Top Banner
Paper prepared for the Offene IB-Sektionstagung der DVPW, 4-6 Oktober 2017 Panel C9: Agency & International Order The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics. Reconstructing the Foundations of Global Governance Very first draft – Please do not cite without author’s permission – Comments are most welcome! Matthias Hofferberth University of Texas at San Antonio Department of Political Science and Geography One UTSA Circle San Antonio, TX 78249 matthias.hoff[email protected] Abstract: Despite the consensus that global governance increasingly becomes more com- plex, convoluted, and intricate, questions of agency, (i.e. which actors can become global governors and hence should be studied) are for the most part still framed in substantial terms. Whether it is states, institutions, or individuals, we ‘locate’ agency in particular entities which then exist, act, and influence outcomes as global governors qua definition. In other words, global governance lacks a social-theoretical grounding that allows us to go be- yond empirical anecdotes of agency diffusion. After reviewing how agency has been framed in global governance and beyond, the paper reverses the dominant ontology and conceptu- alizes agency in world politics in relational terms. As such, it discusses three requirements of agency – efficacy, corporeality, and intentionality – and assumes that each is established in social relations between rather than situated within actors. Such a perspective, it is then argued, can better capture dynamics and ambivalences of global governance and its inherent cSomplexities since it compels researchers to not just assume specific sets of discrete actors but to focus on relational processes through which their agency emerges in the first place and sustains over time. In particular, understanding agency as a relational disposition allows one to reconstruct and normatively engage with processes of agency diffusion to determine when, how, and why this happens in world politics instead of simply stating the emergence of new global governors. Reconstructing these processes reveals their political nature and al- lows us to discuss who should govern the world. In a broader perspective, theorizing agency then helps us (a) to develop more elaborated and social-theoretically grounded claims about world politics in order to (b) reconstruct the foundations of current manifestations of global governance and reveal its normative commitments. This potential of theorizing agency in relational terms for global governance is briefly illustrated by outlining how one could study multinational enterprises and their assumingly changing role. Keywords: global governance, agency, relationalism
26

The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics. Reconstructing the …colfa.utsa.edu/polisci-geography/docs/Bremen_-_Agency.pdf · 2019. 7. 17. · other words, global governance lacks

Dec 18, 2020

Download

Documents

dariahiddleston
Welcome message from author
This document is posted to help you gain knowledge. Please leave a comment to let me know what you think about it! Share it to your friends and learn new things together.
Transcript
Page 1: The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics. Reconstructing the …colfa.utsa.edu/polisci-geography/docs/Bremen_-_Agency.pdf · 2019. 7. 17. · other words, global governance lacks

Paper prepared for the Offene IB-Sektionstagung der DVPW, 4-6 Oktober 2017

Panel C9: Agency & International Order

The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics.

Reconstructing the Foundations of Global Governance

Very first draft – Please do not cite without author’s permission – Comments are most welcome!

Matthias Hofferberth

University of Texas at San AntonioDepartment of Political Science and Geography

One UTSA CircleSan Antonio, TX 78249

[email protected]

Abstract: Despite the consensus that global governance increasingly becomes more com-plex, convoluted, and intricate, questions of agency, (i.e. which actors can become globalgovernors and hence should be studied) are for the most part still framed in substantialterms. Whether it is states, institutions, or individuals, we ‘locate’ agency in particularentities which then exist, act, and influence outcomes as global governors qua definition. Inother words, global governance lacks a social-theoretical grounding that allows us to go be-yond empirical anecdotes of agency diffusion. After reviewing how agency has been framedin global governance and beyond, the paper reverses the dominant ontology and conceptu-alizes agency in world politics in relational terms. As such, it discusses three requirementsof agency – efficacy, corporeality, and intentionality – and assumes that each is establishedin social relations between rather than situated within actors. Such a perspective, it is thenargued, can better capture dynamics and ambivalences of global governance and its inherentcSomplexities since it compels researchers to not just assume specific sets of discrete actorsbut to focus on relational processes through which their agency emerges in the first place andsustains over time. In particular, understanding agency as a relational disposition allowsone to reconstruct and normatively engage with processes of agency diffusion to determinewhen, how, and why this happens in world politics instead of simply stating the emergenceof new global governors. Reconstructing these processes reveals their political nature and al-lows us to discuss who should govern the world. In a broader perspective, theorizing agencythen helps us (a) to develop more elaborated and social-theoretically grounded claims aboutworld politics in order to (b) reconstruct the foundations of current manifestations of globalgovernance and reveal its normative commitments. This potential of theorizing agency inrelational terms for global governance is briefly illustrated by outlining how one could studymultinational enterprises and their assumingly changing role.

Keywords: global governance, agency, relationalism

Page 2: The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics. Reconstructing the …colfa.utsa.edu/polisci-geography/docs/Bremen_-_Agency.pdf · 2019. 7. 17. · other words, global governance lacks

Introduction

Arguably, the main contribution of global governance, both as a framework to study and

make sense of world politics as well as a policy notion (Dingwerth/Pattberg 2006; Hof-

ferberth 2015, 2016a), has been to make scholars and practitioners aware of the fact that

it is no longer provided exclusively by states. Rather, the provision of public goods

at the global level today involves a plethora of different actors (Avant et al. 2010a;

Weiss/Wilkinson 2014b; Karns et al. 2015 (3)). Interestingly enough, however, while

revisiting constitutive debates from earlier years – in his essay on ‘The Actors in Interna-

tional Politics’, Wolfers (1962: 3) already stated that “[e]ven the identity of the ‘actors’

– those who properly can be said to perform on the international stage – is a matter of

dispute which raises not unimportant problems for the analyst, for the practitioner of

foreign policy, and for the public” – global governance for the most part only states the

outcome of diffused agency away from the nation state as a fact without providing much

insight into the process itself. In other words, global governance research, in order to jus-

tify its focus on other actors than the state, answers the question whether agency diffused

in affirmative terms to then study its implications without providing much discussion on

how and why this diffusion occurred in the first place (Finnemore 2014: 223).1

The emphasis on outcome rather than process, I argue, echoes a conceptual prefer-

ence of structure over agency, of substance over relations, which ultimately leaves global

governance in a peculiar spot. Not realizing its full potential in conceptual, intellectual,

and also normative terms, the paradigm, if it ever constituted one, arguably has lost

much of its original momentum in recent years (Pegram/Acuto 2015; Barnett/Sikkink

2008). More specifically, focusing on outcomes and implications of multiple actors in-

volved, and in particular the management thereof, in the provision of public goods has

created a normative-functionalist bias confirming the very notion of global governance,

leaving scholars and practitioners with the task how to accommodate and arrange dif-

ferent actors without raising more foundational questions of who should be involved in

the first place (Sinclair 2012). Put differently, taking the diffusion of agency for granted

and being concerned only with the consequences that follow from it has stripped away

the political and contested character of global governance, providing the notion with an

1 To be somewhat more balanced and less provocative in this opening statement, quite a few pieceswritten from a global governance perspective have been providing historically informed explanationsfor its emergence (Murphy 2014; Mitzen 2013; Ferguson 1999). However, even in those pieces, weoften find rather vague and open-ended explanations, simply linking global governance for example to“that other meta-phenomenon of the last two decades, globalization” (Weiss/Wilkinson 2014b: 208).

1

Page 3: The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics. Reconstructing the …colfa.utsa.edu/polisci-geography/docs/Bremen_-_Agency.pdf · 2019. 7. 17. · other words, global governance lacks

Matthias Hofferberth – The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics

‘there-is-no-alternative’ logic despite the fact that the legitimacy and accountability of

global governors remain problematic in many ways (Sell/Prakash 2004; Barnett 2015).2

Against this background, I argue that focusing on the processes of how new actors

emerge in current manifestations of global governance rather than discussing how to ac-

commodate them, could provide new momentum to the research agenda. In other words,

how and why matters and should be discussed before one simply assumes the whether

to advance research from there. None of this is to deny that we have seen an immense

amount of agency diffusion ever since and even before the notion has been entertained

in the report of the Commission on Global Governance (Commission on Global Gover-

nance 1995). However, as openly admitted in this very report, we need to consider it

as a politically motivated commitment to put into context and challenge it instead of

taking it as an empirical reality to ground problem-solving research on. Put differently,

against staggering evidence that we have truly experienced the emergence of new global

governors in recent years, global governance arguably has to engage in a different mode

of theorizing agency, provide a more elaborated account of the dispositions needed to

qualify as and be(come) an actor of world politics in the first place, and commit to the

reconstruction of processes in which agency became dispersed. Without such discussions,

we are confined to anecdotally report new instances of agency but are otherwise unable

to engage in normative discussions such as who should govern the world.3

In other words, theorizing how agency diffuses in global governance promises to ad-

vance the notion in conceptual terms and reveal its normative commitments at the same

time. Conceptually, we would be in a better position to understand when, how, and why

new actors emerge or fail to do so in certain contexts.4 In normative terms, we would

be able to reveal and reflect commitments that have accompanied and justified the emer-

gence of new actors to engage in discussions of who should ‘sit at the table’. In order

to contribute to this discussion, the paper is structured as follows. First, I review how

agency has been discussed in IR and global governance to reveal both the shortcomings

in these debates and the apparent need for further theorization. Second, focusing on

2 Consider for example the assumed lack of alternatives often advanced in the discourse on CorporateSocial Responsibility which, given their increased numbers and resources, sees no other option thanintegrating multinational enterprises into global governance (Whelan 2012).

3 The distinction between problem-solving and critical theorizing is taken from Cox (1981). However,while Cox himself situated his critical theory in a Marxist-inspired paradigm, in this paper I advancecriticism more in conceptual rather than substantial reasoning. For a substantial critique on globalgovernance, see among others Overbeek (2005).

4 By doing so, we would also ground IR and the current manifestation of global governance on moresolid historical grounding (Ferguson 1999; Murphy 2014; Mitzen 2013).

2

Page 4: The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics. Reconstructing the …colfa.utsa.edu/polisci-geography/docs/Bremen_-_Agency.pdf · 2019. 7. 17. · other words, global governance lacks

Matthias Hofferberth – The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics

efficacy, corporeality, and intentionality, I discuss and relate three dispositions of agency

from a relational perspective (Emirbayer 1997). Third, I outline how this perspective can

help us revitalize global governance and improve our understanding not only whether new

global governors emerged but also fill in the blanks on how and why this occurred. This

argument is illustrated by a short discussion on corporate agency and its emergence in

global governance.5

Approaching Agency in IR and Beyond

Despite (or maybe precisely because of) the fact that philosophers of agency, political

theorists, sociologists, and other social scientists have engaged with the subject at hand

in many ways, the concept of agency, for the most part, remains elusive and ill-defined.

Emirbayer/Mische (1998: 963), for example, argue that it has become “a source of in-

creasing strain and confusion in social thought” while Meyer/Jepperson (2000: 100) attest

an “unspecified core of actorhood [out of which] utilities and preferences said to produce

the entire social world” emanate which, in other terms, remains undefined. More specifi-

cally to IR, it has been argued that “[r]arely it is clear what agency is, what it means to

exercise agency, or who and what might do so” and that the subfield “has not grappled,

in a systematic manner, with the concept” (Wight 2006: 178). In fact, whether such

a (meta-)theoretical discussion is needed at all or not in a subfield defined in substan-

tial terms (i.e. a focus on potentially global cross-boundary encounters with difference)

remains contested (Jackson 2015: 942-5).

Arguably, one of the reasons for the unwillingness to engage with agency in theoret-

ical terms is the assumingly obvious nature of the concept. As such, both IR theory and

global governance have framed their debates on agency, for the most part, in substantial

terms and the reifications which we can make based on this commitment have “common-

sensical appeal [as] we look around our world and apparently see substances everywhere”

(Jackson/Nexon 1999: 299). More specifically, it also provides justification for what we

do and whom we study. Put differently, in need of demarcating their subject areas and

in order to develop a collective academic identity, IR theory and global governance trans-

lated questions of agency into debates on which actors mattered in world politics to claim

relevance for their work. Reproducing the state-centrism ingrained in Political Science

and the inside/outside logic of domestic vs. foreign policy that follows from it, early

accounts for example discussed whether agency resided exclusively within or also beyond

5 This illustration was chosen simply because it resonates with my other research interest.

3

Page 5: The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics. Reconstructing the …colfa.utsa.edu/polisci-geography/docs/Bremen_-_Agency.pdf · 2019. 7. 17. · other words, global governance lacks

Matthias Hofferberth – The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics

nation-states (Haas 1964). The fact that agency was simply ‘located’ in this early stage

and that no one challenged this, reveals a discipline committed from the beginning to a

substantialized understanding of agency. Despite different answers which entities should

be considered, the idea that individual actors held and exercised agency and that these

actors were to be considered as such qua their ontological nature prevailed and ingrained

itself into our thinking of world politics (Epstein 2013: 290-6).

Albeit in different ways and arguments, later proponents of IR theory and their con-

tending paradigms perpetuated this substantialized notion of agency. Speaking broadly,

these paradigms continued to locate agency in particular entities without providing

(meta)theoretical arguments to justify their respective focus on nation-states (Gilpin

1984: 301), institutions (Keohane 1989: 6), or societal actors (Moravcsik 1997: 516).

As such, agency was derived from ontological assumptions about the nature of world

politics relative to your preferred theory. At the same time, all paradigmatic contenders

conceptualized “actors in international relations [as] those entities capable of putting forth

demands effectively” (Haas 1964: 84). In other words, different theories advanced differ-

ent claims about relevant determinants of international relations and used those, albeit

relative and challenged by others, to specify which actors one should consider. Case stud-

ies based on these assumptions revealed how the agency of these actors indeed mattered

and were then used to retrospectively justify theoretical claims made in the first place.

As such, different IR theories disagreed on which actors one should consider but shared

the same substantial notion of agency. Not surprisingly, the question of which entities

determine world politics became one of the major staging grounds for paradigmatic and

hence lasting disagreement in the field (Jackson/Nexon 2009: 917).

Ironically, the contribution of Wendt (1999: 193-237) and his attempt to provide a

more solid social theory foundation for agency did not solve the problem since it ultimately

remained committed to the very same notion of agency. In order to distinguish actors

from structure to then relate both, he maintained that agency is “a function of certain

inherent, ‘given’ properties of the agent” (Epstein 2013: 296), which he understood to be

located within and limited to nation states. This move allowed Wendt to restate the state

as the main actor in world politics, relay his theory to Waltz and others, and present

his approach as a serious contender in IR theory. In terms of an advanced discussion

of agency, though, both Wight (2006: 181-6) and Epstein (2013: 297-9) rightfully point

out that Wendt’s contribution fell short in terms of developing a full-scale alternative

to theorize agency in alternative ontological terms. As such, committed to the same

substantialism advanced by those theories he challenged, Wendt’s approach rather fueled

4

Page 6: The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics. Reconstructing the …colfa.utsa.edu/polisci-geography/docs/Bremen_-_Agency.pdf · 2019. 7. 17. · other words, global governance lacks

Matthias Hofferberth – The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics

the paradigmatism haunting discussions on agency in IR until today instead of solving or

at least significantly advancing them (Kratochwil 2000)

Against this backdrop, scholars of global governance came in during the 1990s and

argued in favor of broadening IR’s notion of agency to include actors other than the

nation-state (Weiss/Wilkinson 2014b; Barnett/Sikkink 2008). Revisiting Keohane/Nye

(1973), they argued that a significant amount of governance on the global scale was

provided by non-state actors. Within the newly emerging paradigm of global governance

research, the activities of these actors were described in detailed case studies, in which

international organizations, NGOs, multinational corporations, think tanks, and epistemic

communities all made a difference and hence were framed as ‘global governors’ (Avant et al.

2010a). Other than their alleged influence in world politics, though, there was no further

theoretical discussion why one should engage with particular entities. Thus, while greatly

expanding our empirical understanding of world politics, global governance also did not

provide a discussion of agency in theoretical terms as it merely advanced anecdotes of

diffused agency previously not considered. Instead of providing theoretical answers to

questions of agency, then, global governance’s empirical emphasis on non-state agency

only aggravated the issue. Ultimately, the question “which actors truly have agency –

which actors are agents of global governance” still remained unanswered as plethoras of

different case studies on particular actors were advanced (Hoffmann/Ba 2005: 255).

Arguably, the reluctance both in conventional IR theory and in the global governance

paradigm to engage with agency in theoretical terms and their persistent reliance on

substantial notions of the concept can be explained in two ways. On the one hand,

mundane, intuitive notions of agency exist and influence our thinking. As an “everyday

concept”, we do not see the need to reflect and theorize it even though its structure and

dispositions must be made explicit in order to go beyond simplistic accounts of particular

entities making a difference in particular situations (Gilbert 1989: 3-5). As Fleming

(2016) elaborates, this is specifically true in IR theory which has to come up with more

sophisticated notions of agency. While we easily connect to action-sentences such as

‘country X / NGO Y / company Z did so and so’ and thereby take their agency for granted,

there seems to be little theoretical reflection on the concept itself. On the other hand,

the belief in individual human agency supporting substantial notions is deeply rooted in

Western philosophy and our culture of modernity. Against the overwhelming forces of

socialization and social structure, we like to reassure ourselves that individuals, including

us, can make a difference, if only to give meaning to our existence which, otherwise looks

rather somber and bleak (Meyer/Jepperson 2000; Archer 2000).

5

Page 7: The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics. Reconstructing the …colfa.utsa.edu/polisci-geography/docs/Bremen_-_Agency.pdf · 2019. 7. 17. · other words, global governance lacks

Matthias Hofferberth – The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics

Whatever the precise reasons may be, IR’s reluctance to theorize agency and its

habit to substantialize it has consequences for how we study world politics. At least

since Waltz (1959) if not earlier, we conveniently agree to locate agency on different

levels and frame it in individual or aggregated terms. While studying agency at the

individual level might be richer and more authentic, we contend that the collective level

provides more comprehensive and ultimately more important answers for a discipline

interested in global issues (Singer 1961: 89). Further theoretical debates whether and

how such an aggregation of agency is possible (List/Petit 2006; List/Pettit 2011; Rovane

2014) are sometimes referred to in IR but for the most part are solved on pragmatic

and/or paradigmatic grounds: As the study of world politics, in it’s different theoretical

approaches, it has long been decided that IR has to engage with collective actors and the

respective ones are determined by the theoretical framework advanced (Verba 1961: 95).

In other words, once defined as making a difference and located in a particular entity,

it is the consequences and not the dispositions of agency that IR scholars are interested

in as we continue to ascribe agency to all sorts of different entities without considering

what constitutes their agency in world politics in the first place. By doing so, we sidestep

theoretical discussions on agency as we conveniently treat it as a definitive capacity of

actors (individual or collective) to determine outcome (Jackson/Nexon 1999: 296-301).

Once reduced to this truism of making a difference, we locate agency in diverse phe-

nomena, ascribing the ability, among others, to “[states], corporations, unions, charities,

provinces, intergovernmental organizations, rebel groups, drug cartels, the global market

and the international community” (Fleming 2016: 18).6 In the end, we base agency on

semantics as we contend that any “entity that is able to serve as the subject of a sen-

tence with an active verb – an entity constituted as the author of a particular action or

set of actions that is performed ‘in the name of’ the actor” can exercise agency (Jack-

son 2003: 55). In order to approach agency in theoretical terms, the next section will

introduce and discuss three general dispositions of agency – efficacy, corporeality, and

intentionality – that define discussions outside (Giddens 1984; Emirbayer 1997; Archer

2000; Meyer/Jepperson 2000; List/Pettit 2011) and within IR (Ringmar 1996; Cederman

1997; Jackson 2004; Wight 2006; Franke/Roos 2010; Epstein 2013). Arguing that a re-

lational ontology has the potential to best capture the dynamics of global governance

(Qin 2016; Jackson/Nexon 1999), these dispositions will be introduced and discussed as

products of social interaction rather than fixed properties or essence.

6 Obviously, this list is not exhaustive as never will be. The lack of referring to individuals in his listcan be explained by Fleming’s deliberative focus on collective entities.

6

Page 8: The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics. Reconstructing the …colfa.utsa.edu/polisci-geography/docs/Bremen_-_Agency.pdf · 2019. 7. 17. · other words, global governance lacks

Matthias Hofferberth – The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics

Three Dispositions of Agency in World Politics – A Relational Take

With different labels floating around in the discourse, as well as different traditions and

intellectual sources referenced to support its claims, it is fair to say that relationalism

as an alternative ontological framework recently gained recognition and momentum in

IR and beyond.7 Described as an “ontology of entanglement” (Zanotti 2017), hailed as

the “new [and improved] constructivism” (McCourt 2016), and even proposed to serve as

the new core for Political Science in general (McClurg/Young 2011), it seems that more

and more scholars in IR and beyond either explicitly draw on relationalism (Qin 2016;

DeMars/Dijkzeul 2015; Sending et al. 2015) or at least connect to it through its roots in

American Pragmatism as they engage in substantial debate on agency on global gover-

nance (Hofferberth 2017; Avant 2016). While diverse in the topics covered, scholars with

an affinity towards relationalism seem to agree that IR would benefit from an ontology

in which world politics and agency therein are conceptualized in processual and dynamic

terms since this potentially offers a way forward for an otherwise substantially confined

discipline caught up in its own paradigms (Jackson/Nexon 1999, 2013).

Following these broader remarks, scholars drawing from a relational ontology stress

the social and hence dynamic character of human existence. More specifically, in a ter-

minology first advanced by Dewey/Bentley (1949), agency is framed in trans-actional

rather than self -actional or inter-actional terms. Whereas self-action and inter-action

reflect ontological stances “where things are viewed as acting under their own powers”,

trans-action argues that “our very capacity to act in the first place originates in rela-

tions” (Dewey/Bentley 1949: 108). As such, in a trans-actional framing, “[t]there is no

pure ‘individual’ action (or agency) outside, beside, or prior to social relations” (Dèpel-

teau 2008: 63). Relations are more than just mere “link[s] between structure (situation,

context, condition) and social actors (with their dispositions, motivations, reasons, inten-

tions)” as they are considered to have ontological primacy and come first to constitute

both structure and actor (Donati 2011: 31). In other words, it is “interactions between

the social actors and the polity [which] are mutually constitutive all the way through,

right down to the actors’ core selves” (Epstein 2013: 289). Relating this perspective to

the three dispositions of agency – efficacy, corporeality, and intentionality – I argue that

7 Anecdotal evidence for this momentum is that other references than those below could have beenused to advance the argument that relationalism has been recognized, discussed, and applied morefrequently in IR in recent years. I am hesitant to call this new focus on relations a turn, though,because, (a) its contours are not quite delineated and spelled out just yet, and (b) one could arguethat IR already experienced too many turns recently.

7

Page 9: The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics. Reconstructing the …colfa.utsa.edu/polisci-geography/docs/Bremen_-_Agency.pdf · 2019. 7. 17. · other words, global governance lacks

Matthias Hofferberth – The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics

each of them originates in and is reproduced through relations instead of preceding those

(Meyer/Jepperson 2000: 106-8). Consequentially, agency is granted, not possessed – it is

constituted in relations as “the very terms or units involved in a transaction derive their

meaning, significance, and identity from the (changing) functional roles they play within

that transaction” (Emirbayer 1997: 287).8

First, efficacy as Wirkmächtigkeit in this perspective can still be closely associated

with the notion ‘to make a difference’. More specifically, this dimension of agency separates

actors from structure because the latter is passive whereas the former performs action and

triggers change. In other words, agency “‘breathes life’ into passive, inert substances [. . . ]

that otherwise would remain perpetually at rest” and reflects the potential to intervene

in the world out there (Emirbayer 1997: 294). In order to exercise agency, we thus need

to be capable, at least in potential terms, to influence other actors, the social structure

around us, and the processes we are involved in.9 This direct, agentic capacity, though,

stems from interaction and cannot be reduced to instances in which actors successfully

‘made a difference’. Rather, we can obviously fail in our attempts to exercise efficacy

which is ultimately based on relational recognition.

Following this train of though, efficacy in relational terms rests on potentiality. While

we presume actors “to be able to deploy (chronically, in the flow of daily life) a range of

causal powers, including that of influencing those deployed by others to ‘make a difference’

to a preexisting state of affairs”, this only happens if said others accept and recognize

the causal power of a particular entity (Giddens 1984: 14). Hence, if we are interested

in agency, “[w]e should not look for boundaries of things but for things of boundaries”

(Abbott 1996: 857). For such things of boundaries, the primacy of relations does not limit

but constitute efficacy since the very ability to make a difference plays out relationally.

In other words, efficacy does not reside in pre-defined entities nor represents an inherent,

self-contained actor disposition. Rather, actors develop efficacy as nexi of relations and

only appear to us as actors if they become stabilized for a certain duration of time. In

other words, efficacy emerges and exists only in relational configurations.10

8 This emphasis on the dynamic nature of human existence should not be confused with the notionof permanent change, though. Stabilized agency can equally well translate into long-term stasis, asJackson/Nexon (1999: 314) elaborate.

9 Note that efficacy in this vein represents a gradual and not an either/or disposition. For example,students arguably have less agency in the process of grading than faculty yet they persistently influencegrades in their favor through negotiation.

10 Granted, due to prior processes of ‘yoking’, most if not all social interaction, already features a “soupof preexisting actors and actions”. However, the efficacy of these actors “ford it with difficulty and

8

Page 10: The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics. Reconstructing the …colfa.utsa.edu/polisci-geography/docs/Bremen_-_Agency.pdf · 2019. 7. 17. · other words, global governance lacks

Matthias Hofferberth – The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics

Second, agency is a function of being anchored and located in time and space. With-

out such a connection to the here and now, the possibility of making a difference is

not perceivable. This anchoring in the present is provided through corporeality (Kör-

perlichkeit) which constitutes the “complex of physio-chemical interactions” between an

individual body and its environment (Dewey 1931: 306). In other words, actors must

be able to relate to others and this ability is endowed through the relational quality of

corporeality. Through it, actors establish connections to other actors and their respec-

tive environment and engage in interventions into the world-out-there (Emirbayer/Mische

1998: 970-93). In other words, we can consider agency only when it becomes physically

perceivable instead of representing ‘merely’ a mental act and that transition depends on

being able to connect to the world out there (Franke/Roos 2010: 1069).11

At the same time, though, corporeality should be understood in metaphorical rather

than literal terms since the latter imply a voluntaristic moment of independent agency

above and beyond the relational existence of things. As such, instead of committing the

crime of reification and turning social phenomena and their bodies into ‘things’ which

assumingly do not require further explanation, corporeality also has to be thought of

something that is being granted and hence originates in relations (Cederman 1997: 20).

In other words, the very subjectivity of any actor is defined through social formation

(Joas 1996: 167-83). As such, individuals as well as collective actors continuously develop

their corporeality in social terms and in interaction as they experience a resistant and

rigid reality to respond to. Once legally, socially, or otherwise incorporated – literally

“embodying” an entity through a “process of personation” (Jackson/Nexon 2004: 281) –

“the parties of ongoing transaction [considered in the ontological perspective of relation-

alism] can just as well be communities, firms, or states as they can be individual persons”

(Emirbayer 1997: 289).12 In other words, it is the ‘idea of acting’ and the emergence of an

‘internal decision structure’ which can serve as a substitute for the individual body and

its physiological connections to the outside world. As such, developing a ‘body image’ as

a notion and acting in awareness of one’s body in relation to others, together with the

in it [may] disappear” as “new actors, new entities, new relations among old parts” establish theirefficacy and thereby emerge out of interaction (Abbott 1996: 863).

11 This distinction between mental and physical acts is different from IR’s distinction between ‘realaction’ and rhetoric or ‘cheap talk’. Uttering a promise or a thread, for example, represents a physicalact in this perspective. Mental acts, on the other hand, refer to action solely carried out “in foro

interno” (Rescher 1996: 50).12 Considering the semantics of Organizational Studies for a moment, it is revealing in this vein that we

refer to individual parts of hierarchical structures as ‘organs’.

9

Page 11: The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics. Reconstructing the …colfa.utsa.edu/polisci-geography/docs/Bremen_-_Agency.pdf · 2019. 7. 17. · other words, global governance lacks

Matthias Hofferberth – The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics

capacity to activate it, constitutes corporeality, both for ‘primary actors’ (i.e. individuals)

as well as collective actors (Joas 1996: 175-6).13

Third and finally, relationalism also reconsiders the notion of intentionality and ar-

gues that it must be further unpacked. Speaking broadly, intentionality, in some form or

another, captures and reflects the “common-sense notion of purposive action” (Coleman

1990: 13). Without such motivation and alleged purpose, actors would not become ac-

tive in the first place as agency reflects more than mere behavior. In other words, “[i]n

full-fledged action – unlike mere behavior – the motivational aspect must always play a

role, since some element of volition will always be present here.” (Rescher 1996: 54). As

such, actors actively “exercise control” and this becomes meaningful in the sense that the

author of the action is not motivated by instinct or reflex, but rather pursues a certain

goal (Gilbert 1989: 24). In other words, agency essentially includes the ability to asso-

ciate meaning to an action, however subjective and ‘wrong’ in the eyes of others. Instead

of reducing it to the rational maximization of interest (i.e. the logic of consequentialism

and the homo oeconomicus) or the normative adherence to certain standards of appro-

priate behavior (i.e. the logic of appropriateness and the homo sociologicus), agency in

relational terms reflects the intentional pursue of aims through meaningful action rather

than reflexive, instinct-driven, and stimuli-generated behavior. The nature and the origin

of these intentions, however, are cast in relational and hence open-ended terms as actors

are considered to represent something more than calculating automatons or ‘norm dopes’

(Joas 1996: 145-66).14

More explicitly, motivation, interest, and purpose, so the argument goes, remain in-

determinate until they are discovered in relations. Such discoveries are made possible

because of actors-in-the-making constantly reflect upon them. Drawing on Mead’s dis-

tinction between ‘I’ and ‘Me’ (Mead 1967 [1934]: 173), the conceptual notion of intention-

ality is supplemented by the idea of reflexivity understood as the aptitude to relationally

consider one’s own actions as objects in the eyes of others and thus adapt them in the

light of interacting with others (Franke/Roos 2010: 1069). Put differently, intentionality

in relationalism is not derived from fixed interests held by actors prior to interaction.

Rather, actors constantly reflect on what they want and how they can achieve it in social

13 The students in their attempts to negotiate grades mentioned above, for example, are far more likelyto influence faculty if they act collectively as a larger student body. To do so, they need to organizeand ‘speak with one voice’.

14 Consider for a moment the Latin origin of ‘interest’ in this context, which literally translates into ‘beingin-between’ and hence arguably cannot logically be perceived as a fixed disposition of individual actors(Hellmann 2017: 18).

10

Page 12: The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics. Reconstructing the …colfa.utsa.edu/polisci-geography/docs/Bremen_-_Agency.pdf · 2019. 7. 17. · other words, global governance lacks

Matthias Hofferberth – The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics

situations which implies that their motivation and purpose continue to change in said

interaction.15 Interaction in this perspective thus reflects more than just the exchange of

preferences. Rather, interaction represents contested sites of determining otherwise in-

determinate boundaries of meaning and feasible action (Hofferberth/Weber 2015: 84-9).

Instead of following pre-defined scripts, whether rational or normative, the outcome of

actors engaging in reflexive processes are never predetermined with agency representing

open-ended probing rather than stimulus-driven scripts. In other words, agency in its

intentional, purposive dimension “involves defining that which is as yet undefined, rather

than simply making a different selection from a reservoir of situation components that

are either already defined or have no need of definition” (Joas 1996: 133). Therefor, the

intentions associated with an action are not independent from said action but evolve in

the process thereof:

“[A]ction [can] not be perceived as the pursuit of preestablished ends, abstracted from con-crete situations, but rather that ends and means develop coterminously within contexts thatare themselves ever changing and thus always subject to reevaluation and reconstruction onthe part of the reflective intelligence.”(Emirbayer/Mische 1998: 967-8)16

Advanced in order to debunk its ontological counterpart of substantialism, relational-

ism offers a different take on efficacy, corporeality, and intentionality. Taken together,

agency emerges from relations and is always ‘performed’ within loose and ever-changing

configurations in which temporarily stabilized entities recognize or challenge each other’s

ability to influence outcomes (Avant et al. 2010b: 8-9). While not providing any substan-

tial answers as to which entities can be considered as actors in any particular instance

of world politics, this discussion can still be applied to the study of world politics and

global governance and, arguably, contributes to the theoretical elaboration of agency in

these contexts. Put differently, discussing these dispositions help us consider agency in

potential, theoretical rather than in actual, substantial terms. More specifically, consid-

ering its dynamic, processual nature, relationalism allows the scholar to approach her or

15 Going back to our student example from above, we can only assume the motivation of studentsapproaching faculty to reconsider their grades because they might not be fully aware of it either orit will change in the interaction of talking to the faculty and further reflecting upon it. Whether itis getting into law school, pleasing one’s parents, or simply feeling treated unjustly, we can conclude,however, that grades matter to them and that they pursue the intention to receive better ones.

16 Obviously, different social situations feature different degrees of stability and hence involve differentdegrees of reflexivity on behalf of the actor. This is reflected in the prominent conceptual distinctionbetween routine and crisis situations in American Pragmatism which is introduced to capture howmuch we (have to) reflect upon our interests. However, said distinction is gradual and situationsof both types have to be consciously reflected upon in order to clarify and adapt what we hope toachieve. In the end, both in routine and crisis situations, it is through changing our intentions whileacting by which “we surprise ourselves by our own action” as we as the author of our action alsoremain subject to it (Mead 1967 [1934]: 174).

11

Page 13: The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics. Reconstructing the …colfa.utsa.edu/polisci-geography/docs/Bremen_-_Agency.pdf · 2019. 7. 17. · other words, global governance lacks

Matthias Hofferberth – The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics

his research with no a priori assumptions on the substance of agency. This and other

implications for the study of global governance are spelled out in the following section.

Contributions and Implications for the Study of Global Governance

More so than any other paradigm of world politics, global governance is concerned with

“who governs the globe” and advances the claim that different entities have become global

governors (Weiss/Wilkinson 2014a; Avant et al. 2010a). As such, the diffusion of agency

can easily be considered as one if not the most axiomatic claim of global governance,

which, as a research agenda, significantly expanded empirical studies into world politics

(Barnett/Sikkink 2008). At the same time, as argued above, the paradigm lacks a theoret-

ical discussion on the dispositions and qualities these actors share. As such, in its efforts

to overcome IR and provide alternative answers to who governs the world, the framework

ironically reproduced the subfield’s substantial notion of agency: Whether it is the UN or

other international organizations, NGOs, think tanks, or multinational enterprise, global

governance, given its abstract and indeterminate nature, for the most part post hoc re-

ports on and thereby substantializes agency. Arguably, this is one of the reasons the first

generation of global governance research lost its momentum. To regain it, the paradigm

has to develop its own conceptualization of agency. Relationalism in particular has the

potential to reinvigorate debate and provide new insights, just as Jackson/Nexon (1999)

argued almost 20 years ago:

“We hold that in many circumstances, a focus upon processes and relations rather thansubstances will enable scholars to formulate better theories of world politics, explaining phe-nomena – for example, globalization, interdependence, and other areas [such as global gov-ernance] which involve unit-change – that fit uneasily into substantialist frameworks.”(Jack-son/Nexon 1999: 292)

To unpack and substantiate this claim as well as spell out its implications, it is worthwhile

to consider the notion of governance and its inherent complexity for a moment. Just as

Rosenau/Czempiel (1992) argued, it is categorically different from government since it is

not (only) organized and provided in any formal or hierarchically fashion. As such, new

actors indeed become involved constantly but may perform their governance activities

only episodically. In other words, providing public goods or engaging in the setting of

rules does not constitute their main commitment. Rather, it might be a side-effect of

being engaged in other activities (e.g. economic activities and the ensuing self-regulation

enterprises have initiated recently). Given that efficacy, corporeality, and intentionality

can be established in different ways and do not only reside in formally recognized actors,

12

Page 14: The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics. Reconstructing the …colfa.utsa.edu/polisci-geography/docs/Bremen_-_Agency.pdf · 2019. 7. 17. · other words, global governance lacks

Matthias Hofferberth – The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics

previously unrecognized entities might become global governors in one instance (assuming

they meet the requirements to exercise agency by being recognized as such) to then retreat

to the back again and no longer engage in the provision of public goods (Avant et al.

2010a).

In addition to the dynamics that follow from different entities becoming involved

and disengaged in governance over time, consider the broad range of different activities,

both formal and informal, that can be included under this broad label. Since governance

“encompasses a variety of cooperative problem-solving arrangements and activities that

states and other actors create in an effort to resolve conflict, serve common purposes, and

overcome inefficiencies in situations of interdependent choices”, we can imagine diverse

contributions such as generating information and knowledge, agenda-setting, the negotia-

tion, creation, implementation, and enforcement of rule systems, compliance monitoring,

and many more particular activities (Karns et al. 2015 (3): 25-35).17 As different entities

perform their different activities, they advance different assets, resources, and capacities

and hence justify their agency in different ways. While some actors find their agency

recognized through setting the agenda and through moral authority (e.g. civil society

and advocacy groups), others hold the means to ensure compliance and enforcement (e.g.

states and supranational organizations) while others bring particular resources to the ta-

ble (corporations). To essentialize any of these qualities or the agency of involved, though,

seems to do injustice to the indeterminate and situational nature of global governance and

the diversity of entities and activities involved (Porter 2009: 87-9).

Against what has been discussed so far, global governance can be understood as the

sum of myriads of configurations of actors engaging and disengaging on different issues

and we need to develop conceptual tools to consider the dynamics of agency diffusion.

Instead of relying on a priori assumptions which actors matter in general terms, a rela-

tional perspective helps us go into our empirical investigation unbiased and reconstruct

when, how, and why actors emerge or fail to do so. Relationalism, in other words, offers

an ontology that allows us to focus on processes in which agency emerges without sub-

stantializing their outcome. The main rational behind assuming a relational perspective

on agency then is simply that we cannot know for sure which entities become involved

in any particular governance configuration for any particular issue until after our studies.

More specifically, since interaction in governance arrangements remains indeterminate as

17 Note the functional-normative bias in the quote. If one expands the notion of governance beyondthe provision of public goods to also include public bads, the range of activities would equally expandsignificantly.

13

Page 15: The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics. Reconstructing the …colfa.utsa.edu/polisci-geography/docs/Bremen_-_Agency.pdf · 2019. 7. 17. · other words, global governance lacks

Matthias Hofferberth – The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics

they unfold (Sabel/Zeitlin 2010), it is rather likely that agency between different entities

shifts over time. As such, the liberating move to open up the notion of governance to

include a larger diversity of activities beyond legal-formal ruling carried out by a larger

range of actors with different constituencies, resources, interests, and world views, pushes

us towards considering agency in its relational dimension – after all, “governing globally is

never a solo act” and one can reasonably assume that the line-ups of the bands as well as

their members keep changing (Finnemore 2014: 223). Put differently, since “governance

involves the creation of new issues, new interests, new communities, and new modes of

action by creative agents”, as well as the ongoing sustainment of their agency (Avant et al.

2010b: 9), relationalism’s most important contribution to the study of global governance

is to make us aware of and enable us to understand its dynamic and processual nature,

reconstruct processes in which agency emerged and diffused, theorize them in terms of

their implications for governance, and ultimately assess them in normative terms.

Focusing on dynamics and process should not be confused with permanent change,

though. To be clear, stable lineages of agency exist in global governance just as they

exist elsewhere in social interaction and human existence. States obviously still matter

and global governance advocates are keen to admit this upfront (Karns et al. 2015 (3):

8-9). However, global governance plays out in evolving social contexts whose boundaries

and opportunities as well as normative commitments and foundations are not fully estab-

lished yet. The political dimension of contesting, negotiating, and, for the time being,

defining these boundaries and foundations remains poorly understood if we only apply

substantial frameworks of ontology (Jackson/Nexon 1999: 296-9). In other words, agency

as the ability to engage in global governance remains an “essentially contingent phenom-

ena, resulting partially from historically specific combinations and configurations” as well

as from situational enactments (Cerny 1990: 27). Consequentially, we have to think of

global governance configurations as moving targets, simply because their constituting el-

ements (i.e. the actors involved) and their modes of (inter)action are likely to change

over time. Instead of predefining which actors to consider and thereby substantializing

their agency, interests, motivations, and reasons, relationalism allows us to study whether

and how entities became recognized in specific contexts. Whether it is Germany in the

informal arrangement of the P5+1 (Litwak 2015), 41 Muslim-majority nations engaged in

the Islamic Military Alliance to fight ISIS (Jenkins 2016), or Royal Dutch/Shell becoming

involved in Nigerian human rights policies (while holding on to economic rationales) (Hof-

ferberth 2017), we need to understand how these new actors emerge and how they relate

to established entities. In other words, against the backdrop of the very assumptions

14

Page 16: The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics. Reconstructing the …colfa.utsa.edu/polisci-geography/docs/Bremen_-_Agency.pdf · 2019. 7. 17. · other words, global governance lacks

Matthias Hofferberth – The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics

that drive global governance, “what we call ‘actors’ is something to be explained, not

something to be assumed” (Abbott 1996: 863) and an engagement with the requirements

of agency from within a relational ontology offers tools to do so.18

In more specific research terms, relationalism encourages us to engage with the foun-

dations and not the outcomes of global governance. Whatever governance issues one

might be interested in, such an ontology encourages us to approach it with an open mind

and not with a list of predefined actors to be checked of in terms of how they influenced

the provision of governance for said issue. In other words, to do justice to complex and

ever-changing patterns of agency, rather than championing a particular group of actors,

we should allow our research to determine which relations of entities we consider. Since

there can be no finite answer to who governs the globe, we should study in particular

the claims and justifications advanced to become global governors instead of outcomes

of dispersed agency. Such claims have to be justified since they need to resonate with

actors established in prior relations (Avant et al. 2010b: 17-25). Studying world politics

in this fashion would make our contributions to global governance less affirmative and

more challenging since they would reveal that the very recognition of entities as global

governors is subject of contentious political debate (or at least has been at some point

in the past). While global governance is often framed in functionalist terms which ex-

plain the dispersion of agency as a logical consequence of untapped resources, capacities

and expertise, who should be engaged in world politics reflects deeply-held cosmologies

about politics in general which constitute the normative if not ideological foundation of

the project (Murphy 2000).19

Relationalism & Corporate Agency in Global Governance

To at least briefly illustrate the potential of relationalism for the study of global governance

for a particular research theme, consider the intellectual engagement with multinational

enterprises and discussions on their agency, social responsibilities, and public roles for

a moment. Just like many other subthemes of global governance, this engagement for

the most part has been framed in substantial terms (Hofferberth 2017: 139-44). As

18 Translating this into a language of variables, Cederman (1997: 213) argues that “whenever technicallyfeasible, actors in world politics should be modeled as dependent rather than independent variables”.

19 Considering the practical dimension of global public policy for a moment, one can argue that notreflecting but rather reproducing the normative foundations of global governance severely limit our“debate about the range of strategic choices open to us in the present and future” of global governanceand regulation (Zeitlin 2007: 135).

15

Page 17: The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics. Reconstructing the …colfa.utsa.edu/polisci-geography/docs/Bremen_-_Agency.pdf · 2019. 7. 17. · other words, global governance lacks

Matthias Hofferberth – The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics

such, corporate actors, have been established as legitimate research objects within IR

and important studies have been advanced on their role in and contributions to global

governance based on the notion that they have become global governors (May 2015;

Haufler 2010; Ougaard/Leander 2010). While doing so, their agency, interests, and modes

of actions have all indeed been substantialized as we spent more time and energy to

‘prove’ that enterprises have become global governors rather than challenge the normative

foundations of this development in the first place. In other words, including my own

work, we take corporate agency for granted and champion enterprises before we begin our

work to conclude that they now matter more in global governance than before. Whether

it is Nike negotiating labor standards for the apparel industry or Royal Dutch/Shell

engaging in human rights in Nigeria by providing training in riot control to police forces

(Litvin 2003: 227-73) – both activities that fall under a broader perspective of governance

activities –, we do not, for the most part, challenge the legitimacy of these involvements

but, assuming that these actors matter in their respective contexts, consider the outcome

(i.e. do we see improved governance in labor standards or human rights because of

corporate involvement?)

A relational perspective would advise us not to focus too heavily on outcome. Rather,

research on multinational enterprises interested in the origin and implications of their

agency would first determine how precisely corporate entities established their agency.

More specifically to what has been discussed above, such research would look into how

enterprises present themselves as capable of (political) action and thus advance claims on

their efficacy in realms outside their core business.20 It would also look into corporate

action to derive at motives instead of subsuming everything these actors do under the

paradigm of rational profit maximization. Obviously, profit holds a large influence on

enterprises but it remains too vague of an objective to guide or let alone determine cor-

porate agency. In other words, by considering how enterprises attempt to establish their

efficacy and specify their intentions in relation to other actors and how and whether these

narratives are accepted allows us to reconstruct their actual role in global governance

instead of having our theoretical assumptions (and hopes) determine this role.21

20 In my own research, I found both Royal Dutch/Shell and ExxonMobil rather reluctant to do so as theycontinue to advance foundational beliefs of limited responsibility despite the fact that they engagein activities beyond their economic core. In other words, by separating politics from business andby claiming responsibility only for the latter and limited influence for the former, both enterpriseslimited their own political agency (Hofferberth 2016b: 390-6).

21 Given their existence as a legal network of contracts and the notion that an act of incorporation isneeded to create an enterprise in the first place, the requirement of corporeality seems to be metrather easily for corporate actors and hence might not be the most exiting research topic.

16

Page 18: The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics. Reconstructing the …colfa.utsa.edu/polisci-geography/docs/Bremen_-_Agency.pdf · 2019. 7. 17. · other words, global governance lacks

Matthias Hofferberth – The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics

Arguably, the non-consideration of corporate agency in this foundational yet dynamic

and open-ended fashion has led the discourse on multinational enterprises in global gov-

ernance into a conceptual dead end with two competing narratives. On the one hand,

those who advance rationalist frameworks claim that any commitment of enterprises will

always remain superficial and triggered by social pressure. In other words, as we advance

strong assumptions on their intentions, we assume that corporate agency cannot change

and hence their alleged role of becoming more involved in CSR and global governance

remains limited (Whelan 2012; Lim/Tsutsui 2012; Haufler 2001). On the other hand, for

those who essentialize corporate agency based on normative assumptions, we often find

confusion between actual deeds and normative hopes. Based on the rather strong believe

that enterprises eventually respond and adhere to broader corporate social responsibilities

and social expectations, we see conclusions that it has assumingly already happened. In

fact, based on necessity and the potential that enterprises change ‘for the better’, calls for

further integrating these actors into global governance have been advanced (Ruggie 2013;

Holzer 2010; Scherer/Palazzo 2006). Obviously, these race-to-the-top arguments clash

with the race-to-the-bottom narrative, leaving the discourse undecided and questions on

the origins and legitimacy of corporate agency unanswered. Arguably, neither captures

the complexity of corporate realities in global governance nor allows us to engage in an

advanced discussion understanding how these actors respond to social expectations and

normative change.

More specifically, a relational take on corporate agency in global governance would

not assume it as an a priori given but make it the very subject of study by focusing on their

historical and contingent emergence as global governors. Instead of taking for granted that

enterprises easily transition into new roles as global governors, one could reconstruct and

challenge the narratives that first advocated and then later sustained corporate agency

in global governance. In other words, one would look at the boundaries which define

corporate actors at any particular moment in time and how these are being determined

in social relations (Morgan 2001: 9-12). Furthermore, instead of charging research with

assumptions on the nature of the firm – whether rational or normative – a relational

framework would consider corporate agency in its social dimension. This would allow

one to reconstruct how and along which socially shared meanings corporate agency has

been established in global governance and whether there is normative ground to challenge

those. Methodologically, one would engage with corporate documents and consider those

as an “indispensable [. . . ] source of information about the range and robustness of the con-

straints faced” by enterprise in their struggle to establish and maintain agency rather than

17

Page 19: The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics. Reconstructing the …colfa.utsa.edu/polisci-geography/docs/Bremen_-_Agency.pdf · 2019. 7. 17. · other words, global governance lacks

Matthias Hofferberth – The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics

discount those as cheap talk or take them as evidence of a changing role (Sabel/Zeitlin

1997: 15). Put simply, one would allow enterprises to voice their own thoughts on their

agency. Debates during the 1970s when the UN Centre on Transnational Corporations

failed to develop global mechanisms of regulating corporations arguably mark a critical

juncture in the story here. This failure plus the ensuing commitment to neoliberalism cre-

ated the foundation for a discourse which asserts that cross-border economic regulation

can only be provided through or at least together with corporations. Gaining momentum

over the years, the discourse culminated in public-private partnerships such as the UN

Global Compact and others in the 2000s which only further established corporate agency

in global governance (Kinderman 2012). Revealing the contentions and ambivalences in

these processes seems to be a promising addition to research on corporate agency other-

wise focused on the implications and design of governance arrangements. The following

conclusion brings these and other considerations together.

Conclusion & Outlook

This theoretical note began with the concern that global governance, due to its substan-

tial focus, so far has not contributed to theoretical discussions on agency. Put bluntly,

the motivation to write this paper lies in the fact that the paradigm, even after years

of influencing and opening IR, seems to be a lacking social-theoretical grounding. As

such, global governance as a new contender did not solve but only further aggravated the

problem of (not) studying agency in IR: While the discipline moved above and beyond its

narrow focus on states, for the most part it only expanded the list of actors considered

in empirical terms without theorizing the dispositions for and dynamics of their agency.

As such, unfortunately, we still rely on substantial answers derived from anecdotes of

actually exercised agency instead of theoretically considering potential agency in global

governance. In other words, in the absence of one world government, we still trivialize

the non-trivial question who governs the globe (Finnemore 2014: 223).

Against this shortcoming, I approached the notion of agency in theoretical terms by

specifying three dispositions and spelled them out in a relational framework. I argued

that each disposition should be thought of in terms of the ontological primacy of relations.

According to this perspective, the ability to purposefully make a difference and act in the

world out there in a meaning-oriented fashion does not reside in but rather between

entities. Such a take on agency, I further argued, is useful since it allows us to raise new

questions and consider the indeterminate nature of global governors and their agency in

18

Page 20: The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics. Reconstructing the …colfa.utsa.edu/polisci-geography/docs/Bremen_-_Agency.pdf · 2019. 7. 17. · other words, global governance lacks

Matthias Hofferberth – The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics

world politics. Various challenges remain to be addressed, though, to establish a relational

ontology as a meaningful and viable alternative in the study of world politics. For one,

its real value cannot be determined through programmatic articles such as this. Rather,

it must be shown in more detailed applications in which one would have to elaborate

how to do relational research ‘all the way done’. There certainly is a challenge to find

the balance between necessary abstraction and fixation on the one hand and the impetus

to deessentialize all social phenomena and concepts due to their contingent nature on

the other hand. More precisely, it remains unclear how to prevent substantialism from

coming in through the back door while trying not to get lost in infinite regression. Put

into methodological terms, if global governance is indeed a collection of processes, how

can we justify bracketing parts of those, both time-wise as well as thematically? In terms

of further theorization, one would also need to elaborate how the three dispositions relate

to each other, how they reflect gradual rather than absolute qualities, and whether one

can substitute for the other (i.e. do we already have agency if only two out of three are

given?). More specifically, one would have to specify how to determine whether any given

entity features them in the first place and how precisely they originate in relations (i.e.

what does corporeality of global governors, for example, entail and how is it granted).

These open questions and challenges aside, theorizing agency in global governance

at least helps us become aware of its inherent complexity, think of it in new ways, and

question some of its established truths (e.g. effective governance and regulation of en-

terprises depends on the involvement of these very actors). In this light, paraphrasing

Jackson/Nexon (1999), global governance has yet to learn to study relations before global

governors. In other words, questions of who governs the world cannot be satisfactorily

discussed let alone theoretically concluded through illustrations of anecdotal influence in

particular empirical instances. Even in a discipline which defines itself with its substan-

tial focus on world politics, a socio-theoretically informed discussion of agency thus seems

unavoidable to move forward. Whichever ontological framework one advances in such

a discussion, theorizing agency would make individual research more transparent and

intersubjective and thereby more accessible, communicable, intelligible, and ultimately

oriented towards dialog in the sense of engaged pluralism instead of reproducing paradig-

matism (Sil/Katzenstein 2010; Lapid 2003). Questions of agency, when discussed as such,

bring with them the challenge and the potential forward towards a post-paradigmatic,

self-conscious, and theoretically reflective field tasked with nothing less than coming to

grips with most complex and convoluted interactions otherwise known and described as

world politics.

19

Page 21: The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics. Reconstructing the …colfa.utsa.edu/polisci-geography/docs/Bremen_-_Agency.pdf · 2019. 7. 17. · other words, global governance lacks

Matthias Hofferberth – The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics

References

Abbott, Andrew 1996: Things of Boundaries, in: Social Research 62: 4, 857–882.

Archer, Margaret S. 2000: Being Human. The Problem of Agency, Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press.

Avant, Deborah D. 2016: Pragmatic Networks and Transnational Governance of PrivateMilitary and Security Services, in: International Studies Quarterly 60: 2, 330–342.

Avant, Deborah D./Finnemore, Martha/Sell, Susan K. (Eds.) 2010a: Who Governs theGlobe?, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Avant, Deborah D./Finnemore, Martha/Sell, Susan K. 2010b: Who Governs the Globe?,in: Avant, Deborah D./Finnemore, Martha/Sell, Susan K. (Eds.), Who Governs theGlobe?, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1–31.

Barnett, Michael 2015: Accountability and global governance: The view from paternal-ism, in: Regulation & Governance (Early Online View).

Barnett, Michael/Sikkink, Kathryn 2008: From international relations to global society,in: Reus-Smit, Christian/Snidal, Duncan (Eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Interna-tional Relations, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 62–83.

Cederman, Lars-Erik 1997: Emergent Actors in World Politics. How States and NationsDevelop and Dissolve, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Cerny, Philip G. 1990: The Changing Architecture of Politics: Structure, Agency, andthe Future of the State, London: Sage Publications Ltd.

Coleman, James S. 1990: The Foundations of Social Theory, Cambridge, MA: HarvardUniversity Press.

Commission on Global Governance 1995: Our Global Neighbourhood.The Report of theCommission on Global Governance, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Cox, Robert W. 1981: Social Forces, States and World Orders: Beyond InternationalRelations Theory, in: Millennium: Journal of International Studies 10: 2, 126–155.

DeMars, William E./Dijkzeul, Dennis 2015: The NGO Challenge for International Rela-tions Theory, New York, NY: Routledge.

Dèpelteau, Francois 2008: Relational Thinking: A Critique of Co-Deterministic Theoriesof Structrue and Agency, in: Sociological Theory 26: 1, 51–73.

Dewey, John 1931: Philosophy and Civilization, New York, NY: Minton, Balch & Com-pany.

Dewey, John/Bentley, Arthur F. 1949: Knowing and the Known, Boston, MA: BeaconPress.

Dingwerth, Klaus/Pattberg, Philipp 2006: Global Governance as a Perspective on WorldPolitics, in: Global Governance 12: 2, 185–203.

Donati, Pierpaolo 2011: Relational Sociology. A New Paradigm for the Social Sciences,New York, NY: Routledge.

Emirbayer, Mustafa 1997: Manifesto for a Relational Sociology, in: The American Journalof Sociology 103: 2, 281–317.

20

Page 22: The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics. Reconstructing the …colfa.utsa.edu/polisci-geography/docs/Bremen_-_Agency.pdf · 2019. 7. 17. · other words, global governance lacks

Matthias Hofferberth – The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics

Emirbayer, Mustafa/Mische, Ann 1998: What is Agency?, in: The American Journal ofSociology 103: 4, 962–1023.

Epstein, Charlotte 2013: Theorizing Agency in Hobbes’s Wake: The Rational Actor, theSelf, or the Speaking Subject?, in: International Organization 67: 2, 287–316.

Ferguson, Yale H. 1999: History’s Revenge and Future Shock. The Remapping of GlobalPolitics, in: Hewson, Martin/Sinclair, Timothy J. (Eds.), Approaches to Global Gov-ernance Theory, Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 197–238.

Finnemore, Martha 2014: Dynamics of Global Governance: Building on What We know,in: International Studies Quarterly 58: 1, 221–224.

Fleming, Sean 2016: Artificial Persons and Attributed Actions: How to Interpret Action-Sentences About States, in: European Journal of International Relations (publishedonline first).

Franke, Ulrich/Roos, Ulrich 2010: Actor, structure, process: transcending the state per-sonhood debate by means of a pragmatist ontological model for International Relationstheory, in: Review of International Studies 36: 4, 1057–1077.

Giddens, Anthony 1984: The Constitution of Society. Outline of the Theory of Structura-tion, Cambridge: Polity Press.

Gilbert, Margaret 1989: On Social Facts, London: Routledge.

Gilpin, Robert 1984: The Richness of the Tradition of Political Realism, in: InternationalOrganization 38: 2, 287–304.

Haas, Ernst B. 1964: Beyond the Nation State. Functionalism and International Organi-zation, Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

Haufler, Virginia 2001: A public role for the private sector. Industry Self-Regulation in aGlobal Economy, Washington, DC: Carnegie Endowment for International Peace.

Haufler, Virginia 2010: Corporations in zones of conflict: issues, actors, and institutions,in: Avant, Deborah D./Finnemore, Martha/Sell, Susan K. (Eds.), Who Governs theGlobe?, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 102–130.

Hellmann, Gunther 2017: Interpreting International Relations., in: International StudiesReview (published online first, https://doi.org/10.1093/isr/vix009) .

Hofferberth, Matthias 2015: Mapping the Meanings of Global Governance: A ConceptualReconstruction of a Floating Signifier, in: Millennium: Journal of International Studies43: 2, 598–617.

Hofferberth, Matthias 2016a: ‘Confusion is a fundamental state of mind’. On the Pecu-liar Intellectual Career of Global Governance in International Relations, in: PalgraveCommunications (Open Access, http://dx.doi.org/10.1057/palcomms.2015.44) .

Hofferberth, Matthias 2016b: Multinationale Unternehmen in der Weltpolitik. Zur Kontin-genz von Rolle und Bedeutung "sozialer Akteure", Baden-Baden: Nomos.

Hofferberth, Matthias 2017: “And of Course Our Major Contribution Remains to Run aDecent Business.” Making Sense of Shell’s Sense-Making in Nigeria During the 1990s,in: Business and Politics (published online first).

21

Page 23: The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics. Reconstructing the …colfa.utsa.edu/polisci-geography/docs/Bremen_-_Agency.pdf · 2019. 7. 17. · other words, global governance lacks

Matthias Hofferberth – The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics

Hofferberth, Matthias/Weber, Christian 2015: Lost in translation: a critique of construc-tivist norm research, in: Journal of International Relations and Development 18: 1,75–103.

Hoffmann, Matthew J./Ba, Alice. D 2005: Contending perspectives on global governance.Dialogue and debate, in: Ba, Alice. D/Hoffmann, Matthew J. (Eds.), Contending Per-spectives on Global Governance. Coherence, Contestation and World Order, New York,NY: Routledge, 249–267.

Holzer, Boris 2010: Moralizing the Corporation. Transnational Activism and CorporateAccountability, Cheltenham: Edward Elgar Publishing Ltd.

Jackson, Patrick T. 2003: Defending the West: Occidentalism and the Formation ofNATO, in: The Journal of Political Philosophy 11: 3, 223–252.

Jackson, Patrick T. 2004: Hegel’s House, or ‘People are states too’, in: Review of Inter-national Studies 30: 2, 281–287.

Jackson, Patrick T. 2015: Must International Studies Be a Science?, in: Millennium:Journal of International Studies 43: 3, 942–965.

Jackson, Patrick T./Nexon, Daniel H. 1999: Relations Before States: Substance, Processand the Study of World Politics, in: European Journal of International Relations 5: 3,291–332.

Jackson, Patrick T./Nexon, Daniel H. 2004: Bridging the Gap: Toward A Realist-Constructivist Dialogue, in: International Studies Review 6: 2, 337–352.

Jackson, Patrick T./Nexon, Daniel H. 2009: Paradigmatic Faults in International Rela-tions Theory, in: International Studies Quarterly 53: 4, 907–930.

Jackson, Patrick T./Nexon, Daniel H. 2013: International Theory in a Post-ParadigmaticEra: From Substantive Wagers to Scientific Ontologies, in: European Journal of Inter-national Relations 19: 3, 543–565.

Jenkins, Brian M. 2016: A Saudi-Led Military Alliance to Fight Terrorism. WelcomeMuscle in the Fight Against Terrorism, Desert Mirage, or Bad Idea?, Rand CorporationPerspective.

Joas, Hans 1996: The Creativity of Action, Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Karns, Margaret P./Mingst, Karen A./Stiles, Kendall W. 2015 (3): International Orga-nizations. The Politics and Processes of Global Governance, Boulder: Lynne RiennerPublishers.

Keohane, Robert O. 1989: Neoliberal Institutionalism: A Perspective on World Politics,in: Keohane, Robert O. (Ed.), International Institutions and State Power. Essays ininternational relations Theory, Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1–20.

Keohane, Robert O./Nye, Joseph S. (Eds.) 1973: Transnational Relations and WorldPolitics, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2. edition.

Kinderman, Daniel 2012: ’Free us up so we can be responsible!’ The co-evolution ofCorporate Social Responsibility and neo-liberalism in the UK, 1977-2010, in: Socio-Economic Review 10: 1, 29–57.

22

Page 24: The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics. Reconstructing the …colfa.utsa.edu/polisci-geography/docs/Bremen_-_Agency.pdf · 2019. 7. 17. · other words, global governance lacks

Matthias Hofferberth – The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics

Kratochwil, Friedrich V. 2000: Constructing a New Orthodoxy? Wendt’s ‘Social Theoryof International Politics’ and the Constructivist Challenge, in: Millennium: Journal ofInternational Studies 29: 1, 73–101.

Lapid, Yosef 2003: Through Dialogue to Engaged Pluralism: The Unfinished Business ofthe Third Debate., in: International Studies Review 5: 1, 128–131.

Lim, Alwyn/Tsutsui, Kiyoteru 2012: Globalization and Commitment in Corporate SocialResponsibility: Cross-National Analyses of Institutional and Political-Economy Effects,in: American Sociological Review 77: 1, 69–98.

List, Christian/Petit, Philip 2006: Group Agency and Supervenience, in: The SouthernJournal of Philosophy 44: 1, 85–105.

List, Christian/Pettit, Philip 2011: Group Agency. The Possibility, Design, and Status ofCorporate Agents, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Litvin, Daniel 2003: Empires of Profit. Commerce, Conquest and Corporate Responsibil-ity, New York, NY: Texere.

Litwak, Robert 2015: Iran’s Nuclear Chess: After the Deal, Woodrow Wilson InternationalCenter for Scholars.

May, Christopher 2015: Global Corporations in Global Governance, London: Routledge.

McClurg, Scott D./Young, Joseph K. 2011: Political Networks. Editors’ Introduction: ARelational Political Science, in: PS: Political Science and Politics 44: 1, 39–43.

McCourt, David M. 2016: Practice Theory and Relationalism as the New Constructivism,in: International Studies Quarterly 60: 3, 475–485.

Mead, George Herbert 1967 [1934]: Mind, Self, and Society. From the Standpoint of aSocial Behaviorist, Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Meyer, John W./Jepperson, Ronald L. 2000: The ’Actors’ of Modern Society: The Cul-tural Construction of Social Agency, in: Sociological Theory 18: 1, 100–120.

Mitzen, Jennifer 2013: Power in Concert. The Nineteenth-Century Origins of GlobalGovernance, Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Moravcsik, Andrew 1997: Taking preferences seriously. A Liberal Theory of InternationalPolitics, in: International Organization 51: 4, 513–553.

Morgan, Glenn 2001: The Multinational Firm: Organizing Across Institutional and Na-tional Divides, in: Morgan, Glenn/Kristensen, Richard, Peer Hull / Whitley (Eds.),The Multinational Firm. Organizing Across Institutional and National Divides, Oxford:Oxford University Press, 1–24.

Murphy, Craig 2000: Global Governance: Poorly Done, Poorly Understood, in: Interna-tional Affairs 76: 4, 789–803.

Murphy, Craig 2014: Global Governance over the Long Haul, in: International StudiesQuarterly 58: 1, 216–218.

Ougaard, Morten/Leander, Anna (Eds.) 2010: Business and Global Governance, NewYork, NY: Routledge.

Overbeek, Henk 2005: Global governance, class, hegemony: a historical materialist per-spective, in: Ba, Alice D./Hoffmann, Matthew J. (Eds.), Contending Perspectives on

23

Page 25: The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics. Reconstructing the …colfa.utsa.edu/polisci-geography/docs/Bremen_-_Agency.pdf · 2019. 7. 17. · other words, global governance lacks

Matthias Hofferberth – The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics

Global Governance. Coherence, Contestation and World Order, New York, NY: Rout-ledge, 39–56.

Pegram, Tom/Acuto, Michele 2015: Introduction: Global Governance in the Interregnum,in: Millennium: Journal of International Studies 43: 2, 584–597.

Porter, Tony 2009: Global Governance as configurations of state/non-state activity, in:Whitman, Jim (Ed.), Palgrave Advances in Global Governance, Houndsmills: PalgraveMacmillan, 87–104.

Qin, Yaqing 2016: A Relational Theory of World Politics, in: International Studies Reviewpublished online first.

Rescher, Nicholas 1996: Process Metaphysics. An Introduction to Process Philosophy,Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

Ringmar, Erik 1996: Identity, interest and action. A cultural explanation of Sweden’sintervention in the Thirty Years War, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Rosenau, James N./Czempiel, Ernst-Otto (Eds.) 1992: Governance without Government.Order and Change in World Politics, New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.

Rovane, Carol 2014: Group Agency and Individualism, in: Erkenntnis. An InternationalJournal of Scientific Philosophy 79: 9, 1663–1684.

Ruggie, John G. 2013: Just Business. Multinational Corporations and Human Rights,New York, NY: W. W. Norton & Company.

Sabel, Charles F./Zeitlin, Jonathan 1997: Stories, strategies, structures: rethinking his-torical alternatives to mass production, in: Sabel, Charles F./Zeitlin, Jonathan (Eds.),World of Possibilities. Flexibility and Mass Production in Western Industrialization,Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1–33.

Sabel, Charles F./Zeitlin, Jonathan 2010: Experimentalist Governance in the EuropeanUnion. Towards a New Architecture, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Scherer, Andreas Georg/Palazzo, Dorothà c©e, Guido / Baumann 2006: Global Rulesand Private actors: Toward a New Role of the Transnational Corporation in GlobalGovernance, in: Business Ethics Quarterly 16: 4, 505–532.

Sell, Susan K./Prakash, Aseem 2004: Using Ideas Strategically: The Contest BetweenBusiness and NGO Networks in Intellectual Property Rights, in: International StudiesQuarterly 48: 1, 143–175.

Sending, Ole Jacob/Pouliot, Vincent/Neumann, Iver B. 2015: Diplomacy and the Makingof World Politics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Sil, Rudra/Katzenstein, Peter J. 2010: Beyond Paradigms. Analytic Eclecticism in theStudy of World Politics, London: Palgrave Macmillan.

Sinclair, Timothy J. 2012: Global Governance, Cambridge: Polity Press.

Singer, David J. 1961: The Level-of-Analysis Problem in International Relations, in:World Politics 14: 1, 77–92.

Verba, Sidney 1961: Assumptions of Rationality and Non-Rationality in Models of the In-ternational System, in: Knorr, Klaus/Verba, Sidney (Eds.), The International System:Theoretical Essays, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 93–117.

24

Page 26: The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics. Reconstructing the …colfa.utsa.edu/polisci-geography/docs/Bremen_-_Agency.pdf · 2019. 7. 17. · other words, global governance lacks

Matthias Hofferberth – The Diffusion of Agency in World Politics

Waltz, Kenneth N. 1959: Man, the state and war. A theoretical analysis, New York, NY:Columbia University Press.

Weiss, Thomas G./Wilkinson, Rorden 2014a: International Organization and Global Gov-ernance: What Matters and Why, in: Weiss, Thomas G./Wilkinson, Rorden (Eds.),International Organization and Global Governance, London: Routledge, 3–17.

Weiss, Thomas G./Wilkinson, Rorden 2014b: Rethinking Global Governance? Complex-ity, Authority, Power, Change, in: International Studies Quarterly 58: 1, 207–215.

Wendt, Alexander 1999: Social Theory of international politics, Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press.

Whelan, Glen 2012: The Political Perspective of Corporate Social Responsibility: AResearch Agenda, in: Business Ethics Quarterly 22: 4, 709–737.

Wight, Colin 2006: Agents, Structures and International Relations. Politics as Ontology,Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Wolfers, Arnold 1962: The Actors in International Politics, in: Discord and Collabroation.Essays in International Politics, Baltimore, MD: John Hopkins University Press, 3–24.

Zanotti, Laura 2017: Reorienting IR: Ontological Entanglement, Agency, and Ethics, in:International Studies Review (published online first).

Zeitlin, Jonathan 2007: The Historical Alternatives Approach, in: Jones, Geof-frey/Zeitlin, Jonathan (Eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Business History, Oxford: Ox-ford University Press, 120–140.

25