Empedocles  provides  both  a  theory  for  the  

emergence  and  decay  of  being  and  an  implied  emotional  stance  towards  that  theory:  

the  lived  sense  of  the  self  as  a  site  of  struggle,  as  a  place  of  potentiality  in  which  

competing  factions  struggle  for  dominance,  turning  the  body  into  a  violent  

Page 22: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     22  

processual  site  of  emergence  in  which  the  push-­‐pull  between  Love  and  Strife  is  

encountered  first  hand.  Which  means  that  Tamburlaine’s  martial  self-­‐scrutiny  can  

help  us  to  unpack  the  problem  of  theoretical  feeling,  and  in  particular,  can  provide  

at  least  one  notably  popular  figure  from  the  public  stage  wrestling  with  the  

emotional  consequences  of  a  materialist  ontology.  Tamburlaine’s  briskly  martial  

embrace  of  the  temperamental  consequences  of  Empedoclean  philosophy  

acknowledges  that  selves  and  souls  are  mortal,  temporary  formations,  doomed  to  

dissolve  and  recombine,  and  resolves  to  act  accordingly,  choosing  strife  and  playing  

to  win.    So  conceived,  Tamburlaine’s  set-­‐piece  offers,  among  others  things,  a  textual  

“soil  sample”  rife  with  what  one  might  term  elemental  sentiment.    

Tamburlaine’s  speech,  precisely  insofar  as  it  uses  a  combinatorial  ontology  to  

understand  how  emotions  arise  within  and  as  the  self,  also  models  precisely  this  

dynamic  of  methodological  double  exposure:  the  being  of  feeling,  the  feeling  of  

being  as  an  energetic  multiplicity.  Tamburlaine’s  martial  declaration  provides  an  

exemplary  early  modern  answer  to  the  question  of  how  it  feels  to  be  Empedoclean:  

aspirational.  Yet  the  theory-­‐and-­‐feeling  pairing  that  this  response  dramatically  

voices  also  flags  a  conceptual  problem  lingering  within  the  intellectual  archive  

which  Marlowe  inherited,  a  problem  that  pulls  downwards  from  aspiration  to  

despair,  which  suggest  that  there  is  a  more  than  accidental  relationship  between  the  

materialist  theory  of  elemental  composition  that  Empedocles  disseminated  and  the  

false,  fiery  narrative  of  his  suicide  upon  Mount  Etna  with  which  that  theory  was  

repeatedly  aligned.  The  suicidal  narratives  attached  to  both  Empedocles  and  

Lucretius  functioned  within  early  modernity  as  limit  cases,  biographical  arcs  

Page 23: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     23  

through  which  early  modern  persons  worked  through  the  imaginary  affective  

consequences  of  material  ontology,  offering  both  roadmaps  for  a  itinerary  of  life-­‐as-­‐

conquest  and  cautionary  stories  of  the  disintegrations  to  which  self-­‐understanding  

assemblages  might  succumb.    

If  the  war  within  the  breast  could  stimulate  aspiring  minds,  the  end  point  of  

materialist  composition  in  ultimate  de-­‐composition  could  also  destroy  despairing  

minds.  In  Doctor  Faustus,  Marlowe  returns  to  the  figuration  of  the  “war  within  the  

breast”  that  inspired  Tamburlaine  to  triumphalist  heights;  but  in  Faustus’  case  the  

proud  vaunt  has  gone  sour:  “Hell  strives  with  grace  for  conquest  in  my  breast.”  

(5.1.1471)20  The  putatively  Christian  framework  transvalues  what  was  a  material  

experience  of  elemental  metaphysics  into  an  allegory  of  sin  as  soul  sickness;  if  self-­‐

as-­‐war  was  intoxicating  for  Tamburlaine,  self-­‐as-­‐war  proves  horrific  for  Faustus  in  

its  implications.  Redoubled  in  the  allure  of  its  metaphysical  pathos  precisely  as  it  

slips  out  of  reach  as  a  source  of  security,  the  elemental  composition  of  bodies  

resurfaces  in  Faustus’  final,  crazed  disquisition:  

Ah,  Pythagoras’  metempsychosis,  were  that  true,  

This  soul  should  fly  from  me  and  I  be  changed  

Unto  some  brutish  beast,  

All  beasts  are  happy,  for,  whey  they  die  

Their  souls  are  soon  dissolved  in  elements,  

But  mine  must  live  still  to  be  plagued  in  hell.  (14,104-­‐109)21      

 

Page 24: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     24  

The  repudiation  of  Empedocles’  predecessor  Pythagoras,  made  definitive  by  

Faustus’  wistful  counterfactual  “were  that  true”,  is  no  sooner  voiced  then  we  see  a  

casually  authoritative  ratification  of  a  material  ontology  as  the  conceptual  bedrock  

upon  which  the  rejection  of  reincarnation  is  itself  based.  Pythagoras  is  wrong,  but  

Empedocles  is  right,  at  least  where  the  material  world  is  concerned.  Note  that  

Faustus  is  not  suggesting  that  animals  have  bodies  that  are  composed  of  elements,  

while  their  souls  are  separable  and  distinct;  even  in  the  midst  of  his  tour-­‐de-­‐force  of  

panic,  he  takes  care  to  insist  that  animal  souls  themselves  really  are  dissolved  back  

into  the  elements.  Yet,  against  this  backdrop  of  cyclic  patterns  of  material  

emergence  and  negation,  resolutely  Empedoclean  in  character,  the  Christian  soul  

now  suffers  in  an  eternal  state  of  exception.  Here  the  metaphysical  pathos  of  an  

Empedoclean  doctrine  arises  precisely  in  order  to  be  indulged  and  then  canceled  on  

behalf  of  an  orthodoxy  from  which  pagan  error  grows  seductive  precisely  insofar  as  

it  has  been  posited  as  proximate  yet  fatally  out  of  reach.  From  Tamburlaine’s  

warlike  confidence  in  the  implications  of  elemental  ontology  to  Faustus’  curiously  

simultaneous  proximity  and  alienation  from  its  explanatory  power,  Marlowe’s  

drama  traces  both  the  availability  and  the  limits  of  elemental  sentiment  as  a  

counter-­‐schema  to  Christianity.    

If  Tamburlaine’s  evocation  of  the  Empedoclean  mixture  leaps  upwards  with  

aspiration  and  offers  a  best  case  scenario  for  how  it  feels  to  feel  Empedoclean,  

Milton’s  posthumous  imprisonment  of  Empedocles  within  the  Paradise  of  Fools  as  a  

consequence  of  his  volcanic  suicide  in  Paradise  Lost  offers  us  a  striking  counter-­‐

plunge  downward  into  the  flames.  Milton  inherits  but  extends  the  polemical  

Page 25: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     25  

understanding  of  pagan  error  which  Marlowe  commenced  in  Doctor  Faustus,  and  in  

the  process  articulates  a  complex  causal  intersection  between  Empedoclean  

theories,  feelings,  and  feelings-­‐about-­‐the-­‐theory.  

Recasting  aspiration  as  folly  and  vanity  rather  than  martial  ambition,  in  

Paradise  Lost  Empedocles’  reach  towards  godhead  consigns  him  to  a  malingering  

posthumous  imprisonment  and  torture:  

All  who  have  thir  reward  on  Earth,  the  fruits  Of  painful  Superstition  and  blind  Zeal,  Naught  seeking  but  the  praise  of  men,  here  find  Fit  retribution,  emptie  as  thir  deeds;  All  th'  unaccomplisht  works  of  Natures  hand,    Abortive,  monstrous,  or  unkindly  mixt,  Dissolvd  on  earth,  fleet  hither,  and  in  vain,  Till  final  dissolution,  wander  here,  Not  in  the  neighboring  Moon,  as  some  have  dreamd;  Those  argent  Fields  more  likely  habitants,    Translated  Saints,  or  middle  Spirits  hold  Betwixt  th'  Angelical  and  Human  kinde:  Hither  of  ill-­‐joyned  Sons  and  Daughters  born  First  from  the  ancient  World  those  Giants  came  With  many  a  vain  exploit,  though  then  renownd:    The  builders  next  of  Babel  on  the  Plain  Of  Sennaar,  and  still  with  vain  designe  New  Babels,  had  they  wherewithall,  would  build:  Others  came  single;  he  who  to  be  deem'd  A  God,  leap'd  fondly  into  Ætna  flames    Empedocles,  and  hee  who  to  enjoy  Plato's  Elysium,  leap'd  into  the  Sea,  

Cleombrotus,  and  many  more  too  long,  Embryo's  and  Idiots,  Eremits  and  Friers  White,  Black  and  Grey  with  all  thir  trumperie.  (3.451-­‐475)22  

As  Hughes  and  others  have  noted,  Milton’s  immediate  source  for  this  section  of  

Paradise  Lost  comes  from  the  third  book  of  the  Divine  Institutes  of  the  early  Christian  

father  Lactantius,  titled  “The  False  Wisdom  of  the  Philosophers”:  

Page 26: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     26  

Many  therefore  of  them,  because  they  suspected  that  the  soul  is  immortal,  laid  violent  hands  upon  themselves,  as  though  they  were  about  to  depart  to  heaven.  Thus  it  was  with  Cleanthes  and  Chryssipus,  with  Zeno,  and  Empedocles,  who  in  the  dead  of  night  cast  himself  into  a  cavity  of  the  burning  Aetna,  that  when  he  had  suddenly  disappeared  it  might  be  believed  that  he  had  departed  to  the  gods.23  

Classifying  Empedocles  as  a  Pythagorean,  Lactantius  omits  the  detail  from  Laertius’  

of  the  telltale  sandal,  but  nonetheless  presents  an  entirely  earthbound  reduction  of  

this  bid  for  apotheosis.  At  once  a  fanatic  and  a  con  artist,  Empedocles  teeters  

unstably  between  a  sincere  but  deluded  victim  of  his  own  belief  system  and  

something  altogether  more  troubling:  a  cynical  narcissist  willing  to  die  purely  for  

the  sake  of  posthumous  fame.  In  leaping  “fondly”,  Empedocles  is  figured  as  self-­‐

indulgent,  besotted  with  vainglory  at  the  prospect  of  being  “deemed”  a  God.  But  the  

odd  lightness  of  this  locution  also  flags  a  kind  of  manic  cheerfulness  with  which  

material  self-­‐destruction  can  be  embraced.  This  imagined  “fondness”  curiously  

manifests  the  best-­‐case  psychological  outcome  of  the  materialist  accounts  of  death:  

since  death  is  simply  the  recombination  of  elemental  components  that  cannot  be  

destroyed,  there  is  no  real  loss  in  the  process,  only  changes  in  organization,  and  so  

we  ought  to  look  without  anxiety  at  the  prospect  of  our  own  deaths.24  That  this  

attitude  towards  death  is  merely  “fond”  in  the  negative  sense  of  “foolish”  connotes  

Milton’s  corrosive  and  satirical  attitude  towards  these  figures-­‐  but,  surprisingly,    

this  does  not  quite  carry  over  into  a  satire  of  material  ontology  itself.    

Taking  up  Lactantius’  stance  but  complicating  its  location,  Milton’s  

ecumenically  inclusive  Paradise  of  Fools  conjoins  Catholic  friars  and  monastic  

orders  together  with  ancient  philosophers  into  a  penal  colony  of  error  whose  formal  

Page 27: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     27  

contours  weirdly  recapitulate  the  very  Empedoclean  doctrine  they  work  to  

discredit:  the  lines  “All  th'  unaccomplisht  works  of  Natures  hand,  /Abortive,  

monstrous,  or  unkindly  mixt”  recall  Marlowe’s  own  evocation  of  Nature  as  the  

framer  of  material  and  elemental  mixtures,  but  here  Strife  has  seemingly  gone  to  

work  and  (penultimately)  undone  what  was  badly  joined  together  in  the  first  place.    

Fittingly,  in  Milton’s  poem  Empedocles  inhabits  a  space  whose  proximity  to  

the  whirl  of  Chaos  flags  the  kinship  that  Chaos  as  a  space  shares  with  the  ultimate  

loop-­‐point  fixed  within  the  cyclic  ontology  of  Empedocles:  the  triumph  of  strife  in  

the  dissolution  of  all  temporary  bonds  in  which  all  mixtures  are  canceled  and  

everything  returns  to  its  state  as  disjunctive  “roots”.  That  this  metaphysics  offers  

little  hope  for  human  ambitions  and  aspirations  is  still  apparent  in  contemporary  

articulations  of  Empedocles’  view.  Even  the  soberest  of  textual  editors  cannot  

restrain  himself  from  an  emotional  reading  of  this  metaphysical  picture  as,  at  best,  a  

mixed  blessing:  “Empedocles’  profound  pessimism  about  our  world,  like  the  rather  

bleak  metaphysics  which  he  propounds  in  his  poem,  is  designed,  in  part,  to  show  

that  the  ultimate  end  of  our  personal  identity  in  cosmic  dissolution  is  a  blessed  and  

happy  event.”25  

The  rhetoric  of  having  already  become  a  “god”  upon  earth,  which  is  the  

source  of  much  mockery  in  the  biographies,  might  itself  be  understood  not  as  

cynically  undercut  by  Empedocles’  own  imagined  death  in  Mount  Etna;  rather  the  

bodily  disintegration  forced  by  such  a  death  could  itself  be  a  direct  expression  of  a  

confidence  in  the  outcome  of  the  apparent  “destruction”  of  his  mixed  body-­‐  the  

Page 28: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     28  

sooner  that  mixture  is  canceled  out,  the  sooner  the  individual  ascends  to  an  

ontologically  prior,  and  thus  in  a  sense  “higher”  category,  of  the  roots  themselves.    

As  contemporary  Empedocles  textual  editor  and  scholar  Brad  Inwood  puts  it,  “On  

this  reading  the  immortality  is  achieved  by  the  loss  of  his  individual  identity  and  

return  to  the  gods  in  the  sense  of  the  six  basic  entities.”26    

Thus,  to  risk  a  reparative  reading  more  in  the  spirit  of  his  doctrine  than  in  the  

punitive  echoes  of  its  outcome,  Empedocles  suicidal  death  might  be  read  as  

something  quite  different  than  the  expression  of  an  inherent  despair  or  

miserabilism  which  a  material,  combinatorial  ontology  entails-­‐  rather,  it  might  be  

taken  to  demonstrate  a  total  devotion  to  the  aspirational  schema  of  recombination  

implicit  within  it.  Again,  Inwood  is  helpful,  “There  is  in  Empedocles  a  fundamental  

and  inevitable  ambivalence  about  the  world  of  our  experience:  it  is  a  world  of  woe,  

but  it  is  also  the  only  means  we  have  to  redeem  ourselves,  to  enlighten  ourselves,  

and  ultimately  to  restore  ourselves  to  the  ontological  purity  and  “immortality”  

which  is  only  achievable  under  the  rule  of  hateful  strife.”27  To  take  up  Milton’s  

pejorative  term  and  subject  it  to  a  reparative  transformation  from  an  ontological  

perspective,  to  achieve  a  certain  kind  of  “fondness”  for  the  material  facts  of  our  own  

transience  begins  to  look  like  something  other  than  suicidal  narcissism:  it  is  a  

rapprochement  with  the  terms  under  which  matter  is  loaned  to  us  by  the  universe,  

and  a  radical  acceptance  of  our  finitude.    

 

Conclusion:  Was  There  an  Empedoclean  Renaissance?  

Page 29: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     29  

 

To  repeat  my  refrain,  for  the  last  time:  What  does  theory  feel  like?  From  

certain  disciplinary  vantage  points,  to  even  pose  the  question  of  a  given  

philosophy’s  sentimental  payoff  is  to  miss  the  point.28  A  philosophy  is  true  or  false  

based  upon  its  arguments,  its  evidence,  its  consistency.  Yet,  as  Arthur  Lovejoy  

delicately  put  it,  “it  is  not  chiefly  as  a  science  that  philosophy  has  been  a  factor  in  

history.”29  Offering  some  answers  to  the  question  of  how  theory  feels,  intellectual  

history  has  been  taken  up  with  tracing  not  the  cases  for  or  against  a  belief  but  

simply  with  accounts  of  why  a  given  belief,  view,  or  doctrine  did  or  did  not  take  hold  

based  upon  the  satisfactions  it  offered,  or  crises  of  doubt  or  fear  it  palliated,  or,  for  a  

perverse  vanguard,  induced.  And  Lovejoy’s  contribution  to  the  intellectual  history  of  

early  modernity  has  been  particularly  felicitous  in  giving  us  a  portable  term  and  an  

implicit  theory—“metaphysical  pathos”-­‐-­‐  through  which  to  think  about  the  purchase  

of  philosophy  over  and  against  its  validity  or  coherence:    

Metaphysical  pathos  is  exemplified  in  any  description  of  the  nature  of  things,  any  characterization  of  the  world  to  which  one  belongs,  in  terms  which,  like  the  words  of  a  poem,  awaken  through  their  associations,  and  through  a  sort  of  empathy  which  they  engender,  a  congenial  mood  or  tone  of  feeling  on  the  part  of  the  philosopher  or  his  readers.30  

Taking  up  Lovejoy’s  teminology,  we  might  then  ask:  what  is  the  metaphysical  pathos  

of  materialism?    

 Congeniality  is  not  materialism’s  strong  suit.  Indeed,  those  of  another  party  

tend  to  forecast  despair  as  an  inevitable  consequence  of  adopting  or  endorsing  a  

materialist  philosophy:  the  materialist  is  imagined  as  someone  permanently  at  risk  

Page 30: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     30  

of  succumbing  to  a  downward  spiral  of  depression  and  sorrow  at  the  transience  and  

finitude  of  all  the  temporary  components  of  a  universe  from  which  all  

transcendence  has  been  bracketed  or  canceled.  As  William  James  warned  in  “The  

Sentiment  of  Rationality”:  

A  philosophy  whose  principle  is  so  incommensurate  with  our  most  intimate  powers  as  to  deny  them  all  relevancy  in  universal  affairs,  as  to  annihilate  their  motives  in  one  blow,  will  be  even  more  unpopular  than  pessimism.  Better  face  the  enemy  than  the  eternal  Void!  This  is  why  materialism  will  always  fail  of  universal  adoption,  however  well  it  may  fuse  things  into  an  atomistic  unity,  however  clearly  it  may  prophesy  the  future  eternity.  For  materialism  denies  reality  to  the  objects  of  almost  all  the  impulses  which  we  cherish.  31  

From  the  position  of  the  variously  materialist  stances  available  at  the  present  

moment-­‐-­‐  which,  if  not  quite  enjoying  “universal  adoption”,  can  feel  close  enough-­‐-­‐  

we  might  either  smile  or  groan  at  James’  forthright  disgust.  Yet  however  dubious  

this  certitude  might  seem,  it  rather  neatly  captures  a  historically  earlier  era  in  the  

reception  of  materialism,  and  precisely  the  one  which  has  detained  me  in  this  essay,  

and  which  has  proven  curiously  productive  of  late  as  a  subject  for  scholarly  inquiry:  

the  late  medieval  and  early  modern  dissemination  of  materialist  ontologies.    

My  title  is  both  a  deliberately  provocative  hat-­‐tip  and  a  clinamen-­‐esque  

swerve  away  from  the  ongoing  Lucretius  publishing  boom.  At  the  present  time,  the  

circulation  of  Lucretius  within  the  Renaissance  has  become  a  critical  “Just  So”  story  

about  emergence,  modernity,  and  what  one  might  term  literary  ontology.  By  way  of  

definition:  to  work  upon  literary  ontology  is  to  engage  the  question  of  literature  as  

matter,  and  to  inquire  into  the  particular  contours  of  its  being,  in  order  to  ask:  are  

the  material  conditions  of  literary  transmission  over  time  distinct  from  other  kinds  

Page 31: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     31  

of  transmission?  Need  the  total  set  of  modes  of  being  represented  within  literature  

necessarily  correspond  with  the  social  ontology  of  literature  as  sign-­‐system,  

assemblage,  or  practice  within  the  world  outside  literature?  Literary  ontology  is  not  

a  historicist  “history  of  the  book”  but  a  reframing  of  the  being  of  literature  that  

considers  literature  as  a  particular  kind  of  matter  whose  study  might  itself  alter  or  

revise  whatever  ontological  theories  are  ready-­‐to-­‐hand  in  novel,  unforeseen  ways.    

Thanks  to  the  very  strength  and  diversity  of  the  best  of  the  recent  

scholarship  upon  Lucretius,  it  is  now  retrospectively  clear  why  the  “Lucretian  

Renaissance”  offers  a  particularly  rich  nexus  of  theories  and  textual  exempla  

through  which  to  pursue  the  methodological  and  intellectual  historical  implications  

of  literary  ontology,  for  the  De  Rerum  Natura  provides  an  undeniably  influential,  yet  

also  localized  and  traceable  history  of  dissemination  for  an  irreducibly  hybrid  work  

of  philosophy-­‐and/as-­‐poetry.  As  Gerard  Passannante  and  Jonathan  Goldberg  have  

shown,  within  the  literary  ontology  of  his  De  Rerum  Natura,  a  combinatorial  axis  of  

atoms-­‐as-­‐letters  and  letters-­‐as-­‐atoms  lets  Lucretius  imagine  matter  itself  at  the  

atomic  level  as  a  kind  of  scripting,  subject  to  revision,  deformation  and  

recombination.  In  proposing  an  “Empedoclean  Renaissance”  as  a  conjoined,  

monstrous  twin  to  the  ongoing  scholarly  construction  of  a  Lucretian  Renaissance,  I  

am  hoping  to  re-­‐animate  the  Pre-­‐Socratic  precursor  from  the  double  occultation  of  

conventional  omnipresence  and  suicidal  self-­‐cancellation,  and  to  suggest  that  there  

are  unresolved  problems  concerning  the  place  of  negative  affect  and  suicide  within  

the  Lucretian  archive  which  might  be  broached,  if  not  illuminated,  by  placing  side  by  

side  these  two  materialist  philosopher-­‐poets  falsely  imagined  to  have  killed  

Page 32: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     32  

themselves.  More  than  kin  and  less  than  kind,  it  is  my  hope  that  the  pairing  of  

Empedocles  and  Lucretius  sparks  a  certain  productive  friction  across  the  

history/theory  DMZ  within  early  modern  studies  today.    

    But  the  melancholy  fact  of  the  disparity  between  these  two  partners  must  be  

faced.  In  the  case  of  Lucretius,  the  once  “lost”  author  stands  now  before  us  vividly,  

vitally  present  in  the  form  of  a  masterpiece  of  Latin  literature  which-­‐  however  

incomplete-­‐  can  be  studied  and  admired,  turned  and  turned  again,  and  richly  mined  

for  its  recurrences  across  subsequent  history.  In  the  case  of  Empedocles  we  have  

only  cinders,  scraps,  occasional  bursts  of  quotation  and  resonant  paraphrase.  The  

asymmetry  is  pronounced,  and  the  wind  has  scattered  the  letter-­‐atoms  of  

Empedocles’  material  texts  we  know  not  where.  The  once  great  works  are  gone,  lost  

long  before  the  men  and  women  we  now  regard  as  “early  modern”  were  born.  

Accordingly,  there  will  not  and  cannot  be  an  “Empedoclean  Renaissance”  to  set  

alongside  the  “Lucretian  Renaissance”  as  the  positive  production  of  a  critical  and  

literary-­‐ontological  archive  (short  of  an  archival  discovery  to  rival  the  already  near  

miraculous  recent  recovery  of  the  Strasbourg  papyrus).  Yet,  against  such  bitter  and  

presumably  irreversible  loss,  I  hope  that  the  poetic  remainders  I  have  here  

assembled  from  writers  as  disparate  as  Marlowe,  Breton  and  Milton  have  shown  

that,  at  the  level  of  the  metaphysical  pathos  with  which  early  modern  subjects  

encountered  their  own  being  as  somehow  composed  of  earth  and  air  and  fire  and  

water  there  was  an  Empedoclean  Renaissance.  Its  components  are  small,  but  

durable:  A  sandal  on  a  mountainside,  and  a  war  within  the  breast.    

Page 33: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     33  

 

 

 

                                                                                                               1  Gilles  Deleuze,  The  Logic  of  Sense,  Ed.  Constantin  V.  Boundas.  Trans.  Mark  Lester.  New  York:  Columbia  University  Press,  1990,  128.    2  Catherine  Wilson,  Epicureanism  at  the  Origin  of  Modernity,  Oxford:  Clarendon  Press,  2008;  Jonathan  Goldberg,  The  Seeds  of  Things:  Theorizing  Sexuality  and  Materiality  in  Renaissance  Representations,  New  York:  Fordham  UP,  2009;  Alison  Brown,  The  Return  of  Lucretius  to  Renaissance  Florence,  Cambridge:  Harvard  University  Press,  2010;  Gerard  Passannante,  The  Lucretian  Renaissance:  Philology  and  the  Afterlife  of  Tradition,  Chicago:  University  of  Chicago  Press,  2011;  Stephen  Greenblatt,  The  Swerve:  How  the  World  Became  Modern,  New  York:  W.W.  Norton  &  Co,  2011.  My  title  is  a  loving  nod  to  Gerard  Passannante’s  work,  which  inspired  this  essay.    3  See  Jonathan  Gil  Harris,  Untimely  Matter  in  the  Time  of  Shakespeare,  Philadelphia:  University  of  Pennsylvania  Press,  2011;  Alexander  Nagel  and  Christopher  Wood,  Anachronic  Renaissance,  New  York:  Zone  Books,  2010.    4  Sacvan  Bercovitch  “Empedocles  in  the  English  Renaissance”,  Studies  in  Philology,  Vol.  65  (No.  1),  1968,  67-­‐80.  5  Nineteenth  century  and  early  twentieth  century  textual  scholarship  of  Empedocles  divided  the  fragments  along  disciplinary  lines,  imagining  that  Empedocles  had  written  a  scientific  text  On  Nature  and  a  separate,  explicitly  religious  text  called  Purifications.  By  contrast,  recent  textual  scholarship,  bolstered  by  the  recovery  in  1999  of  a  relatively  intact  papyrus  with  Empedoclean  passages  that  range  from  the  one  the  domain  to  the  other,  has  shifted  entirely  towards  a  “single  work  hypothesis”,  regarding  Empedocles’  thought  as  necessarily  connecting  these  areas.  For  a  summary  of  the  textual  editing  history  of  Empedocles  and  the  consequences  of  the  Strasbourg  papyrus  for  the  “two  works  or  one?”  question,  see  Simon  Trépanier,  “The  Single-­‐Work  Hypothesis”,  Empedocles:  An  Interpretation,  New  York:  Routledge,  2004,  1-­‐15.  6  Empedocles,  The  Poem  of  Empedocles:  A  Text  and  Translation,  ed.  Brad  Inwood,  Toronto:  University  of  Toronto  Press,  2001,  217.  7  Ava  Chitwood,  Death  By  Phillosophy:  The  Biographical  Tradition  in  the  Life  and  Death  of  the  Archaic  Philosophers  Empedocles,  Hearaclitus,  and  Democritus,  Ann  Arbor:  The  University  of  Michigan  Press,  2004,  23.    8  Diogenes  Laertius,  The  Lives  of  the  Eminent  Philosophers,  Vol.  II,  Trans.  R.  D.  Hicks,  Cambridge:  Harvard  University  Press,  1925,  VIII.  67-­‐69,  383.    9  Diogenes  Laertius,  The  Lives  of  the  Eminent  Philosophers,  Vol.  II,  Trans.  R.  D.  Hicks,  Cambridge:  Harvard  University  Press,  1925,  VIII.  69-­‐71,  385.  

Page 34: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     34  

                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                         10  George  Bataille,  “Big  Toe”,  Encyclopedia  Acephalica,  London:  Atlas  Press,  1995,  87.    11  Chitwood,  56.    12  Gilles  Deleuze,  The  Logic  of  Sense,  Ed.  Constantin  V.  Boundas.  Trans.  Mark  Lester  New  York:  Columbia  University  Press,  1990,  128  

13  Deleuze,  130.    14  Lucretius,  On  the  Nature  of  Things,  ed.  W.  H.  D.  Rouse,  Loeb  Classical  Library,  1.716-­‐733,  Cambridge:  Harvard  University  Press,  1975,  58-­‐60.  15  Lucretius,  On  the  Nature  of  Things,  trans.  Anthony  Esolen,  Baltimore:  Johns  Hopkins  University  Press,  1995,  45.    16  C.  S.  Lewis  “Verse  in  the  ‘Golden’  Period”,  English  Literature  in  the  Sixteenth  Century,  New  York:  Oxford  University  Press,  1954,  481.    17  Nicholas  Breton,  Brittons  bovvre  of  delights  Contayning  many,  most  delectable  and  fine  deuices,  of  rare  epitaphes,  pleasant  poems,  pastorals  and  sonets  by  N.B.  Gent.  Imprinted  at  London  :  By  Richard  Ihones,  at  the  Rose  and  Crowne  neere  Holborne  Bridge,  (1591)  30.  

18  Christopher  Marlowe  “Tamburlaine  the  Great,  Part  I”,  Complete  Plays  and  Poems,  Ed.  E.d.  Pendry  and  J.C.  Maxwell,  London:  J.M.  Dent,  1976,  28.    19  Of  course,  such  shorthand  characterization  belies  the  complexity  of  each  author’s  archive.  Written  at  the  request  of  Princess  Elizabeth  of  Bohemia,  Les  Passions  de  L’Ame  (1649)  constitutes  Descartes’  attempt  to  re-­‐connect  these  disparate  elements  through  a  materialization  of  affect  as  the  work  of  animal  spirits,  infamously  localized  in  the  operation  of  the  pineal  gland.  See  Descartes  “The  Passions  of  the  Soul”,  The  Philosophical  Writings  of  Descartes,  Vol.  I,  Cambridge:  Cambridge  University  Press,  1985,  328-­‐405.    20  It  is  worth  noting  that  this  line  occurs  in  the  context  of  a  struggle  with  “despaire,”  signaling  the  affective  opposite  of  Tamburlaine’s  exultation.  Christopher  Marlowe,  “Doctor  Faustus”  The  Complete  Works  of  Christopher  Marlowe,  Vol.  II,  Ed.  Fredson  Bowers,  Cambridge:  Cambridge  University  Press,  1973,  219.    21  Christopher  Marlowe,  “Doctor  Faustus”,  The  Complete  Plays.  Eds.  Frank  Romany  and  Robert  Lindsey.  London:  Penguin  Books,  2003,  394.    22  John  Milton,  “Paradise  Lost”,  Complete  Poems  and  Major  Prose,  Ed.  Merritt  Y.  Hughes,  New  York:  Odyssey  Press,  1957,  269.  23  Lactantius,  “Of  the  False  Wisdom  of  the  Philosophers”,  Divine  Institutes:  Books  I  –  VII,  Trans.  Mary  Francis  McDonald.  New  York:  Catholic  University  of  America  Press,  1992.  Book  III,  Chap  XVIII,  443.  24  See  the  extended  Epicurean  account  of  death  and  mourning  in  the  Third  Book  of  De  Rerum  Natura:  the  non-­‐existence  of  the  dead  self  demonstrates  that  all  of  the  concerns  voiced  by  human  mourners  about  emotional  loss  miss  the  point.    Lucretius,  On  the  Nature  of  Things,  trans.  Anthony  Esolen,  Baltimore:  Johns  Hopkins  University  Press,  1995,  Book  III,  890-­‐900,  116.    25  Inwood,  57.    26  Inwood,  58.  27  Inwood,  63.  

Page 35: The Empedoclean Renaissance

Daniel  “The  Empedoclean  Renaissance”     35  

                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                         28  For  a  different  answer  drawn  from  a  different  critical  archive,  see  Rei  Terada  Feeling  in  Theory:  Emotion  after  the  “Death  of  the  Sublime”  Cambridge:  Harvard  University  Press,  2001.    29  Arthur  O.  Lovejoy,  The  Great  Chain  of  Being:  A  Study  in  the  History  of  An  Idea,  Cambridge;  Harvard  University  Press,  1936,  13.  30  Arthur  O.  Lovejoy,  The  Great  Chain  of  Being:  A  Study  in  the  History  of  An  Idea,  Cambridge;  Harvard  University  Press,  1936,  11.  31  William  James  “The  Sentiment  of  Rationality”,  Essays  in  Pragmatism.  New  York:  Hafner  Publishing,  1948,  3-­‐37,  17.