Top Banner
1 The duty of inquiry, or why Othello was a fool * ABSTRACT: This paper argues that Othello helps us adjudicate in an important epistemological debate, by showing that we have a distinctively epistemic duty of inquiry. Epistemologists who repudiate this duty cannot fully account for Othello’s epistemic situation, and thus have an impoverished ethics of belief. Appeals to Shakespeare in analytic philosophy tend to suffer from two drawbacks. First, examples from his plays are inevitably used for cosmetic purposes rather than for generating substantive arguments. Second, no attention is paid to the relevant text 1 . The unhappy result is that such appeals are unsatisfying to both the more literarily minded and the hardnosed philosopher, striking the former as glib and the latter as of marginal philosophical value. In this paper I show that taking Shakespeare seriously can help us do real philosophical work. I focus on Othello as someone particularly overworked in the cosmetic line (e.g., Russell 1971, Williams 1973). Shortly before Othello embarks on his selfeulogy and suicide, he addresses himself as ‘O fool! fool! fool!’ (5.2.322) 2 . I argue that this exclamation dramatizes a central feature of his epistemic situation, which can adjudicate in an important epistemological debate concerning our ethics of belief. Our ethics of belief specifies the epistemically good ways of forming and revising our beliefs. The godfather of this ethics, W. K. Clifford (1877), thought that its defining norm was the evidence norm: you should proportion your beliefs to your evidence. But he also thought that complying with this norm sometimes involves the epistemic duty of inquiry the duty to seek more evidence than one has.Clifford’s descendants ‘evidentialists’ keep the evidencenorm, but repudiate the duty of inquiry. According to them, if we have such aduty at all, it is always prudential or moral, never epistemic (e.g., Conee and Feldman 2004; Dougherty 2010). I argue here that Othello shows us that Clifford was right that we have an epistemic duty of inquiry. An ethics of belief which doesn’t feature this duty fails to accommodate important forms of epistemic appraisal. I first outline the Othello argument (§ 1) and then defend its three premises by appeal to textual evidence (§§ 25). I conclude by drawing out the more constructive implications of the argument: Othello gives us the beginnings of a positive account of when we have a duty of inquiry (§ 6). * Acknowledgements 1 Stanley Cavell (2003) is a notable exception in both these respects. 2 All references to the play are to Shakespeare (2005). C. Bourne and E. Bourne (Eds.) (In press) The Routledge Companion to Shakespeare and Philosophy, (Routledge) If you want to read the longer version, email me
12

The duty of inquiry or why Othello was a fool

May 12, 2023

Download

Documents

Veli Mitova
Welcome message from author
This document is posted to help you gain knowledge. Please leave a comment to let me know what you think about it! Share it to your friends and learn new things together.
Transcript
Page 1: The duty of inquiry or why Othello was a fool

1  

The  duty  of  inquiry,  or  why  Othello  was  a  fool*  ABSTRACT:   This   paper   argues   that   Othello   helps   us   adjudicate   in   an   important  

epistemological   debate,   by   showing   that   we   have   a   distinctively   epistemic   duty   of  

inquiry.   Epistemologists   who   repudiate   this   duty   cannot   fully   account   for   Othello’s  

epistemic  situation,  and  thus  have  an  impoverished  ethics  of  belief.    

Appeals  to  Shakespeare  in  analytic  philosophy  tend  to  suffer  from  two  drawbacks.  First,  examples  from  

his  plays  are  inevitably  used  for  cosmetic  purposes  rather  than  for  generating  substantive  arguments.  

Second,  no  attention  is  paid  to  the  relevant  text1.  The  unhappy  result  is  that  such  appeals  are  

unsatisfying  to  both  the  more  literarily  minded  and  the  hard-­‐‑nosed  philosopher,  striking  the  former  as  

glib  and  the  latter  as  of  marginal  philosophical  value.  In  this  paper  I  show  that  taking  Shakespeare  

seriously  can  help  us  do  real  philosophical  work.  I  focus  on  Othello  as  someone  particularly  

overworked  in  the  cosmetic  line  (e.g.,  Russell  1971,  Williams  1973).    

Shortly  before  Othello  embarks  on  his  self-­‐‑eulogy  and  suicide,  he  addresses  himself  as  ‘O  fool!  

fool!  fool!’  (5.2.322)  2.  I  argue  that  this  exclamation  dramatizes  a  central  feature  of  his  epistemic  situation,  

which  can  adjudicate  in  an  important  epistemological  debate  concerning  our  ethics  of  belief.    

Our  ethics  of  belief  specifies  the  epistemically  good  ways  of  forming  and  revising  our  beliefs.  

The  godfather  of  this  ethics,  W.  K.  Clifford  (1877),  thought  that  its  defining  norm  was  the  evidence-­‐‑

norm:  you  should  proportion  your  beliefs  to  your  evidence.  But  he  also  thought  that  complying  with  

this  norm  sometimes  involves  the  epistemic  duty  of  inquiry  -­‐‑  the  duty  to  seek  more  evidence  than  one  

has.  Clifford’s  descendants  -­‐‑  ‘evidentialists’  –  keep  the  evidence-­‐‑norm,  but  repudiate  the  duty  of  

inquiry.  According  to  them,  if  we  have  such  a  duty  at  all,  it  is  always  prudential  or  moral,  never  

epistemic  (e.g.,  Conee  and  Feldman  2004;  Dougherty  2010).    

I  argue  here  that  Othello  shows  us  that  Clifford  was  right  that  we  have  an  epistemic  duty  of  

inquiry.  An  ethics  of  belief  which  doesn’t  feature  this  duty  fails  to  accommodate  important  forms  of  

epistemic  appraisal.  I  first  outline  the  Othello  argument  (§  1)  and  then  defend  its  three  premises  by  

appeal  to  textual  evidence  (§§  2-­‐‑5).  I  conclude  by  drawing  out  the  more  constructive  implications  of  the  

argument:  Othello  gives  us  the  beginnings  of  a  positive  account  of  when  we  have  a  duty  of  inquiry  (§  6).

* Acknowledgements1  Stanley  Cavell  (2003)  is  a  notable  exception  in  both  these  respects.2  All  references  to  the  play  are  to  Shakespeare  (2005).

C. Bourne and E. Bourne (Eds.) (In press) The Routledge Companion to Shakespeare and Philosophy,

(Routledge)  

If  you  want  to  read  the  longer  version,  email  me  

Page 2: The duty of inquiry or why Othello was a fool

2    

1.  The  Othello  argument  

Let  me  first  distinguish  the  two  sides  of  the  debate  for  ease  of  reference:  

Evidentialism:     The  epistemic  status  of  a  belief  that  p  at  a  time  is  solely  fixed  by  the  belief’s  fit  with  the  believer’s  evidence  concerning  p  at  that  time.  

Clifford-­‐‑evidentialism3:    The  epistemic  status  of  a  belief  that  p  at  a  time  is  fixed  by  both  

(1)     the  belief’s  fit  with  the  believer’s  evidence  at  that  time,  and    

(2)     whether  the  believer  has  complied  with  her  duty  of  inquiry.  

The  Othello  argument  aims  at  showing  that  Clifford-­‐‑evidentialism  gives  us  a  better  ethics  of  belief  in  

virtue  of  adding  condition  (2).    

The  argument,  in  outline,  is  this:  

(P1)   The  following  two  claims  are  true:  

JUSTIFIED:    Othello’s  belief  that  Desdemona  is  unfaithful  is  justified  by  the  evidentialist’s  lights  (§  2).    

BLAME:     Othello’s  ‘fool’,  nonetheless,  epistemically  censures  the  belief  for  the  way  it  was  formed  (§  3).  

(P2)     The  evidentialist  can’t  account  for  BLAME  (§  4).  

(P3)     The  Clifford-­‐‑evidentialist  can  account  for  both  JUSTIFIED  and  BLAME  (§  5).  

(C)     So,  Clifford-­‐‑evidentialism  provides  a  better  ethics  of  belief.  

In  what  follows,  I  take  it  as  read  that  Othello  was  right  to  censure  himself  in  the  way  envisaged  by  

BLAME.  The  play  is  a  typically  Aristotelian  tragedy  in  which  a  virtuous  person  commits  an  error  of  

judgement  due  to  giving  in  to  passion.  If  there  were  nothing  epistemically  wrong  with  Othello’s  belief,  

then  no  error  of  judgement  would  be  committed4.  So,  if  we  think  that  his  fate  was  tragic  then  we  think  

that  his  epistemic  self-­‐‑censure  was  correct.  Hence,  we  need  the  richer  ethics  of  belief  that  Clifford-­‐‑

evidentialism  gives  us.  

2.  (P1):  JUSTIFIED  

In  this  section  I  argue  for  the  first  half  of  (P1):  Othello’s  belief  that  Desdemona  is  unfaithful  (henceforth  

‘BDU’)  is  justified  by  the  evidentialist’s  lights.    

   

                                                                                                                         3  This  label  is  meant  as  a  convenience,  rather  than  a  faithful  reflection  of  Clifford’s  view.  As  far  as  I  am  aware,  the  only  modern  Clifford-­‐‑evidentialist  is  Baehr  (2011).  The  argument  I  offer  here  is,  like  his,  a  friendly  amendment  to  evidentialism.  But  unlike  Baehr,  I  don’t  think  that  the  virtue-­‐‑machinery  can  fix  evidentialism  (see  fn.  6).  

4    Clearly,  an  error  of  judgement  is  a  normatively  richer  notion  than  a  false  belief.  The  evidentialist  can  point  out  that  Othello’s  belief  is  false.  But  this  isn’t  a  blameworthy  epistemic  defect,  so  it  would  not  explain  Othello’s  distinctly  normative  censure.  

Page 3: The duty of inquiry or why Othello was a fool

3    

2.1  The  evidence  for  BDU  

When  Iago  first  insinuates  to  Othello  his  ‘doubts’  about  Desdemona’s  fidelity,  Othello  himself  raises  the  

question  of  evidence:  

Be  sure  thou  prove  my  love  a  whore  –  

Be  sure  of  it.  Give  me  the  ocular  proof  (3.3.359-­‐‑60).  

And  he  presses  the  request  throughout  the  scene:  

Make  me  to  see’t,  or  at  least  so  prove  it  

That  the  probation  bear  no  hinge  nor  loop  

To  hang  a  doubt  on  (3.3.364-­‐‑366;  see  also  3.3.386  and  3.3.410)    

Iago  obliges  Othello  with  an  elaborate  seven-­‐‑stage  ‘proof’:  

(1)   Iago  instructs  Othello  (a  foreigner  in  Venice)  in  the  deceptive  and  promiscuous  ways  of  Venetian  women,  in  between  deftly  reminding  Othello  that  Desdemona  has  already  deceived  her  father  (3.3.203-­‐‑5).  

(2)   Iago  plays  on  Othello’s  misgivings  that  he  is  an  ‘unnatural’  match  for  Desdemona  in  virtue  of  his  race,  cultural  background,  and  age,  in  contrast  to  Cassio  who  is  of  her  culture,  her  age,  and  handsome  to  boot  (3.3.229-­‐‑39).    

 (3)     After  having  engineered  Cassio’s  dismissal  from  his  lieutenantship,  Iago  urges  Othello  to  delay  Cassio’s  reemployment  in  order  to  see  how  insistently  Desdemona  entreats  for  it  (3.3.251-­‐‑3).  She  does  so  avidly  (3.4.86-­‐‑96),  tragically  explaining  in  Othello’s  hearing  that  she  is  doing  so,  ‘for  the  love  I  bear  to  Cassio’  (4.1.224).    

(4)     Iago  relates  in  great  and  steamy  detail  how  Cassio  putatively  sleep-­‐‑talked  about  his  affair  with  Desdemona  (3.3.418-­‐‑24).  

(5)     Iago  tells  Othello  that  Cassio  has  explicitly  confessed  to  intimacy  with  Desdemona  (4.1.30-­‐‑34).  

(6)   Iago  has  Othello  witness  a  scene  in  which  Cassio  is  deriding  his  affair  with  Bianca,  a  courtesan,  while  Othello  thinks  (curtesy  of  Iago)  that  he  is  referring  to  Desdemona  (4.1.108-­‐‑154).  

(7)   Finally,  of  course,  there  is  the  handkerchief.  It  is  Othello’s  first  gift  to  Desdemona  and  he  has  asked  her  always  to  carry  it  about  her  (3.3.294).  Emilia  finds  it  and  gives  it  to  Iago  who  plants  it  in  Cassio’s  lodgings.  It  thereafter  features  as  evidence  in  three  ways:  

(a)     Iago  tells  Othello  he  has  seen  Cassio  wipe  his  beard  with  it  (3.3.437-­‐‑9).  

(b)     Othello  sees  it  in  Bianca’s  hands,  and  hears  her  say  that  it  clearly  belonged  to  another  of  Cassio’s  lovers  (4.1.146-­‐‑8).  As  Iago  helpfully  points  out  to  Othello,  this  means  that  Desdemona  has  given  the  precious  handkerchief  to  Cassio,  and  ‘he  hath  given  it  his  whore’  (4.1.169-­‐‑70).  

(c)     When  Othello  asks  Desdemona  whether  she  has  lost  it,  she  repeatedly  lies  to  him  (3.4.81,  83,  84)  and  refuses  his  insistent  requests  to  produce  it.  Her  refusals  are  accompanied  by  urgent  pleas  for  Cassio’s  re-­‐‑employment  (3.4.83-­‐‑86).    

Page 4: The duty of inquiry or why Othello was a fool

4    

These  are  the  pieces  of  evidence  on  which  Othello’s  belief  is  based,  as  he  makes  poignantly  clear  before  

he  literally  collapses  with  jealousy  and  grief:    

Handkerchief  –  confessions  –  handkerchief…  It  is  not  words  that  shake  

me  thus…  Confess-­‐‑handkerchief!  O  Devil!    

Othello  falls  in  a  trance  (4.1.36-­‐‑42).  

On  coming  to,  he  witnesses  the  conversation  between  Cassio  and  Iago  (6),  sees  the  handkerchief  in  

Bianca’s  hands  (7b),  and  BDU  is  irrevocably  cemented.    

2.2  BDU  is  justified  by  the  evidentialist’s  lights  

I  think  we  can  all  intuitively  appreciate  the  overwhelming  cumulative  force  of  these  pieces  of  evidence,  

which  gets  surprisingly  often  missed.  I  now  argue  that  BDU  is  also  justified  by  the  evidentialist’s  lights.  

  What  are  these  lights?  Evidentialism  is  wedded  to  the  following  notion  of  epistemic  

justification:    

Doxastic  attitude  D  toward  proposition  p  is  epistemically  justified  for  S  at  t  if  and  only  if  having  D  toward  p  fits  the  evidence  S  has  at  t  (Conee  and  Feldman  2004:  83).  

This  is  what  has  come  to  be  known  in  the  literature  as  ‘synchronic  justification’:  justification  is  solely  a  

matter  of  the  evidence  available  to  the  believer  at  the  time  of  evaluation.  All  that  is  meant  by  ‘evidence’  

are  considerations  which  speak  in  favour  of  the  truth  of  p.  Available  evidence  consists  of  these  

considerations  internalised:  ‘S  has  [e]  available  as  evidence  at  t  iff  S  is  currently  thinking  of  [e]’  (ibid.  

232).    

I  think  BDU  is  pretty  clearly  synchronically  justified.  To  begin  with,  notice  that  the  evidence  for  

BDU  is  of  two  kinds:  Iago’s  allegations  against  Venetian  women  (1),  his  tales  about  Cassio’s  dream  (4),  

confession  (5),  and  seeing  the  handkerchief  on  Cassio  (7a)  are  pieces  of  testimony.  The  rest  of  the  

evidence  is  of  the  ‘ocular-­‐‑proof’  kind.  Although  Iago  has  largely  engineered  the  latter,  Othello  still  

witnesses  Desdemona’s  entreaties  for  Cassio’s  re-­‐‑employment  (3),  Cassio’s  derision  of  his  affair  (6),  the  

handkerchief  on  Bianca  (7b),  and  Desdemona’s  repeated  lies  that  she  still  has  it  (7c).    

  Clearly,  not  all  of  the  above  pieces  of  evidence  weigh  equally.  The  first  three,  by  themselves,  are  

insufficient  to  justify  BDU.  But  they  do  reinforce  the  main  body  of  evidence  -­‐‑  the  handkerchief  (7),  

Cassio’s  putative  derision  of  Desdemona  (6),  and  his  supposed  confession  (5).  The  handkerchief  is  

obviously  the  weightiest  piece  of  evidence.  Regarding  the  others,  they  would  be  good  evidence  

provided  they  are  undefeated5  by  evidence  that  the  attestant  is  untrustworthy.  

  This  is  precisely  Othello’s  case.  He  has  no  evidence  against  Iago’s  trustworthiness.  Iago  is  

continuously  addressed  as  ‘good’  and  ‘honest’  by  everyone  in  the  play  (2.1.96,  97;  2.3.21,  39;  4.2.150).  

                                                                                                                         5    A  defeater  is  a  consideration  which  undermines  the  justification  of  the  belief  that  p,  by  being  either  evidence  against  p  itself  (a  ‘rebutting  defeater’,  Pollock  1987:  485)  or  evidence  that  my  evidence  for  p  is  not  a  reliable  indication  of  p’s  truth  (an  ‘undercutting  defeater’,  ibid.).  

Page 5: The duty of inquiry or why Othello was a fool

5    

Moreover,  Othello  and  Iago  have  known  each  other  for  a  long  time  and  have  fought  side  by  side  in  

many  battles  (1.1.26-­‐‑29).  Iago’s  testimony,  then,  is  an  undefeated  source  of  justification  for  BDU.  

  What  about  other  potential  defeaters?  The  only  candidates  are:  

• Othello’s  previous  trust  in  Desdemona,    

• Desdemona’s  own  testimony  that  she  is  innocent,    

• and  Emilia’s  testimony  that  Desdemona  is  innocent.  

Othello’s  trust  in  Desdemona  fails  to  undercut  the  synchronic  justification  of  BDU  simply  

because  he  barely  knows  her.  First,  he  has  just  married  her  (1.1.165-­‐‑6).  Second,  he  has  only  known  her  

for  nine  months  before  that  (1.3.85).  Third,  during  this  time  they  have  mostly  met  in  her  father’s  

presence.  Indeed,  their  courtship  has  needed  Cassio  as  a  go-­‐‑between  (3.3.95-­‐‑102).  Finally,  during  their  

short-­‐‑lived  marriage,  the  two  have  hardly  had  any  time  together.  So  little,  in  fact,  that  many  critics  

argue  that  the  play  closes  with  the  marriage  unconsummated  (Bloom  2005:  236).  

Desdemona’s  own  testimony  that  she  is  innocent  (4.2.34-­‐‑87  and  5.2.48-­‐‑76)  is  equally  

inauspicious  for  a  defeater.  For  starters,  it  is  itself  defeated  in  obvious  ways  once  Othello’s  trust  in  her  is  

undercut.  Moreover,  just  before  he  kills  her,  Othello  repeatedly  asks  her  to  swear  that  she  is  faithful  

(4.2.35-­‐‑7),  and  she  doesn’t.  All  she  says  in  reply  is  ‘Heaven  doth  truly  know  it’  (4.2.38),  a  phrase  that,  

lofty  and  dignified  as  it  is,  surely  sounds  evasive  and  incriminating  in  this  context.  Finally,  he  knows  

her  to  have  lied  both  to  her  father  and  to  himself.  

Emilia’s  testimony  fares  no  better.  First,  recall  that  Iago,  a  trusted  informant  and  Emilia’s  

husband,  has  warned  Othello  of  the  deviousness  of  Venetian  women.  Second,  Emilia’s  testimony  is  

negative:  she  has  not  seen  signs  of  intimacy  between  Desdemona  and  Cassio,  she  avers  (4.2.2-­‐‑10),  which  

is  compatible  with  the  existence  of  such  intimacy.  By  contrast,  Iago’s  testimony  and  some  of  the  

episodes  Othello  witnesses  constitute  positive  evidence  incompatible  with  there  not  being  such  

intimacy.  Third,  Othello  hardly  knows  Emilia  but  is  convinced  that  he  knows  Iago.  Finally,  (1)-­‐‑(7)  

comprise  a  far  more  comprehensive  body  of  evidence  than  Emilia’s  testimony.  They  are  evidence  about  

both  parties  to  the  putative  affair,  and  they  include  ‘ocular’  bits  as  well  as  testimony.    

 

BDU  emerges  as  justified  by  the  evidentialist’s  lights,  then:  Iago’s  testimony  is  undefeated,  Othello  has  

considerable  ‘ocular’  evidence,  and  the  only  candidates  for  defeaters  fail  to  defeat  BDU’s  justification.    

   

Page 6: The duty of inquiry or why Othello was a fool

6    

3.  (P1):  BLAME    

I  have  so  far  defended  the  first  half  of  (P1)  of  the  Othello  argument.  I  now  argue  for  the  second  half,  

BLAME:  Othello’s  ‘fool’  epistemically  censures  BDU  for  the  way  it  was  formed.  This  involves  showing  

that  ‘fool’  is  epistemic  (§  3.1),  normative  (§  3.2),  and  targets  Othello’s  evidence  for  BDU  (§  3.3).  

3.1  Othello’s  ‘fool’  is  epistemic  

When  Othello  calls  himself  a  fool,  he  has  some  serious  non-­‐‑epistemic  concerns  -­‐‑  a  dead  beloved,  for  

example.  So,  in  one  way  it  is  quite  perverse  to  suggest  that  he  is  fretting  about  his  epistemic  hygiene  at  

this  point  in  the  play.  And,  of  course,  I  don’t  mean  to  suggest  that  this  is  the  only  thing  he  is  worried  

about,  just  that  it  is  one  of  the  things  he  is  worried  about,  and  his  ‘fool’  expresses  this  epistemic  concern.    

Clearly  ‘fool’  doesn’t  express  moral  self-­‐‑reproach.  Moral  self-­‐‑censure  -­‐‑  directed  at  his  having  

committed  murder  or  at  having  wronged  Desdemona  -­‐‑  would  hardly  be  an  apt  explanans  of  ‘fool’.  The  

apt  epithet  here  would  be  ‘monster’  or  ‘villain’,  not  ‘fool’.  The  most  plausible  self-­‐‑censuring  attitude,  if  

it  is  to  concern  Desdemona  and  explain  his  use  of  ‘fool’  would  be  a  negative  attitude  to  his  having  

believed  that  of  her.    

To  labour  the  obvious,  the  two  primary  meanings  of  ‘fool’  are  consummately  epistemic.  The  

first  is  ‘One  deficient  in  judgement  or  sense,  one  who  acts  or  behaves  stupidly,  a  silly  person,  a  

simpleton.’  The  second  is  ‘One  who  is  made  to  appear  a  fool;  one  who  is  imposed  on  by  others;  a  dupe’  

(OED).  And  this  is  how  ‘fool’  and  related  epithets  are  used  throughout  Othello.  Iago  uses  ‘fool’  to  

describe  his  other  dupes  Roderigo  (‘Thus  do  I  ever  make  my  fool  my  purse’,  1.3.356)  and  Cassio  (‘this  

honest  fool’,  2.3.329).  This  use  is  not  peculiar  to  him.  For  instance,  in  an  interchange  of  quips,  Iago,  

Emilia,  and  Desdemona  pun  on  foolishness  as  an  antonym  of  wit,  on  the  one  hand,  and  as  a  synonym  of  

credulity,  on  the  other  (2.1.143-­‐‑55).    

3.2  Othello’s  ‘fool’  is  normative  

It  is  pretty  obvious  that  when  someone  calls  himself  a  fool,  he  is  in  the  business  of  self-­‐‑appraisal.  This  is  

corroborated  by  Iago.  Throughout  the  play,  he  uses  a  whole  range  of  related  epithets  to  capture  the  

gullibility  of  his  epistemic  victims.  The  epithets  are  clearly  normative.  For  example,  he  tells  us  that  he  

intends  to  

Make  the  Moor  thank  me,  love  me  and  reward  me,  

For  making  him  egregiously  an  ass  (2.1.302-­‐‑305,  my  italics).  

And  a  bit  earlier,  that  Othello  ‘will  as  tenderly  be  led  by  the  nose/  As  asses  are’  (1.3.393-­‐‑395).  Again,  

when  Othello  falls  into  a  fit,  Iago  kindly  comments:    

Thus  credulous  fools  are  caught  

And  many  worthy  (4.1.44-­‐‑5).  

Page 7: The duty of inquiry or why Othello was a fool

7    

The  derision  with  which  Iago  uses  synonyms  of  ‘fool’,  such  as  ‘ass’,  suggests  that  he  is  epistemically  

condemning  his  victims.  The  last  cited  lines  make  especially  vivid  both  the  normative  and  distinctly  

epistemic  character  of  ‘fool’,  by  simultaneously  reiterating  the  connection  between  folly  and  credulity  (l.  

44),  and  dissociating  folly  from  considerations  of  moral  worth  (l.  45).  

3.3  Othello’s  ‘fool’  targets  his  evidence  for  BDU  

That  Othello’s  ‘fool’  targets  the  evidence  for  BDU  becomes  obvious  when  we  notice  that  it  is  uttered  in  

response  to  Emilia’s  and  Cassio’s  disclosures  of  Iago’s  fraudulence  and  of  the  truth  about  the  

handkerchief.    

The  build-­‐‑up  to  the  disclosures  already  makes  it  plain  that  BDU  and  the  evidence  for  it  are  at  

issue:  

Othello…  Thy  husband  knew  it  all.  

Emilia     My  husband?  

Othello     Thy  husband.  

Emilia     That  she  was  false  to  wedlock?  

Othello     Ay,  with  Cassio…  

Emilia     My  husband?  

Othello     Ay,  ’twas  he  that  told  me  on  her  first,  

An  honest  man  he  is…  

Emilia     My  husband?  

Othello     What  needs  this  iterance,  woman?  I  say  thy  husband.  

Emilia  …   My  husband  say  she  was  false?  

Othello     He,  woman.  

I  say  thy  husband.  Dost  understand  the  word?  

My  friend,  thy  husband,  honest,  honest  Iago.  

…    

Emilia  …   O  gull,  O  dolt,  

As  ignorant  as  dirt!  (5.2.  138  –  162)  

The  first  two  repetitions  of  ‘My  husband?’  betoken  Emilia’s  gradual  awakening  to  Iago’s  true  part  in  the  

tragedy.  The  third  and  fourth  repetitions  are  steeped  in  ridicule  for  Othello’s  trust  in  Iago.  By  his  second  

reiteration  of  his  faith  in  ‘honest,  honest  Iago’,  Emilia’s  derision  bursts  uncontrollably  into  a  barrage  of  

epistemic  invectives  -­‐‑  gull,  dolt,  ignorant  as  dirt  –  all  (stronger)  synonyms  of  ‘fool’.    

Emilia’s  revelation  of  how  the  handkerchief  ended  up  with  Cassio  follows  (5.2.224-­‐‑228).  By  the  

time  Cassio  has  filled  in  the  last  details  (5.2.319-­‐‑22),  Othello  needs  no  more  external  epistemic  

chastising;  he  is  ready  to  do  it  himself.  That’s  when  he  cries  ‘O  fool!  fool!  fool!’  (5.2.322).    These  

revelations  make  clear  to  Othello  the  worthlessness  of  all  his  testimonial  evidence  for  BDU  and  

weightiest  piece  of  non-­‐‑testimonial  evidence.  What  could  his  self-­‐‑censure  target  other  than  the  belief  

Page 8: The duty of inquiry or why Othello was a fool

8    

whose  credentials  have  been  thus  exposed6?  

4.  (P2)  The  evidentialist  can’t  account  for  BLAME  

This  completes  my  defence  of  (P1)  of  the  Othello  argument:    

JUSTIFIED:  BDU  is  justified  by  the  evidentialist’s  lights;  yet    

BLAME:  Othello’s  ‘fool’  epistemically  censures  BDU  for  the  way  it  was  formed.    

I  now  argue  for  (P2):  the  evidentialist  can’t  make  sense  of  BLAME.  

  She  obviously  can’t  do  so  on  the  basis  of  the  available  evidence.  If  she  tries,  she  will  lose  her  

grip  on  JUSTIFIED:  if  the  available  evidence  does  not  support  BDU,  then  BDU  is  not  synchronically  

justified.  In  that  case,  the  evidentialist  cannot  account  for  both  JUSTIFIED  and  BLAME.  But  I  have  

argued  that  both  claims  are  plausible  (§§  2-­‐‑3).    

  But  she  also  can’t  make  sense  of  the  claim  in  terms  of  any  other  epistemic  notion.  For  

evidentialists  insist  that  evaluation  in  terms  of  anything  other  than  the  available  evidence  is  non-­‐‑

epistemic.  Here  are  Conee  and  Feldman,  evidentialism’s  most  fervent  champions:  

You  should  gather  more  evidence  concerning  a  proposition  only  when  having  a   true  belief  about  the  subject  matter  of   the  proposition  makes  a  moral  or  prudential  difference  and  gathering  more  evidence  is  likely  to  improve  your  chances  of  getting  it  right  (Conee  and  Feldman  2004:  189).  

This  means  that  they  can’t  account  for  BDU’s  epistemic  deficiency  in  terms  of  Othello’s  having  violated  

an  epistemic  duty  to  inquire,  since  they  think  that  all  such  duties  are  moral  or  prudential.    

But  the  evidentialist  can’t  account  for  Othello’s  censure  in  terms  of  any  more  general  normative  

epistemic  notion  either.  Here,  for  example,  is  Dougherty  using  ‘responsibility’  as  an  umbrella  term  for  

any  such  notion  that  goes  beyond  synchronic  justification:  

Each   instance   of   epistemic   irresponsibility   is   just   an   instance   of   purely   non-­‐‑epistemic  irresponsibility/irrationality  (either  moral  or  instrumental)  (Dougherty,  2010:  422).  

So,  according  to  evidentialism,  the  epistemic  status  of  a  belief  at  a  time  is  solely  fixed  by  the  believer’s  

evidence  at  that  time.  But  then,  once  a  belief  is  synchronically  justified,  the  evidentialist  has  no  room  for  

acknowledging  any  epistemic  (normative)  defect  in  it  at  that  time.  Since  Othello’s  belief  is  synchronically  

justified,  the  evidentialist  cannot  censure  it  as  epistemically  deficient.  She  can  thus  not  accommodate  

BLAME.  

                                                                                                                         6  The  only  contender  is  a  character  failing.  But  this  wouldn’t  make  sense  here.  Othello  is  a  universally  respected  general  who  has  risen  to  this  position  precisely  because  of  his  tactical  wisdom  and  cool  judgement,  and  whose  advice  on  important  state  decisions  is  continuously  sought.  (See,  for  example  Ludovico’s  praise  of  these  qualities  -­‐‑  4.1.257-­‐‑261.)    

Page 9: The duty of inquiry or why Othello was a fool

9    

 

5.  (P3)  The  Clifford-­‐‑evidentialist  can  account  for  both  JUSTIFIED  and  BLAME  

But  Clifford-­‐‑evidentialism  can.  This  is  the  view,  recall,  that  the  epistemic  status  of  a  belief  that  p  at  a  

time  is  fixed  by  both:    

(1)     the  belief’s  fit  with  the  believer’s  evidence  at  the  time,  and    

(2)     whether  the  believer  has  complied  with  her  duty  of  inquiry.  

Clifford-­‐‑evidentialism  accounts  for  JUSTIFIED  by  appeal  to  (1),  just  as  the  evidentialist  did.  But  

Clifford-­‐‑evidentialism  can  additionally  account  for  BLAME  by  appeal  to  (2).    

By  ‘inquiry’,  I  simply  mean  what  Clifford  did  -­‐‑  looking  for  more  evidence  for  and  against  the  

relevant  proposition.  When  do  we  have  an  epistemic  duty  to  look  for  more  evidence?  The  answer  is  

fairly  straightforward  in  cases  in  which  we  have  not  yet  formed  a  belief  but  are  inquiring  into  some  

topic.  Say  that  I  am  researching  newts  and  stumble  on  a  particular  aquatic  salamander.  I  have  some  

evidence  that  the  salamander  is  a  newt  and  some  evidence  that  it  is  not.  Since  I  want  to  form  a  belief  

either  way,  I  have  an  epistemic  reason  to  look  for  more  evidence.  I  could,  of  course,  have  pragmatic  and  

moral  reasons  to  inquire,  too.  Perhaps,  unless  I  found  out  whether  it  is  a  newt,  my  funding  would  be  

stopped  or  someone  would  be  tortured  to  death.  But  I  have,  in  any  case,  an  epistemic  reason  to  inquire  if  

I  am  researching  newts.    

The  second  tenet  of  Clifford-­‐‑evidentialism  implicitly  features  this  notion  of  a  reason  to  inquire  

but  with  a  slight  twist:  it  presupposes  that  we  can  have  such  a  reason  for  beliefs  which  we  already  hold.  

The  evidentialist  disputes  that  there  are  such  epistemic  reasons.  If  we  can  show  that  citing  these  reasons  

is  our  only  way  of  making  sense  of  Othello’s  epistemic  situation,  we  would  show  the  evidentialist  

misguided.  

The  best  way  of  getting  a  handle  on  such  reasons,  is  by  distinguishing  them  from  defeaters.  (If  

they  were  merely  defeaters,  of  course,  then  they  would  undermine  the  synchronic  justification  of  the  

belief.)  We  could  then  say  that  while  Othello’s  belief  is  undefeated  and  thus  synchronically  justified,  it  is  

nonetheless  epistemically  deficient  because  he  has  violated  his  duty  to  inquire  when  he  had  reason  to  

inquire.  

The  Clifford-­‐‑evidentialist  explanation  of  Othello’s  ‘fool’  then  is  that  Othello  is  censuring  himself  

for  having  violated  his  duty  to  inquire.  It  is  this  that  his  jealousy  prevents  him  from  doing;  hence,  his  

error  of  judgement.  And  he  realizes  this;  hence,  his  ‘fool’.    

Page 10: The duty of inquiry or why Othello was a fool

10    

6.  The  duty  of  inquiry  

What  triggers  the  duty  of  inquiry  in  Othello’s  case?  I  suggest  that  the  answer  lies  in  the  two  most  

conspicuous  features  of  his  epistemic  situation,  which  will  give  us  the  resources  to  start  on  a  positive  

account  of  our  duty  of  inquiry.    

First,  although,  as  I  have  argued,  Emilia’s  and  Desdemona’s  testimony  are  not  enough  to  

constitute  defeaters  to  BDU,  they  do  constitute  reasons  for  Othello  to  inquire.  At  a  minimum,  this  is  

because  each  of  them  contains  an  explicit  request  to  perform  an  easy  inquiry.    

The  earlier  ‘my  husband’  quote  (§  3.3)  already  points  in  this  direction.  There,  Emilia  was  asking  

Othello  to  reflect  on  the  source  of  his  evidence.  Here  she  is  again,  urging  him  to  reflect  and  see  that  

infidelity  simply  doesn’t  make  sense  in  light  of  Desdemona’s  character  (ll.  17-­‐‑19),  and  to  consider  BDU’s  

origin  (ll.15-­‐‑16):  

If  any  wretch  have  put  this  in  your  head,  

Let  heaven  requite  it  with  the  serpent’s  curse!  

For  if  she  be  not  honest,  chaste,  and  true,  

There’s  no  man  happy.  The  purest  of  their  wives  

Is  foul  as  slander  (4.2.15-­‐‑19).  

The  simplest  thing  Othello  could  have  done,  then,  is  to  reflect  on  whether  any  ‘wretch’  has  had  a  hand  

in  sowing  the  seed  for  the  belief  and  in  helping  sustain  it.  The  briefest  reflection  would  have  recalled  to  

him  that  it  was  all  started  by  Iago.  Indeed,  as  obvious  from  the  ‘my  husband’  quote  in  §  3.3,  he  realizes  

this  as  soon  as  he  is  forced  to  reflect:  ‘Ay,  ’twas  he  that  told  me  on  her  first’  (5.2.144).

Desdemona’s  request  to  inquire  is  even  more  explicit,  when  Othello  charges  her  with  having  

given  Cassio  the  handkerchief:  

No,  by  my  life  and  soul!  

Send  for  the  man,  and  ask  him  (5.2.48-­‐‑9).  

And  when  Othello  tells  her  he  has  seen  the  handkerchief  on  Cassio,  she  warns  him:  

He  found  it  then.  

I  never  gave  it  him.  Send  for  him  hither.  

Let  him  confess  a  truth  (5.2.66-­‐‑8).  

Crucially,  the  requests  to  inquire  concern  the  two  main  groups  of  Othello’s  evidence  –  Iago’s  testimony  

(Emilia’s  request)  and  the  adventures  of  the  handkerchief  (Desdemona’s  request).  As  the  end  of  the  play  

makes  painfully  clear,  the  recommended  inquiries  would  have  quickly  and  effortlessly  revealed  all.  

The  second  feature  of  Othello’s  situation  is  that  he  was  asked  to  inquire  into  an  epistemically  

very  central  belief,  a  belief  which  has  inferential  connections  to  many  of  his  other  beliefs.  Othello  

himself  makes  BDU’s  centrality  amply  clear.  The  first  seeds  of  doubt  planted  by  Iago,  Othello  looks  at  

Desdemona  and  exclaims:  

  Perdition  catch  my  soul  

Page 11: The duty of inquiry or why Othello was a fool

11    

But  I  do  love  thee.  And  when  I  love  thee  not,  

Chaos  is  come  again  (3.3.91-­‐‑93).  

And  a  little  later:  

If  she  be  false,  heaven  mocked  itself  (3.3.278).  

These  phrases  are  not  merely  a  tribute  to  Desdemona’s  centrality  to  Othello’s  life,  but  to  the  epistemic  

centrality  of  the  belief  in  her  fidelity.  They  indicate  BDU’s  importance  for  Othello’s  general  self-­‐‑  and  

world-­‐‑conception:  if  it  turned  out  to  be  false,  the  passages  suggest,  then  things  would  not  be  ordered  

the  way  he  supposed  them  to  be  (first  quote),  and  virtue  would  not  be  what  he  took  it  to  be  (second  

quote).  Many  of  his  other  beliefs,  in  other  words,  would  have  to  be  revised.  This  is  corroborated  by  the  

passage  cited  in  §  2.1,  where,  as  Othello  forms  BDU,  he  literally  collapses  into  incoherence  and  a  fit,  

both  signifying  the  power  of  BDU  to  destabilize  his  whole  world  view.    

Conclusion  

Othello  was  explicitly  asked  to  perform  an  easy  inquiry  into  an  epistemically  central  belief.  That  gave  

him  epistemic  reason  to  inquire.  Jealousy  does  not  prevent  him  from  going  with  the  available  evidence  (as  

the  evidentialist  says  we  should);  that  he  does  all  too  willingly,  as  Iago  shrewdly  anticipates.  It  prevents  

him  from  heeding  his  epistemic  duty  to  inquire.  In  this  consists  his  error  of  judgement.  And  it  is  this  

that  his  ‘fool’  poignantly  censures.    

This  explanation  is  not  available  to  the  evidentialist,  I  have  argued  here,  because  she  denies  that  

we  have  such  an  epistemic  duty.  The  denial  makes  her  incapable  of  accounting  for  Othello’s  epistemic  

situation  and,  hence,  makes  her  ethics  of  belief  an  impoverished  one.  Taking  Othello  seriously,  thus,  

adjudicates  in  an  important  debate  in  epistemology,  and  advances  it  by  suggesting  the  direction  in  

which  to  look  for  a  positive  account  of  our  duty  of  inquiry.  

   

Page 12: The duty of inquiry or why Othello was a fool

12    

Bibliography  Baehr,  J.  (2011).  Evidentialism,  Vice,  and  Virtue.  In  T.  Dougherty  (Ed.),  Evidentialism  and  Its  Discontents.  Oxford:  

Oxford  University  Press.  

Bloom,  H.  (2005).  An  Essay  by  H.  Bloom.  In  Shakespeare  (2005).    

Cavell,  S.  (2003).  Disowning  Knowledge  in  Seven  Plays  of  Shakespeare.  New  York:  Cambridge  University  Press.  

Clifford,  W.  K.  (1877).  The  Ethics  of  Belief.  Contemporary  Review  ,  29,  289-­‐‑309.  

Conee,  E.  &  Feldman,  R.  (2004).  Evidentialism.  New  York:  Oxford  University  Press.  

Dougherty,  T.  (2010).  Reducing  Responsibility.  European  Journal  of  Philosophy  ,  20  (4),  534–547.  

Pollock,  J.  (1987).  Deafeasible  Reasoning.  Cognitive  Science  ,  481-­‐‑518.  

Russell,  B.  (1971).  Truth  and  Falsehood.  In  The  Problems  of  Philosophy.  London:  Oxford  University  Press.  

Shakespeare,  W.  (2005).  Othello.  (B.  Raffel,  Ed.)  New  Haven  and  London:  Yale  University  Press.  

Williams,  B.  (1973).  Imagination  and  the  Self.  In  Problems  of  the  Self.  Cambridge:  Cambridge  University  Press.