Top Banner

of 28

Spontenaous Emergence of Law - Customary Law

May 31, 2018

Download

Documents

legalmatters
Welcome message from author
This document is posted to help you gain knowledge. Please leave a comment to let me know what you think about it! Share it to your friends and learn new things together.
Transcript
  • 8/14/2019 Spontenaous Emergence of Law - Customary Law

    1/28

    603

    9500

    SPONTANEOUS EMERGENCE OF LAW:

    CUSTOMARY LAW

    Francesco ParisiGeorge Mason University School of Law

    Copyright 1999 Francesco Parisi

    Abstract

    In the social contract framework, customary rules can be regarded as animplied and often non-verbalized exercise of direct legislation by the membersof society. Those legal systems that grant direct legal force to customary rulesregard custom as a primary, although not exclusive, source of law. In such legaltraditions, courts enforce customary rules as if they had been enacted by theproper legislative authority. Custom thus amounts to a spontaneous norm whichis recognized by the legal system and granted enforcement as a proper legalrule.Judicial recognition of spontaneous norms amounts to a declaratory (rather than

    constitutive) function that treats custom as a legal fact. The legal system findsthe law by recognizing social norms, but does not create the law. The mostnotable illustration is the system of international law, where, absent a centrallegislative authority, custom stands next to treaties as a primary source of law.(See, for example, Article 38 (1) of the Statute of the International Court ofJustice; and Restatement 102 of the Foreign Relations Law of the UnitedStates.)

    Whenever they are granted legitimate status in a legal system, customaryrules are usually given the same effect as other primary sources of law.Although often subordinated to formal legislation, customary rules derive theirforce from the concurrence of a uniform practice and a subjective belief thatadherence to them is obligatory (opinio iuris), without necessarily being

    formally incorporated into any written body of law. For this reason, they areusually classified as immaterial sources of law (Brownlie, 1990). This notionimplies that the custom remains the actual source of law even after its judicialrecognition. In this setting, the judicial decisions that recognize a custom offeronly persuasive evidence of its existence and do not themselves become sourcesof law. In turn, this prevents the principle ofstare decisis from crystallizingcustomary law.

    Modern legal systems generally recognize customary rules that haveemerged either within the confines of positive legislation (consuetudosecundum legem) or in areas that are not disciplined by positive law(consuetudo praeter legem). Where custom is in direct conflict with legislation

  • 8/14/2019 Spontenaous Emergence of Law - Customary Law

    2/28

    604 Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law 9500

    (that is, custom contra legem) the latter normally prevails. In some instances,however, a custom supersedes prior legislation (that is, abrogative custom), andsome arguments have been made in support of emerging practices that conflictwith obsolete provisions of public international law (desuetudo, or abrogativepractice) (Kontou, 1994). The theoretical and practical significance of theseforms of spontaneous social order, which compete with enacted law ininfluencing human choice, are discussed below.

    JEL classification: K00Keywords: Customary Law, Spontaneous Law, Social Norms

    1. Introduction

    Legal theorists define custom as a practice that emerges outside of legalconstraints, and which individuals and organizations spontaneously follow inthe course of their interactions out of a sense of legal obligation. Two categoriesof social practices are generally distinguished:

    (a) Practices that reflect mere behavioural patterns. In legal jargon, suchbehaviour is a mere usage; in economic terms it simply represents anequilibrium convention. A mere behavioural regularity does not generate acustomary rule.(b) Practices that reflect an internalized belief that the practice is necessary orsocially desirable. These practices are considered necessary for socialwell-being and are treated as proper legal custom, often entering the legalsystem as primary sources of law.

    The terminology used in the legal and economic literature should becontrasted with the terminology employed in sociological literature (see, forexample, Weber, 1978, pp. 319-320). What is legally termed a mere usage isdefined in sociological literature as a custom (Sitte), in the sense of a typicallyuniform activity that is not considered to be socially necessary. Convention -

    the sociological notion closest to the legal concept of custom - amounts toconduct manipulated by express approval or disapproval by other members ofthe group, but lacking the enforceability that characterizes a legal custom.

    A. The Theory of Spontaneous Law

    2. The Formative Elements of a Customary Rule

    According to the theory of customary law, individual actors gradually come toembrace norms that they view as requisite to their collective wellbeing. An

  • 8/14/2019 Spontenaous Emergence of Law - Customary Law

    3/28

    9500 Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law 605

    enforceable custom emerges from two formative elements: (a) a quantitativeelement consisting of a general or emerging practice; and (b) a qualitativeelement reflected in the belief that the norm generates a desired social outcome.

    2.1 The Quantitative ElementThe quantitative requirements for the formation of customary law concern boththe length of time and the universality of the emerging practice. Regarding the

    time element, there is generally no universally established minimum durationfor the emergence of customary rules. Customary rules have evolved from bothimmemorial practice and a single act. Still, French jurisprudence hastraditionally required the passage of forty years for the emergence of aninternational custom, while German doctrine generally requires thirty years(see Tunkin, 1961; Mateesco, 1947). Naturally, the longer the time required toform a valid practice, the less likely it is for custom to effectively anticipate theintervention of formal legislation, and to adapt to changing circumstancesovertime.

    Regarding the condition of universality, international legal theory isambivalent. Charney (1986) suggests that the system of international relationsis analogous to a world of individuals in the state of nature, dismissing the ideathat unanimous consent by all participants is required before binding customarylaw is formed. Rather than universality, recent restatements of international lawrefer to consistency and generality (see DAmato, 1971). Where it isimpossible to identify a general practice because of fluctuations in behavior, theconsistency requirement is not met (see Asylum (1950) pp. 276-277; andWimbledon (1923), Ser. A, no. 1). Similarly, more recent cases in internationallaw restate the universality requirement in terms of increasing and widespreadacceptance (see, for example, Fisheries Jurisdiction (1974), pp. 23-26;NorthSea Continental Shelf (1969), p. 42), allowing special consideration foremerging general norms (or local clusters of spontaneous default rules) that areexpected to become evolutionarily stable over time.

    With regard to rules at the national or local level, the varying pace withwhich social norms are transformed suggests that no general time or

    consistency requirement can be established as an across-the-board condition forthe validity of a custom. Some variance in individual observation of the practiceshould be expected because of the stochastic origin of social norms. A flexibletime requirement is particularly necessary in situations of rapid flux, whereexogenous changes are likely to affect the incentive structure of the underlyingrelationship.

    2.2 The Qualitative ElementThe second formative element of a customary rule is generally identified by thephrase opinio iuris ac necessitatis, which describes a widespread belief in thedesirability of the norm and the general conviction that the practice representsan essential norm of social conduct. This element is often defined in terms of

  • 8/14/2019 Spontenaous Emergence of Law - Customary Law

    4/28

    606 Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law 9500

    necessary and obligatory convention. (Kelsen, 1939, 1945; DAmato, 1971;Walden, 1977). The traditional formulation of opinio iuris is problematicbecause of its circularity. It is quite difficult to conceptualize that law can beborn from a practice which is already believed to be required by law.

    The practical significance of this requirement is that it narrows the rangeof enforceable customs: only those practices recognized as socially desirable ornecessary will eventually ripen into enforceable customary law. Once there is

    a general consensus that members of a group ought to conform to a given ruleof conduct, a legal custom can be said to have emerged when some level ofspontaneous compliance with the rule is obtained. As a result, observableequilibria that are regarded by society as either undesirable (for example, aprisoners dilemma uncooperative outcome) or unnecessary (for example, acommon practice of greeting neighbours cordially) will lack the subjective andqualitative element of legal obligation and, therefore, will not generateenforceable legal rules.

    B. The Emergence of Spontaneous Law

    According to the traditional legal approach to customary law, two elements aregenerally required for the emergence of a binding custom: (1) the practiceshould emerge out of the spontaneous and uncoerced behaviour of variousmembers of a group, and (2) the parties involved must subjectively believe inthe obligatory or necessary nature of the emerging practice (opinio iuris). Toan economist, the first element corresponds to the rather standard assumptionof rational choice. The second element may be appraised as a belief of socialobligation, emerging in response to game inefficiencies, to support behaviouralrules that avoid aggregate losses from strategic behaviour.

    The law and economics literature has examined some additional structuralconditions for the emergence of customary law, which will briefly be analyzedbelow. (For a more extensive analysis, see Parisi, 1998b.)

    3. Structural Symmetry and Incentive Alignment

    The literature on social norms focuses on non-contractual mechanisms andconsiders the situations that are more easily governed by spontaneous law.Under symmetrical conditions, norms that maximize group welfare alsomaximize individual expected payoffs. Thus, no one has any reason tochallenge the emerging norm. Paradoxically, therefore, there is no need for lawor norm enforcement in an environment characterized by perfect incentivealignment, as contracts or relationships are self-enforcing (Klein, 1996).

  • 8/14/2019 Spontenaous Emergence of Law - Customary Law

    5/28

    9500 Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law 607

    In the presence of perfect incentive alignment, cooperation will result inboth the case of repeated games in which the players are faced with highdiscount factors, and in one-shot games. It is worth noting that situationscharacterized by symmetric payoffs or role reversibility do not present anopportunity for strategic preference revelation. The expected costs and benefitsof alternative rules are the same among the members of the group. Eachindividual has an incentive to agree to a set of rules that maximize the

    aggregate welfare of the group, consequently maximizing his expected shareof wealth. True preferences will therefore be revealed in situations of stochasticsymmetry. Conversely, strategic choices are more likely to characterize real lifesituations with misaligned individual incentives.

    Additionally, in the absence of perfect incentive alignment, the discountfactor plays an important role. In situations where the probability of futureinteraction is relatively high, the discount factor captures two analyticallydistinct elements. First, it acts as a function of the players time preference.Second, the discount factor is a function of the probability of futureinteractions.

    The discount factors role in evolutionary models is therefore critical.Environments promoting a high probability of future interaction and low timepreference are therefore more likely to induce optimizing equilibria. In the caseof a one-shot game, on the other hand, the probability of future interaction iszero, so that the expected value of future cooperation is also zero (see,generally, Axelrod, 1984).

    Another area of research in the customary law literature considers the roleof morality and internalized obligations as a means for inducing cooperationin conflict games (see, for example, Gauthier, 1986; Ullmann-Margalit, 1977).Internalization of the norm is a source of spontaneous compliance. Forexample, individuals internalize obligations when they disapprove and sanctionother individuals deviations from the rule, or when they directly lose utilitywhen the norm is violated. In this setting, Cooter (1994a) suggests that a legalcustom will successfully evolve when the ex ante individual incentives arealigned with the collective public interest. Cooter (1994a, p. 224) calls this

    proposition the alignment theorem.

    4. Stochastic Symmetry and Role Reversibility

    Traditionally, strategic preference revelation is viewed as a hindrance to thespontaneous emergence of cooperation. Such a problem is likely to beminimized in situations of role reversibility or stochastic symmetry (Parisi,1995). Similar to a Rawlsian veil of ignorance, role reversibility and stochasticsymmetry induce each member to agree to a set of rules that benefits the entiregroup, thus maximizing her expected share of the wealth.

  • 8/14/2019 Spontenaous Emergence of Law - Customary Law

    6/28

    608 Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law 9500

    These conditions in fact occurred during the formative period of themedieval law merchant (lex mercatoria), when traveling merchants acted in thedual capacity of buyer and seller. If they articulated a rule of law which wasfavourable to them as sellers, it could have the opposite effect when they actedas buyers, and vice-versa. This role reversibility changed an otherwiseconflicting set of incentives (buyer versus seller) into one that converged towardsymmetrical and mutually desirable rules.

    The law merchant therefore illustrates a successful system of spontaneousand decentralized law (see Benson, 1989, 1990; Greif, 1989). Fuller (1969, p.24) observes that frequent role changes foster the emergence of mutuallyrecognized and accepted duties in a society of economic traders. By definitionthe members of such a society enter direct and voluntary relationships ofexchange. ... Finally, economic traders frequently exchange roles, now selling,now buying. The duties that arise out of their exchanges are thereforereversible, not only in theory but in practice.

    Certainly, the emergence of consensus for a given rule does not exclude thepossibility of subsequent opportunistic deviation by some individuals whenroles are later reversed. This is a typical enforcement problem, however, andthe possibility of strategic defection does not undermine the rules qualitativefeatures. The general acceptance of or acquiescence to a custom dependsprimarily on its anticipated effect on the group. Those strategies that maximizethe expected payoff for each participant if reciprocally undertaken evolve intonorms. This conception of spontaneous law is examined by Stearns (1994, pp.1243-1244), who observes that if the participants were unable to devise rulesgoverning future interactions, and unforeseen circumstances placed them in aforced market relationship requiring post-contractual negotiations, courts andlegislatures might have a comparative advantage over the participants indevising market facilitating rules. Unlike market participants, courts andlegislatures choose from among alternative solutions as if the underlying eventshad not yet occurred, without attempting to strategically maximize theadvantage caused by unforeseen circumstances (see also Shubik, 1987). Whererules are breached following role reversal, norms play a collateral yet crucial

    role in sanctioning case-by-case opportunism.Conditions of role reversibility, coupled with norms that generate

    disincentives to adopt opportunistic double standards, are therefore likely togenerate optimal rules via spontaneous processes. The groups ability to imposea sanction obviously depends on an individuals accountability for his pastbehaviour. Benson (1992d, pp. 5-7) explores the role of reputation in situationsof repeated market interaction, observing that reputation serves as a source ofcollective knowledge regarding past actions.

  • 8/14/2019 Spontenaous Emergence of Law - Customary Law

    7/28

    9500 Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law 609

    5. Induced Symmetry and Reciprocity Constraints

    Prisoners dilemma-type games are plagued by the dominance of opportunisticbehaviour because of the potential accessibility of off-diagonal, non-cooperativeoutcomes. Schotter (1981), Lewis (1969) and Leibenstein (1982) analyze therole of conventions in correcting prisoners dilemma situations.

    Among the devices capable of correcting prisoners dilemma-type games,

    the players can bind their strategic choices to those of their opponents,drastically changing the equilibrium of the game. Ensuring automaticreciprocity by binding a players strategy to that of his opponent eliminatesaccess to off-diagonal outcomes and renders the reward for unilateral defectionunobtainable. Just as no rational player will employ defection strategies in thehope of obtaining higher payoffs from unilateral cheating, neither will arational player be induced to select defection strategies as a merely defensivetactic. Automatic reciprocity mechanisms thus guarantee a shift towardoptimizing cooperation. As pointed out by Parisi (1997), ancient customs ofretaliation, based on conceptions of symmetry and punitive balance, provide anintriguing illustration of the principle of reciprocity at work (see, for example,Exodus 21:23; and Code of Hammurabi Paragraphs 108 and 127). Parisi(1998a) considers another example of a reciprocity constraint. Art. 21 (1)b ofthe 1969 Vienna Convention, which articulates an established custom ofreciprocity, creates a mirror-image mechanism in the case of unilateralreservations in the process of treaty ratification: A reservation established withregard to another party ... modifies those provisions to the same extent for thatother party in its relations with the reserving state. The effects of thisautomatic reciprocity mechanism are similar to a tit-for-tat strategy without theneed for active retaliation by states: whenever a treaty is modified unilaterallyin favour of one state, the result will be as if all the other states had introducedan identical reservation against the reserving state. By imposing a symmetryconstraint on the parties choices, this rule offers a possible solution toprisoners dilemma problems.

    Parisi (1998a) further observes that, while the principle of reciprocity solves

    conflict situations characterized by a prisoners dilemma structure (in bothsymmetric and asymmetric cases), alone it is incapable of correcting otherstrategic problems. When a conflict occurs along the diagonal possibilities ofthe game (such that the obtainable equilibria are already characterized bysymmetric strategies), a reciprocity constraint will not eliminate the divergenceof interests between the players and will not affect the results of the game. Thedynamic process of norm formation may unveil the existence of a tilt pointbeyond which emerging beliefs become stable and self-sustaining. In light ofreciprocal constraints undertaken by other members of the community,individuals who frequently exchange roles in their social interactions haveincentives to constrain their behaviour to conform to socially optimal norms of

  • 8/14/2019 Spontenaous Emergence of Law - Customary Law

    8/28

    610 Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law 9500

    conduct. Buchanan (1975) insightfully anticipated this result, suggesting thatan even stronger logic explains the emergence of cooperation in situations ofinduced reciprocity. In both cases, the non-idealistic and self-interestedbehaviour of human actors will generate optimal norms.

    6. Articulation Theories in the Formation of Customary Law

    Notable scholars have considered the conditions under which principles of justice can emerge spontaneously through the voluntary interaction andexchange of individual members of a group. As in a contractarian setting, thereality of customary law formation relies on a voluntary process through whichmembers of a community develop rules that govern their social interaction byvoluntarily adhering to emerging behavioural standards. In this setting,Harsanyi (1955) suggests that optimal social norms are those that wouldemerge through the interaction of individual actors in a social setting withimpersonal preferences. The impersonality requirement for individualpreferences is satisfied if the decision makers have an equal chance of findingthemselves in any one of the initial social positions and they rationally choosea set of rules to maximize their expected welfare. Rawls (1971) employsHarsanyis model of stochastic ignorance in his theory of justice. However, theRawlsian veil of ignorance introduces an element of risk aversion in thechoice between alternative states of the world, thus altering the outcomeachievable under Harsanyis original model, with a bias toward equaldistribution (that is, with results that approximate the Nash criterion of socialwelfare). Further analysis of the spontaneous formation of norms and principlesof morality can be found in Sen (1979), Ullmann-Margalit (1977) and Gauthier(1986).

    Legal theorists and practitioners have addressed a similar issue whenconsidering the requirements ofopinio iuris. In attempting to solve one of theproblems associated with the notion of opinio iuris, namely the troublesomeproblem of circularity, legal scholars (notably, DAmato, 1971) have considered

    the crucial issue of timing of belief and action in the formation of customaryrules. The traditional approach emphasizes the awkward notion that individualsmust believe that a practice is already law before it can become law. Thisapproach basically requires the existence of a mistake for the emergence of acustom: the belief that an undertaken practice was required by law, wheninstead, it was not. Obviously, this approach has its flaws. Placing such relianceon systematic mistakes, the theory fails to explain how customary rules canemerge and evolve overtime in cases where individuals have full knowledge ofthe state of the law.

    In this context, legal theorists have proposed to look past the notions ofopinio iuris and usage concentrating on the qualitative element of

  • 8/14/2019 Spontenaous Emergence of Law - Customary Law

    9/28

    9500 Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law 611

    articulation. Consistent with the predicament of the economic models,articulation theories suggest that greater weight should be given to beliefs thathave been expressed prior to the emergence of a conflict.

    Here, it is interesting to point out a strong similarity between the legal andthe economic models. Articulations that are made prior to the unveiling ofconflicting contingencies can be analogized to rules chosen under a Harsanyianveil of uncertainty. States and individuals will have an incentive to articulate

    and endorse norms that maximize their expected welfare. Given some degreeof uncertainty as to the future course of events, the emerging rules will be suchas to maximize the expected welfare of the community at large. Conversely,rules that are articulated after an outburst of conflict may be strategicallybiased. Once the future is disclosed to them, parties will tend to articulate rulesthat maximize their actual welfare, rather than the expected welfare to bederived from an uncertain future. Thus, ex ante norms should be given greaterweight in the adjudication process.

    This predicament seems to be contradicted by the empirical and anecdotalevidence on commercial customary law. Bernstein (1996) examines customaryrules that have developed in various modern commercial trades. Her findingsseem to indicate that in the adjudication of business disputes, commercialtribunals tend to enforce customary rules that are quite different from thebusiness norms spontaneously followed by the parties in the course of theirrelationship. Rather, customary rules develop around practices developedduring the conflictual phase of a relationship. In this setting, Bernsteindistinguishes between relationship norms and end-of-the-game norms. Whenadjudicating a case, courts are faced with parties who have reached the endpoint in their relationship. The end-of-the-game norms of the conflictual phasethus tend to be enforced, while the cooperative norms developed in the courseof their relationship remain outside the domain of adjudication.

    C. The Failures of Customary Law

    According to the popular paradigms of economic analysis, decentralized marketprocesses have a comparative advantage over centralized allocativemechanisms in the creation of efficient equilibria. Customary law formationcan be analogized to a decentralized decision making process, with acomparative advantage over centralized processes in the creation of efficientrules.

    Customary rules are generally accepted by the community, with a largershare of rules followed spontaneously by the community and a consequentreduction in law enforcement costs. In the decentralized dynamic ofspontaneous law, individual decision makers directly perceive the costs andbenefits of alternative rules, and reveal their preferences by supporting or

  • 8/14/2019 Spontenaous Emergence of Law - Customary Law

    10/28

  • 8/14/2019 Spontenaous Emergence of Law - Customary Law

    11/28

    9500 Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law 613

    If we agree that path dependence has something to do with the emergenceand evolution of customary law, we should follow this logic to its conclusion,revisiting the very foundations of the efficiency claim. The main question iswhether path dependence could ever lead to inefficient results. According tocurrent research (Roe, 1996), path dependence may lead to inefficientequilibria. Once a community has developed its norms and conventions, thecosts of changing them may outweight the benefits. Less efficient rules may

    persist if the transition to more efficient alternatives is costly. Thus, if oneallows for some randomness and path dependence, norms and conventions,although driven by an evolution-toward-efficiency dynamic, may stabilizearound points of local, rather than global, maximization. Our history, in thissense, constrains our present choices. We may wish we had developed moreefficient customs and institutions, but it would be foolish now to attempt tochange them. The claim of efficiency of spontaneous law thus becomes arelative one vis--vis the other sources of law. The point then becomes that ofweighing the relative advantages of spontaneous law-making against theattributes of engineered legislation, taking full account of the pervasive publicchoice and information problems underlying such alternatives.

    8. Rational Abstention and Norm Manipulation

    A public choice analysis of customary law should consider the vulnerability ofnorms and customs to the pressure of special interest groups. This line ofanalysis - relatively undeveloped in the current literature - should search forparallels between the legislative process and the dynamic of norm formation.In that setting, the opportunity for collective beliefs and customs to bemanipulated by special interest groups should be analyzed. Any claim thatcustomary sources are superior to proper legislation will have to rest on a solidunderstanding of the relative sensibility of each source to possible politicalfailures.

    The application of a well-known theorem of public choice to the study of

    customary law generates very interesting results. Unlike legislation in arepresentative democracy, customary law rests on the widespread consensus ofall individuals affected by the rule. If principal-agent problems are likely toarise in a political world characterized by rational ignorance and rationalabstention of voters, no such problems appear to affect customary sources.Individuals are bound by a customary rule only to the extent that they concurred- actively or through voluntary acquiescence - in the formation of the emergingpractice.

    Imperfect information, however, may induce voluntary acquiescence - oreven active concurrence - to an undesirable practice. Economic models ofcascade or bandwagon behaviour have shown how inferior paths can be

  • 8/14/2019 Spontenaous Emergence of Law - Customary Law

    12/28

    614 Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law 9500

    followed by individuals who rely on previous choices undertaken by othersubjects, and value such observed choices as signals of revealed preference.Economic models have shown that, when information is incomplete, excessiveweight can be attached to the signal generated by others. Others choices maybe followed even when the agents own perception conflicts with the content ofthe observed signal. In this way, a biased or mistaken first-mover can generatea cascade of wrong decisions by all his followers, with a result that may prove

    relatively persistent under a wide array of conditions.Cascade arguments may also unveil the relative fragility of spontaneoussources of law in light of the possible manipulation of collective beliefs throughbiased leadership. If information is imperfect, the input of politically biasedfirst-movers may generate undesirable norms. These norms may persist becauseof the weight attached to the choices of our predecessors. Thus, once generated,wrong beliefs may become stable and widespread in any community ofimperfect decision makers.

    9. Collective Action Problems in Customary Legal Regimes

    Another potential weakness of customary law is revealed by the application ofa collective action framework to the study of the formation and enforcement ofcustomary rules. We can start the analysis by observing that legal rules and lawenforcement are public goods. In the case of customary rules, collective actionproblems may thus arise at two distinct stages: first, in the formative processof customary rules; and second, in the enforcement of the emerged customs.

    The process of a custom formation relies on the spontaneous andwidespread acceptance of a given rule by the members of a group. Individualsoften face a private cost when complying with the precepts of the rule, and theygenerally derive a benefit because of the compliance of others with existingrules. Thus, the formation of customary law can be affected by a public goodproblem. When discussing the conditions under which customary rules caneffectively develop, I illustrated the analysis with a game-theoretic framework.

    The public good problem considered here is in many respects similar to thestrategic tension that we have examined in the context of customary lawformation. If individuals face a private cost and generate a public benefitthrough norm creation, there will be a suboptimal amount of norms createdthrough spontaneous processes. Any individual would like others to observe ahigher level of norm compliance than he or she observed. The resulting levelof norm compliance would thus be suboptimal. Collective action problems inthe formation of customary rules have traditionally been corrected by normswhich sanctioned opportunistic double standards, and by metarules imposingreciprocity constraints on the parties.

  • 8/14/2019 Spontenaous Emergence of Law - Customary Law

    13/28

    9500 Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law 615

    The issue has only marginally been addressed in the economic literature.The reader may look at Hirshleifer (1982) who discusses enforcement by thesanction of one time retaliation by defection in a prisoners dilemma setting;and Witt (1986) who discusses enforcement by costly retaliation and otherpunishment not depending on repeat interactions.

    More serious collective action problems emerge in the enforcement ofspontaneous norms. If the enforcement of norms is left to the private initiative

    of individual members of the group, a large number of cases will becharacterized by a suboptimal level of enforcement. Punishing violators of anorm creates a public good because of the special and general deterrent effectof the penalty. Yet if imposition of the penalty is left to private initiative,punishers would be willing to enforce norms only to the point at which theprivate marginal cost of enforcement equals its private marginal benefit. Thisequilibrium obviously diverges from the social optimum, where enforcementwould be carried out until the marginal cost equals the social, rather thanprivate, marginal benefit.

    This consideration explains why the customs of ancient societies recognizedand sanctioned only a limited category of wrongs. Generally speaking, onlythose wrongs that had a well-identified victim were likely to be addressedthrough a system of private law enforcement. For the system of private lawenforcement to function properly, it was necessary for the victim or his clan tohave a strong interest in carrying out the punishment. This also explains whyother categories of wrong with a broader class of victims tend to emerge duringmore advanced stages of legal development, when law enforcement is delegatedto a central authority.

    In sum, collective action problems may be pervasive in the enforcement ofcustomary rules, with a consequential risk that enforcement will be suboptimal.This conclusion suggests that the decentralized process of law formation maybe successfully coupled with a centralized mechanism of law enforcement. Inthis way, the advantages that customary sources have in gathering diffuseinformation will be available, free from the collective action problems thattypically affect decentralized processes of law enforcement.

    10. Adjudicating Social Norms

    According to the theory of spontaneous law, customary law has a comparativeadvantage over the other institutional sources. The intellectual basis of thisclaim is related to the proposition that any social arrangement that isvoluntarily entered upon by rationally self-interested parties is beneficial tosociety as a whole.

    The inductive process which underlies spontaneous law builds upon the roleof individuals giving direct effect to their revealed preferences, without the

  • 8/14/2019 Spontenaous Emergence of Law - Customary Law

    14/28

    616 Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law 9500

    interface of third-party decision makers. To the extent that social practices haveemerged under competitive conditions (that is, so long as there is an implicitcost for indulging in inefficient equilibria) without Pareto-relevant externalities,we may be able to draw plausible conclusions regarding the desirability ofemerging customs. It is in this latter sense that custom may reclaim full dignityas a source of law. The evolutionary and game-theoretic appraisals of the law-making process have shed new light on the normative foundations of

    spontaneous law, but they require an appropriate analysis of the incentivestructure in the originating social environment (Cooter, 1992).Evolutionary theories of cooperation have indeed explained the ability of

    rationally self-interested individuals to cooperate for the sake of mutual gain.Evolutionarily stable cooperative strategies serve efficiency goals and mayemerge as social norms recognized by the community to be obligatory. Onceemerged, customary rules generate the expectations of the other members ofsociety and those expectations in turn demand judicial enforcement. In someinstances, peer pressure and spontaneous processes of norm internalization willsupport their enforcement.

    The legal system may further this process by recognizing and enforcingwelfare-maximizing social norms. In this regard, Cooter (1994a) argues thatlegal recognition and enforcement should consequently be denied in the caseof non-cooperative practices, under a test that amounts to a structural analysisof the social incentives that generated the norm. He further argues that in theprocess of common law adjudication, a distinction must necessarily be madebetween cooperative norms and non-cooperative practices. Courts are notspecialized in the adjudication of most norms. They must therefore resort to astructural approach, first inquiring into the incentives underlying the socialstructure that generated the norms, rather than attempting to weigh their costsand benefits directly.

    11. Local Information and Evolutionary Traps

    When the private incentives of the parties diverge from the collective good andthe parties cannot enter into binding and enforceable social contracts,inefficient social interactions may follow. These situations may generatesuboptimal Nash equilibria as the benefit pursued by each individual player isinsufficient to compensate for the harm suffered by the other players. While attimes benefitting a few members of the group, strategies of this kind may resultin a net social loss for the collectivity. Generally considered undesirable, theymay be condemned from the other members of the group. In this way, rules thatare expected to harm the aggregate wellbeing of the community will not besupported by a belief of social necessity. By discouraging the adoption of

  • 8/14/2019 Spontenaous Emergence of Law - Customary Law

    15/28

    9500 Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law 617

    socially suboptimal strategies, the group ethic may serve to destabilizeundesirable stalls in the evolutionary process. Therefore, those societies thatfoster a strong group ethic will maintain a comparative advantage over others.Whenever the societies operate in an intergroup environment marked by strongcompetition, competing societies will adopt the norms of societies with thecomparatively strong group ethic, or else they will suffer negative selection.

    In a different setting, one may also think of a group ethic evolving to correct

    for evolutionary stalls and to stabilize individual behaviour on a point of globalmaximization (Hirshleifer, 1982). Figure 1 illustrates a possible scenario for anevolutionary trap, where, even in the absence of any strategic interactionbetween individuals, global maximization is facilitated by the existence ofnorms.Whenever the non-convexity of individual preferences does not permit aprogressive shift from B to A without a utility loss, the point of localmaximization B may be characterized as a behavioural trap. In these situations,individuals face a no pain, no gain dilemma. Individuals are at a point oflocalmaximization and - because of imperfect knowledge or perhaps inertia in theirconsumption or behavioural habits - are unlikely to shift to a differentoptimizing point without external incentives. Imperfect information, in thiscontext, implies that individuals may have complete information about wherethey are, but not necessarily about where they are going - such that thepreferences that are revealed through the observed choices of the parties maynot be used as an absolute proxy for individual optimization.

    Figure 1 The Utility-Enhancing Norm

  • 8/14/2019 Spontenaous Emergence of Law - Customary Law

    16/28

    618 Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law 9500

    When this type of evolutionary stall persists in a group, social norms ofacceptable behaviour may emerge (Levy, 1988). Those who depart from thesenorms may be subjected to sanctions (condemnation).

    Individuals, perhaps even the large majority of individuals in society, maybe trapped in behaviour B due to incomplete (ly known) preferences over never-experienced alternatives. It would then be utility enhancing for society (or othermembers within the group who have obtained information over the alternative

    states of the world) to influence the consumption choices of other individualsby stigmatization or punishment, in order to lead the individual out of his orher trap. Such stigmatization - one may observe: paternalistic in nature - maywell evolve spontaneously in societies because it makes individuals and societyas a whole better off. In an evolutionary setting, societies that developed suchnorms - be them social, ethical, or moral in nature - will enjoy a comparativeadvantage over other societies.

    Despite the general economic motion which views constraints as bads foroptimization problems, Figure 1 thus shows the possibility of autility-enhancing constraint capable of correcting a suboptimal equilibriumobtained in a point of local maximization along a non-convex preference set.Within a local optimization setup, moral constraints may supply informationnot otherwise revealed by the local surface. Together with social norms andgroup standards, moral constraints transmit the accumulated wisdom of pastexperience to individual decision makers. In this framework, norms oftradition, morality, and group ethics do not conflict in any general way with theeconomic paradigms of efficiency and optimization. Evolution assures thatpractices which are socially inferior (in the sense that they do not make acost-justified contribution to human wellbeing) are less frequently adoptedbecause they are labelled as immoral, socially inappropriate, or ethically wrong.Of course, evolutionary processes are never completed, and their task is onlystochastically accomplished. Still, the strong correlation between activities andinstitutions that are efficient, and the communitys moral approval of them,should not be underestimated. Many activities that are generally consideredimmoral (for example, stealing, cheating, lying, and so on) are also inefficient

    in that they dissipate human wealth. While counterexamples exist in whichmorally condemned behaviour actually contributes to overall human welfare,social norms and moral principles of the type described above should beconsidered rules of thumb principles of conduct for individuals who operatein a world of imperfect information and limited cognitive competence (see,Heiner, 1983; Frank, 1987; Parisi, 1995).

  • 8/14/2019 Spontenaous Emergence of Law - Customary Law

    17/28

    9500 Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law 619

    Bibliography on Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law (9500)

    Ackerman, Bruce A. (1986), Law, Economics and the Problem of Legal Culture, 66Duke LawJournal, 929-947.

    Adelstein, Richard P. (1979), The Moral Costs of Crime: Prices, Information and Organization, inGray, Charles M. (ed.), The Costs of Crime, Beverly Hills, CA, Sage Publications, 233-252.

    Adelstein, Richard P. (1981), Institutional Function and Evolution in the Criminal Process, 76Northwestern University Law Review, 1-99.

    Adelstein, Richard P. and Peretz, Steven I. (1985), The Competition of Technologies in Markets for

    Ideas: Copyright and Fair Use in Evolutionary Perspective, 5International Review of Law andEconomics, 209-238.

    Alchian, Armen A. (1950), Uncertainty, Evolution and Economic Theory, 58Journal of PoliticalEconomy, 211-221.

    Arthur, W. Brian (1988), Self-Reinforcing Mechanisms in Economics, in Anderson, Philip W. et al.(eds), The Economy as an Evolving Complex System, Reading, MA, Addison-Wesley.

    Axelrod, R. (1981), The Emergence of Cooperation Among Egoists, 75American Political ScienceReview, 306-318.

    Axelrod, R. (1984), The Evolution of Cooperation, New York, Basic Books.Bailey, Martin J. and Rubin, Paul H. (1994), A Positive Theory of Legal Change, 14International

    Review of Law and Economics , 467-477.Barnes, David W. and Stout, Lynn A. (1992), Economics of Constitutional Law and Public Choice,

    St. Pauls West Publishing.Barry, B.M. (1995),Justice as Impartiality, Oxford, Clarendon.Bell, John W. (1977), Averting a Crisis in Product Liability: An Evolutionary Process of

    Socioeconomic Justice, 65Illinois Bar Journal, 640-648.

    Benson, Bruce L (1990), The Enterprise of Law: Justice Without the State, San Francisco, PacificResearch Institute for Public Policy.

    Benson, Bruce L. (1988), Legal Evolution in Primitive Societies, 144Journal of Institutional andTheoretical Economics, 772-788.

    Benson, Bruce L. (1989a), The Spontaneous Evolution of Commercial Law, 55Southern EconomicJournal, 644-661, reprinted in Klein, Daniel B. (ed.), Reputation: Studies in the VoluntaryEnforcement of Good Behavior, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press.

    Benson, Bruce L. (1989b), Enforcement of Private Property Rights in Primitive Societies: LawWithout Government, 9Journal of Libertarian Studies, 1-26.

    Benson, Bruce L. (1990), Customary Law With Private Means of Resolving Disputes and DispensingJustice: A Description of a Modern System of Law and Order Without State Coercion, 9Journalof Libertarian Studies, 25-42. Reprinted in Law and Order Without State Coercion, inVeljanovski, Cento (ed.) (1991),Regulation, Regulators and the Market, London, Institute ofEconomic Affairs, 159-179.

    Benson, Bruce L. (1991a), An Evolutionary Contractarian View of Primitive Law: The Institutionsand Incentives Arising Under Customary American Indian Law,5Review of Austrian Economics ,

    65-89.Benson, Bruce L. (1991b), Reciprocal Exchange as the Basis for Recognition of Law: Examples from

    American History, 10Journal of Libertarian Studies, 53-82.

  • 8/14/2019 Spontenaous Emergence of Law - Customary Law

    18/28

    620 Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law 9500

    Benson, Bruce L. (1992a), Market Failure Versus Government Failure in the Production ofAdjudication, in Bowman, Gary W., Hakim, Simon and Seidenstat, Paul (eds), Privatizing theUnited States Justice System: Police, Adjudication, and Corrections Services from the PrivateSector, Jefferson, NC, McFarland & Co., 203-225.

    Benson, Bruce L. (1992b), The Evolution of Values and Institutions in a Free Society: TheUnder-Pinnings of a Market Economy, 5 International Journal on the Unity of Sciences,411-442. Reprinted in Radnitzky, Gerard and Bouillon, Hardy (eds) (1995),Values and the SocialOrder Vol.I, Aldershot, Avebury, 87-125.

    Benson, Bruce L. (1992c), The Development of Criminal Law and Its Enforcement: Public Interest

    or Political Transfers,3

    Journal des Economistes et des Etudes Humaines

    , 79-108.Benson, Bruce L. (1992d), Customary Law as a Social Contract: International Commercial Law, 2Constitutional Political Economy, 1-27.

    Benson, Bruce L. (1992e), Customary Indian Law: Two Case Studies, in Anderson, Terry L. (ed.),Property Rights and Indian Economics, Lanham , MD, Rowman and Littlefield Press.

    Benson, Bruce L. (1993), The Impetus for Recognizing Private Property and Adopting EthicalBehavior in a Market Economy: Natural Law, Government Law, or Evolving Self-Interest, 6Review of Austrian Economics, 43-80.

    Benson, Bruce L. (1994), Legal Philosophy, in Boettke, Peter J. (ed.), The Elgar Companion toAustrian Economics, London, Edward Elgar, 270-275.

    Benson, Bruce L. (1994), Emerging from the Hobbesian Jungle: Might Takes and Makes Rights, 5Constitutional Political Economy, 129-158. Translated into Spanish and republished (1995)LasInstituciones y Los Derechos de Propiedad al Emerger de la Jungla Hobbesiana: La FuerzaQuita los Reprinted Derechos y los Crea Libertas, 12, 35-75.

    Benson, Bruce L. (1995), Competition Among Legal Institutions: Implications for the Evolution ofLaw, in Gerken, Luden (ed.), Competition Among Institutions, London, Macmillan, 153-175.

    Benson, Bruce L. (1995), An Exploration of the Impact of Modern Arbitration Statutes on theDevelopment of Arbitration in the United States, 11 Journal of Law, Economics, andOrganization , 479-501.

    Berlin, I. (1970), Two Concepts of Liberty, in Berlin, I. (ed.), Four Essays on Liberty, New York,NY, Oxford University Press.

    Berman, Harold J. and Dasser, Felix J. (1990), The New Law Merchant and the Old: Sources,Content, and Legitimacy, in Carbonneau, Thomas E. (ed.),Lex Mercatoria and Arbitration: ADiscussion of the New Law Merchant, New York, Dobbs Ferry, Transnational Juris Publications.

    Bernstein, Lisa (1996), Merchant Law In a Merchant Court: Rethinking the Codes Search forImmanent Business Norms, 144University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 1765 ff.

    Binmore, Ken and Samuelson, Larry (1994), An Economists Perspective on the Evolution of Norms,150Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 45-63.

    Boyd, R. and Richerson, P.J. (1992), Punishment Allows the Evolution of Cooperation (or AnythingElse) in Sizable Groups, 13Ethology and Sociobiology, 171-195.

    Boyd, R. and Richerson, P.J. (1994), The Evolution of Norms: An Anthropological View, 150Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 72-86.

  • 8/14/2019 Spontenaous Emergence of Law - Customary Law

    19/28

    9500 Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law 621

    Bromley, Daniel W. (1989), Institutional Change and Economic Efficiency,23Journal of EconomicIssues, 735-759.

    Brownlie, Ian (1990), Principles of Public International Law, 4th edn, Oxford, Clarendon Press.Buchanan, James M. (1975), The Limits of Liberty: Between Anarchy and Leviathan , Chicago,

    University of Chicago Press.Buchanan, James M. (1979), General Implications of Subjectivism in Economics, in X (ed.), What

    Should Economists Do?, Indianapolis, Liberty Press.Buchanan, James M. (1991), The Foundations for Normative Individualism, in X (ed.), The

    Economics and the Ethics of Constitutional Order, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press.

    Buchanan, James M. (1994), Choosing What to Choose, 150 Journal of Institutional andTheoretical Economics, 123-135.Buxbaum, Hertig and Hirsch, Hopt (1996) (eds), European Economic and Business Law, Legal and

    Economic Analyses on Integration and Harmonization , Berlin, Springer, 401 p.Cassone, Alberto and Marchese, Carla (1994), Indulgenze Religiose: unAnalisi Economica, 2-3

    Economia delle Scelte Pubbliche, 191-209.Charney, J.I. (1986), The Persistent Objector Rule and the Development of Customary International

    Law, 56British Yearbook of International Law, 1 ff.Christiansen, Gregory B. (1990), Law as a Discovery Procedure, 9Cato Journal, 497-530.Clark, Robert C. (1981), The Interdisciplinary Study of Legal Evolution, 90Yale Law Journal,

    1238-1274.Clay, Karen (1997), Trade Without Law: Private-Order Institutions in Mexican California, 13

    Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 202-231.Coleman, Jules L. (1992),Risks and Wrongs, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.Contending with Hayek (1994), On Liberalism, Spontaneous Order and The Post-Communist

    Societies in Transition, Bern, Peter Lang.

    Cooter, Robert D. (1989), Kin Groups and the Common Law Process, in Larmour, Peter (ed.),Customary Land Tenure: Registration and Decentralisation in Papua New Guinea, MonographXXIX, Papua New Guinea Institute of Applied Social and Economic Research, 33-50.

    Cooter, Robert D. (1991), Inventing Market Property: The Land Courts of Papua New Guinea, 25Law and Society Review, 759-801.

    Cooter, Robert D. (1992), Against Legal Centrism 81 California Law Review, 425 ff.Cooter, Robert D. (1993), Against Legal Centrism: Review of Robert C. Ellicksons Order Without

    Law, 81California Law Review, 417 ff.Cooter, Robert D. (1994a), Structural Adjudication and the New Law Merchant: A Model of

    Decentralized Law, 14International Review of Law and Economics, 215-231. Reprinted underthe title, The Structural Approach to Decentralizing Law: A Theory of Games and Norms, in abook edited by Gerard Hertig.

    Cooter, Robert D. (1994b), Decentralized Law for a Complex Economy, 23Southwestern LawReview, Hayek Symposium, 443-451.

    Cooter, Robert D. (1996), Decentralized Law for a Complex Economy: The Structural Approach toAdjudicating the New Law Merchant, University of Pennsylvania Law Review.

  • 8/14/2019 Spontenaous Emergence of Law - Customary Law

    20/28

    622 Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law 9500

    DAmato, A. (1971), The Concept of Custom in International Law, Ithaca, NY, Cornell UniversityPress.

    Eger, Thomas (1996), Die Evolution von Recht als Proze der Selbstorganisation (The Evolution ofLaw as a Process of Self-Organization), in Priddat, B.P. and Wegner, G. (eds), ZwischenInstitution und Evolution. Neue Anstze in der konomischen Theorie, Marburg, Metropolis,211-244.

    Eger, Thomas and Weise, Peter (1995), Die Evolution von Normen aus Unordnung, Ein synergetischesModell (The Evolution of Norms out of Disorder, A Synergetic Model), in X. (ed.), konomieund Gesellschaft. Jahrbuch 11, Markt, Norm und Moral, Frankfurt/New York, 192-209.

    Eisenberg, Melvin Aron (1988),The Nature of the Common Law, Cambridge, MA, Harvard UniversityPress.

    Ellickson, R.C. (1991), Order Without Law: How Neighbors Settle Disputes, Cambridge, MA,Harvard University Press.

    Ellickson, R.C. (1994), The Aim of Order Without Law, 150 Journal of Institutional andTheoretical Economics, 97-100.

    Elliott, E. Donald (1984), Holmes and Evolution: Legal Process as Artificial Intelligence, 13Journalof Legal Studies, 113-146.

    Elliott, E. Donald, Ackerman, Bruce A. and Millian, John C. (1985), Toward a Theory of StatutoryEvolution: The Federaliza tion of Environmental Law, 1 Journal of Law, Economics, andOrganization , 313-340.

    Epstein, Richard A. (1980), The Static Conception of the Common Law, 9Journal of Legal Studies,253-275.

    Epstein, Richard A. (1992), The Path to the T. J. Hooper: The Theory and History of Custom in theLaw of Tort, 21Journal of Legal Studies, 1-38.

    Fortier, V. (1991), La Fonction Normative des Notions Floues (The Normative Functions of theVagueness Notions), Aix-Marseille, Presses Universitaires d, 755 p.

    Frank, Robert H. (1987), If Homo Economicus Could Choose his Utility Function, Would He wantone with a Conscience?, 77American Economic Review, 593-604.

    Frank, Robert H. (1994), Passions Within Reason: The Strategic Role of Emotions, New York, W.W.Norton.

    Frech, H. Edward III (1972), The Public Choice Theory of Murray N. Rothbard: A ModernAnarchist, 14Public Choice, 143-154.

    Fried, Charles, Summers, Robert S., Tullock, Gordon and Arrow, Kenneth J. (1982), Commentary onHirshleifer Paper, 4Research in Law and Economics, 61-208.

    Friedman, David D. (1979), Private Creation and Enforcement of Law: A Historical Case, 8Journalof Legal Studies, 399-415.

    Fudenberg, Drew and Maskin, Eric (1986), The Folk Theorem in Repeated Games with Discountingor with Incomplete Information, 54Econometrica, 533-554.

    Fuller, Lon L. (1969), The Morality of Law. Revised Edition, New Haven, CT, Yale University Press.Galanter, Marc (1987), Conceptualizing Legal Change and Its Effect: A Comment on George Priests

    Measuring Legal Change, 3Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 235-241.Gauthier, David Peter (1986),Morals by Agreement, Oxford, Clarendon.Goldberg, Victor P. (1974), Institutional Change and the Quasi-Invisible Hand, 17Journal of Law

    and Economics, 461-492. Reprinted in Goldberg, Victor P. (ed.) (1989), Readings in theEconomics of Contract Law, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 169-173.

  • 8/14/2019 Spontenaous Emergence of Law - Customary Law

    21/28

    9500 Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law 623

    Goodman, John C. (1978), An Economic Theory of the Evolution of the Common Law, 7Journalof Legal Studies, 393-406.

    Gordon, Wendy J. (1992), Of Harms and Benefits: Torts, Restitution, and Intellectual Property, 21Journal of Legal Studies, 449-482.

    Grady, Mark F. (1992), Toward a Positive Economic Theory of Antitrust,30Economic Inquiry, 225ff.

    Grady, Mark F. (1995), Legal Evolution and Precedent, 3Annual Review of Law and Ethics , 147ff.

    Greif, Avner (1989), Reputation and Coalitions in Medieval Trade: Evidence on the Maghribi

    Traders,49

    Journal of Economic History

    , 857 ff.Hardin, Garrett (1968), The Tragedy of the Commons, 162Science, 1243 ff.Harsanyi, John C. (1955), Cardinal Welfare Individualistic Ethics, and Interpersonal Comparisons of

    Utility, 63Journal of Political Economy, 315 ff.Hart, Herbert Lionel A. (1961), The Concept of Law, Oxford, Clarendon.Hayek, Friedrich A. von (1955), The Counterrevolution of Science, New York, NY, Free Press.Hayek, Friedrich A. von (1960), The Constitution of Liberty, Chicago, University of Chicago Press.Hayek, Friedrich A. von (1967), The Results of Human Action but not of Human Design, in X (ed.),

    Studies in Philosophy, Politics and Economics, Chicago, University of Chicago Press.Hayek, Friedrich A. von (1989), The Fatal Conceit, Chicago, University of Chicago Press.Heiner, Ronald A. (1983), Origin of Predictable Behavior,73American Economic Review , 561-595.Hesse, Gnter (1980), Der Property-Rights-Ansatz. Eine konomische Theorie der Vernderung des

    Rechts? (The Property Rights Approach. An Economic Theory of Legal Change?),195Jahrbuchfr Nationalkonomie und Statistik, 481 ff.

    Hesse, Gnter (1983), Zur Erklrung der nderung von Handlungsrechten mit Hilfe derkonomischen Theorie (The Explanation of the Change of Property Rights with Aid from

    Economic Theory), in Schller, Alfred (ed.),Property Rights und konomische Theorie

    ,Mnchen, Vahlen, 79-109.Hirshleifer, Jack (1982), Evolutionary Models in Economics and Law: Cooperation versus Conflict

    Strategies, 4Research in Law and Economics, 1-60.Hirshleifer, Jack and Coll Martinez, Juan Carlos (1988), What Strategies can Support the Evolutionary

    Emergence of Cooperation?, 32Journal of Conflict Resolution, 367-398.Holmes, Oliver Wendell (1980), The Common Law, Boston, Little Brown.Hovenkamp, Herbert J. (1983), The Economics of Legal History, 67Minnesota Law Review,

    645-697.Huang, Peter H. and Wu, Ho-Mou (1994), More Order without More Law: A Theory of Social Norms

    and Organizational Cultures, 10Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 390-406.Jaffe, Austin J. (1988), Toward an Evolutionary Theory of Trade Associations: The Case of Real

    Estate Appraisers, 16 American Real Estate and Urban Economics Association Journal,230-256.

    Janis, M.W. (1993),An Introduction to International Law, New York, Little Brown and Co..

  • 8/14/2019 Spontenaous Emergence of Law - Customary Law

    22/28

    624 Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law 9500

    Josserand, L. (1937), Un Ordre Juridique Nouveau (A New Juridical Order), Dalloz, 41 p.Kelsen, Hans (1939), Thorie du Droit International Coutumier, 1 Revue Internationale de la

    Thorie du Droit (New Series), 263 ff.Kelsen, Hans (1945), General Theory of Law and State, New Jersey, Lawbook Exchange.Kennedy, Duncan (1981), Cost-Reduction Theory as Legitimation,90Yale Law Journal, 1275-1283.Kitch, Edmund W. (1987), Law and the Economic Order, in Lipson, Leon and Wheeler, Stanton

    (eds),Law and the Social Sciences, New York, Russel Sage Foundation, 109-149.Kitch, Edmund W. (1991), Business Organization Law: State or Federal?, in Buxbaum, Richard M.,

    Hertig, Gerard, Hirsch, Alain and Hopt, Klaus J. (eds), European Business Law, Berlin, Walter

    de Gruyter, 35 ff.Kitch, Edmund W. (1996), Competition Between Securities Markets: Good or Bad?, in X (ed.), TheFuture for the Securities Market: Legal and Regulatory Aspects, Oxford, Clarendon, 233 ff.

    Klein, B. (1996), Why Hold-Ups Occur: The Self-Enforcing Range of Contractual Relationships, 34Economic Inquiry, 444 ff.

    Klein, B. and Leffler, K. (1981), The Role of Market Forces in Assuring Contractual Performance,89Journal of Political Economy, 615-641.

    Kobayashi, Bruce H. and Ribstein, Larry E. (1996), Evolution and Spontaneous Uniformity: Evidencefrom the Evolution of the Limited Liability Company, 34Economic Inquiry.

    Kontou, N. (1994), The Termination and Revision of Treaties in the Light of New CustomaryInternational Law, Oxford, Clarendon.

    Kornhauser, Lewis A. (1992), Are There Cracks in the Foundations of Spontaneous Order? BookReview of Ellickson, Order without Law, 67New York University Law Review, 647 ff.

    Kraus, Jody S. (1997), Segal Design and the Evolution of Commercial Norms, 16Journal of LegalStudies, 377-411.

    Krauss, Michael I. (1994), La Rglementation Contre le March dans le Dveloppement de Normes

    (Regulation against the Market in Norms Formation), 5Journal des Economistes et des EtudesHumaines, 573-599.Kronman, Anthony T. (1985), Contract Law and the State of Nature, 1Journal of Law, Economics,

    and Organization, 5-32.Kubasek, N. (1985), The Artificiality of Economic Models as a Guide for Legal Evolution, 33

    Cleveland State Law Review, 505-512.Kunz, Harald (1985), Zur Entstehung und Verhaltenswirkung sozialer Normen, mit einigen

    Argumenten fr eine konomisch rationale Kriminalpolitik (On the Evolution and the IncentiveEffect of Social Norms, with Some Arguments for an Economic Rational Crime Policy), 68Monatsschrift fr Kriminologie und Strafsrechtsreform, 202-215.

    Larmore, Charles E. (1987), Liberalism and the Neutrality of the State, in Larmore, Charles E. (ed.),Patterns of Moral Complexity, Cambridge, New York.

    Lehmann, Michael (1982), konomie, Sozialbiologie - Humanwissenschaften. ber dieNotwendigkeit und Mglichkeit einer interdisziplinren Grundlagenforschung (Economics, SocialBiology - Human Sciences. About the Necessity and Possibility of an InterdisciplinaryFundamental Reform),Der Betriebs-Berater, 1997-2004.

    Lehmann, Michael (1986), Evolution in Biologie, konomie und Jurisprudenz (Evolution in Biology,Economics and Jurisprudence), 17Rechtstheorie, 463-477.

  • 8/14/2019 Spontenaous Emergence of Law - Customary Law

    23/28

    9500 Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law 625

    Lehmann, Michael (1993), Das Prinzip Wettbewerb. Ein gemeinsames Gesetz der Evolution frBiologie, konomie und Wirtschaftsrecht (The Competition Principle. A Common Law ofEvolution for Biology. Economics and Commercial Law), in McGuire, Michael T. (ed.), DerFaktor Mensch im neuen Europa, Luchterhand, Neuwied et. al., 241-258.

    Leibenstein, Harvey (1982), The Prisoners Dilemma in the Invisible Hand: An Analysis of IntrafirmProductivity, 72American Economic Review. Papers and Proceedings , 92 ff.

    Lemieux, Pierre (1983), Du Libralisme lAnarcho-capitalisme (From Liberalism toAnarcho-Capitalism), Paris, Presses Universitaires de France (PUF).

    Lemieux, Pierre (1988), LAnarcho-Capitalisme (What is Anarcho-Capitalism?), Paris, PressesUniversitaires de France (PUF).

    Leoni, B. (1991), Freedom and the Law, 3rd edn, Indianapolis, Liberty Fund.Levy, D. (1988), Utility-Enhancing Consumption Constraints, 4Economics and Philosophy, 69-88.Levy, D. (1992), Adam Smith and the Texas A&M; Rats, in Levy, D. (ed.), The Economic Ideas of

    Ordinary People: From Preferences to Trade, New York, NY, Routledge.Lewis, D. (1969), Convention: A Philosophical Study, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press.Leyd, L., Leydesdoff, L.A., Besselaar, P.V. and Allen, P.M. (1994), Evolutionary Economics and

    Chaos Theory: New Directions in Technology Studies, New York, St. Martins Press.Libecap, Gary D. (1978), Economic Variables and the Development of the Law: The Case of Western

    Mineral Rights, 38Journal of Economic History, 338-362.Loasby, Brian J. (1976),Choice, Complexity, and Ignorance: An Enquiry into Economic Theory and

    the Practice of Decision-Making, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.Mackaay, Ejan (1988), LOrdre Spontan Comme Fondement du Droit - un Survol des Modles de

    lmergence des Rgles dans une Socit Civile (Spontaneous Order as Foundation of Law - ASurvey of Models of the Emergence of Rules in Civil Society), 22Revue Juridique Themis,347-383.

    Mackaay, Ejan (1989), LOrdre Spontan comme Fondement du Droit - un Survol des Modles delEmergence des Rgles dans la Socit Civile (Spontaneous Order as the Foundation of Law - ASurvey of Models of the Emergence of Rules in Civil Society), 3Revue Internationale de DroitEconomique, 247-287.

    Mackaay, Ejan (1995), Mededinging, Welvaart en Federalisme (Competition, Welfare andFederalism), in Kanning, Walter (ed.),Liber Amicorum voor Arnold Heertje, Leiden, StenfertKroese, 93-100.

    Mateesco, N.M. (1947),La Coutume dans les Cycles Juridiques Internationaux, Paris.McAdams, H. (1997), The Origin, Development, and Regulation of Norms, 96 Michigan Law

    Review, 338 ff.Miller, Geoffrey P. (1993), Ritual and Regulation: A Legal Economic Interpretation of Selected

    Biblical Texts, 22Journal of Legal Studies, 477-501.Miller, Geoffrey P. (1993), Contracts of Genesis, 22Journal of Legal Studies, 15-45.Miller, Geoffrey P. (1994), The Legal-Economic Analysis of Comparative Civil Procedure, the

    Legal-Economic Approach to Biblical Interpretation, 150 Journal of Institutional andTheoretical Economics, 755 ff.

    Miller, Geoffrey P. (1995a), Verbal Feud in the Hebrew Bible: Judges 3:12-30 and 19-21',55Journalof Near Eastern Studies, 105 ff.

  • 8/14/2019 Spontenaous Emergence of Law - Customary Law

    24/28

    626 Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law 9500

    Miller, Geoffrey P. (1995b), J as Constitutionalist: A Legal-Economic Interpretation of Exodus17:8-16 and Related Texts,70Chicago-Kent Law Review, 1829 ff. to be republished in Lindgren,James and Miller, Laurent Geoffrey (eds),Ancient Law: the New Learning (tentative title) (1996)

    Miller, Geoffrey P. (1996a),A Riposte Form in the Song of Deborah , Manuscript.Miller, Geoffrey P. (1996b), Foreword: The Development of Ancient Near Eastern Law, 70

    Chicago-Kent Law Review, 1623 ff.Miller, Geoffrey P. (1996c), Ancient Law: the New Learning (tentative title) (1996) Constitutionalist:

    A Legal-Economic Interpretation of Exodus 17:8-16 and Related Texts, 70Chicago-Kent LawReview, 1829 ff. To be republished in Lindgren, James and Miller, Lauren Geoffrey (eds).

    Miller, Geoffrey P. (1996d), The Song of Deborah: A Legal-Economic Analysis, 144University ofPennsylvania Law Review, 2293 ff.Miller, Geoffrey P. (1998), A Riposte Form in the Song of Deborah, in Frymer-Kensky, Tikva,

    Levinson, Bernard and Matthews, Victor (eds), Gender and Law in the Hebrew Bible and theAncient Near East, Shefheld Academic Press.

    Miller, Geoffrey P., Lindgren, James and Laurent Mayali (1995), Why Ancient Law?, 70Chicago-Kent Law Review, 1465 ff.

    Mueller, Dennis C. (1989), A Just Social Contract, in Mueller, Dennis C. (ed.), Public Choice II,Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.

    Noreau, Pierre (1993),Droit Prventif - Le Droit au-Del de la Loi (Preventive Law - Law BeyondLegislation), Montral, ditions Thmis.

    ODriscoll, Gerald P., Jr and Rizzo, Mario J. (1986), Subjectivism, Uncertainty, and Rules, inKirzner, Israel M. (ed.), Subjectivism, Intelligibility and Economic Understanding. Essays inHonor of Ludwig M. Lachmann on his Eightieth Birthday , London, Macmillan, 252-267.

    Ott, Claus and Schfer, Hans-Bernd (1991), Emergence and Construction of Efficient Rules in the Legal System of German Civil Law, Paper Presented at the European Law and Economics

    Association.Parisi, Francesco (1994), Autonomy and Private Ordering in Contract Law, 1European Journal ofLaw and Economics, 213-227.

    Parisi, Francesco (1995), Toward a Theory of Spontaneous Law, 6 Constitutional PoliticalEconomy, 211-231.

    Parisi, Francesco (1996a), Normative Knowledge and Self-Enforcing Rules in International Law, 2International Legal Theory, 27-30.

    Parisi, Francesco (1996b), Law as a Voluntary Enterprise, in Ratnapala, S. and Moens, G. (eds), TheJurisprudence of Liberty, London, Butterworths.

    Parisi, Francesco (1997), The Genesis of Liability in Ancient Law, George Mason University Law andEconomics Working Paper Series, 97-07.

    Parisi, Francesco (1998a), Customary Law, in Newman, Peter (ed.), The New Palgrave Dictionaryof Economics and the Law, New York, Macmillan, 572-578.

    Parisi, Francesco (1998b), The Economics of Customary Law: Lessons From EvolutionarySocio-Biology, in Ott, Claus and von Wangenheim, Georg (eds), Essays in Law and EconomicsIV, Antwerpen, Maklu, 245-269.

    Parisi, Francesco (1998c), Opinio Iuris Revisited: A Law and Economics Perspective (Forthcoming),4International Legal Theory.

  • 8/14/2019 Spontenaous Emergence of Law - Customary Law

    25/28

    9500 Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law 627

    Parisi, Francesco (1999), The Cost of the Game: A Topology of Social Interactions (Forthcoming),European Journal of Law and Economics .

    Parisi, Francesco and Ribstein, Larry E. (1998), Choice of Law, New York, Macmillan.Pollock, F. (1929), First Book of Jurisprudence, 6th edn, London, Macmillan.Popper, Karl R. (1995), The Open Society and Its Enemies , 5th edn, London, Routledge.Posner, Eric A. (1996a), Law, Economics and Inefficient Norms, 145University of Pennsylvania

    Law Review, 1697-1744.Posner, Eric A. (1996b), Norms, Formalities, and the Statute of Frauds: A Comment, 144University

    of Pennsylvania Law Review, 1971 ff.

    Posner, Richard A. (1980), A Theory of Primitive Society, with Special Reference to Law, 23Journalof Law and Economics, 1-53.Posner, Richard A. (1981), The Economics of Justice, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 415

    p.Priest, George L. (1981), The New Scientism in Legal Scholarship: A Comment on Clark and Posner,

    90Yale Law Journal, 1284-1295.Priest, George L. (1987), Measuring Legal Change, 3 Journal of Law, Economics, and

    Organization , 193-225.Prigogine, Ilya and Stengers, Isabelle (1984), Order Out of Chaos: Mans New Dialogue with Nature,

    Boulder, CO, New Science Library.Rapoport, Anatol (1987), Prisoners Dilemma, in X (ed.), The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of

    Economics, New York, McGraw-Hill.Rawls, John (1971),A Theory of Justice, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press.Raz, J. (1986), The Morality of Freedom, Oxford, Clarendon.Reese, David A. (1989), Does the Common Law Evolve?, 12Hamline Law Review, 321-353.Ress, G. (1994), Ex Ante Safeguards Against Ex Post Opportunism in International Treaties: Theory

    and Practice of International Public Law, 150 Journal of Institutional and TheoreticalEconomics, 279-303.Ribstein, Larry E. and Kobayashi, Bruce H. (1995), Uniform Laws, Model Laws and Limited Liability

    Companies, 66University of Colorado Law Review, 947-999.Ribstein, Larry E. and Kobayashi, Bruce H. (1996), An Economic Analysis of Uniform State Laws,

    25Journal of Legal Studies, 131-199.Ridley, Matt (1997), Origins of Virtue: Human Instincts and the Evolution of Cooperation, New

    York, Viking.Rizzo, Mario J. (1980), Symposium: Change in the Common Law: Legal and Economic Perspectives.

    A Symposium Sponsored by The Institute for Humane Studies and the Liberty Fund, 9Journalof Legal Studies, 189-427.

    Roe, Mark J. (1996), Chaos and Evolution in Law and Economics, 109Harvard Law Review,641-668.

    Rubin, Paul H. (1982), Symposium: Evolutionary Models in Economics and Law,4Research in Lawand Economics, 218 ff.

    Rubin, Paul H. (1983),Business Firms and the Common Law. The Evolution of Efficient Rules , New

    York, Praeger, 189 p.Rubin, Paul H. (1993), Private Mechanisms for the Creation of Efficient Institutions for MarketEconomies, in Somogyi, Laszlo (ed.), The Political Economy of The Transition Process inEastern Europe, Cheltenham, Edward Elgar.

  • 8/14/2019 Spontenaous Emergence of Law - Customary Law

    26/28

    628 Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law 9500

    Rubin, Paul H. (1994), Growing A Legal System in the Post-Communist Economies, 27CornellInternational Law Journal, 1-47.

    Rubin, Paul H. (1996), Promises, Promises: Contracts in Russia and Other Post-CommunistEconomies, Shaftesbury Papers, Edward Elgar and the Locke Institute.

    Rubin, Paul H. (in press), Growing a Legal System, with Special Reference to the Post-CommunistEconomies Center for International Reform and the Informal Sector, Working Paper, No. 63.

    Rubin, Paul H. and Tesche, Jean (in press), Enforcement of Agreements in Russia, in the Rule of Lawand Economic Reform in Russia, in Sachs, Jeffrey (ed.), Boulder, Westview Press, 912 ff.

    Ruhl, J.B. and Ruhl, H.J., Jr (1997), The Arrow of the Law in Modern Administrative States: UsingComplexity Theory to Reveal the Diminishing Returns and Increasing Risks the Burgeoning ofLaw Poses to Society, 30University of California at Davis Law Review, 405 ff.

    Salmond, J.W. (1966),Jurisprudence (12th edn), London, Sweet & Maxwell.Santagata, Walter (1995), Istituzioni per il Mercato dellArte: Artisti e Mercanti tra Regole,

    Convenzioni e Allocazioni dei Diritti (Institutions for the Market of Works of Art: Artists andMerchants among Rules, Conventions and Allocation of Rights), Economia Pubblica, 87-115.

    Savatier Ren (1959),Les Mthamorphoses Economiques et Sociales du Droit Civil Aujourdhui(The Economic and Sociologic Metamorphoses of Civil Law Today).

    Schlicht, Ekkehart (1993), Koordinationskosten und Social Capital (Co-ordination Costs and SocialCapital), in Schlieper, Ulrich and Schmidtchen, Dieter (eds), Makro, Geld & Institutionen,Tbingen, 95-100.

    Schmidt Trenz, Hans Jorg and Schmidtchen, Dieter (1994), Theorie optimaler Rechtsrume. DieRegulierung sozialer Beziehungen durch die Kontrolle von Territorium (Theory of Optimum LegalAreas), 13Jahrbuch fr Neue Politische konomie, 7-29.

    Schmidtchen, Dieter (1995), Die Zwillingsideen der Evolution und der spontanen Bildung einerOrdnung (The Twin Ideas of Evolution and Spontaneous Order), in Francke, H.-H. (ed.),konomischer Individualismus und Freiheitliche Verfassung, Freiburg, 239-271.

    Schotter, Andrew (1981), Economic Theory of Social Institutions, Cambridge, MA, HarvardUniversity Press.

    Schwartz, Warren F. et al. (1984), The Duel: Can These Gentlement be Acting Efficiently?, 8Journal of Legal Studies, 321 ff.

    Scott Kenneth E. (1994), Bounded Rationality and Social Norms, 150Journal of Institutional andTheoretical Economics, 315-319.

    Selten, Reinhard (1978), The Chain-Store Paradox, 9Theory and Decision, 127-159.Sen, Amartya K. (1979), Rational Fools: A Critique of the Behavioural Foundations of Economic

    Theory, in Hahn, F. and Hollis, M. (eds), Philosophy and Economic Theory, Oxford, Clarendon.Shubik, Martin (1987), Game Theory in the Social Sciences: Concepts and Solutions,4th edn,

    Boston, MA, The MIT Press.Shughart, William F., II and Tollison, Robert D. (1985), Corporate Chartering: An Exploration in the

    Economics of Legal Change, 23Economic Inquiry, 585-599.Simpson, Alfred William Brian (1979), The Horwitz Thesis and the History of Contracts, 46

    University of Chicago Law Review, 533-601.

  • 8/14/2019 Spontenaous Emergence of Law - Customary Law

    27/28

    9500 Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law 629

    Smith, James Charles (1977), Book Review of Morton J. Horwitz the Transformation of AmericanLaw (1780-1860), 53Wisconsin Law Review, 1253-1276.

    Stearns, M.L. (1994), The Misguided Renaissance of Social Choice, 103Yale Law Journal, 1219 ff.Terrebonne, R. Peter (1981), A Strictly Evolutionary Model of Common Law, 10Journal of Legal

    Studies, 397-407.Tietzel, Manfred (1986), Zur Entstehung des Privateigentums (On the Evolution of Private Property),

    37Ordo, 105-127.Trakman, Leon E. (1983),The Law Merchant: The Evolution of Commercial Law, Littleton, CO, Fred

    B. Rothman and Company.

    Tucker, A.W. (1950),A Two-Person Dilemma

    , Unpublished manuscript. Reprinted in: Straffin, P.(1980) The Prisoners Dilemma, UMAP Journal, 101 ff.Tullock, Gordon (1987), Private Wants, Public Means - An Economic Analysis of the Desirable

    Scope of Government, Lanham (MD), University Press of America.Tunkin, G.I. (1961), Remarks on the Juridical Nature of Customary Norms in International Law,49

    California Law Review, 419 ff.Turnbull, Shann (1977),Impact of Mining Royalties on Aboriginal Communities in the Northern

    Territory, First Report, Parliamentary Paper, Canberra, Australian Government Publishing Service,No. 135/1978, Oct..

    Turnbull, Shann (1978), Economic Development of Aboriginal Communities in the NorthernTerritory Second Report, Self-sufficiency (with Land Rights), Parliamentary Paper, Canberra,Australian Government Publishing Service, No. 438/1978.

    Turnbull, Shann (1980), Economic Development of Aboriginal Communities in the NorthernTerritory: A Study in Two Parts, Department of Aboriginal Affairs, Canberra, AustralianGovernment Publishing Service.

    Turnbull, Shann (1986), When Land Owns People, 43 (4) Et cetera: A Review of General

    Semantics, 389-392.Udehn, Lars (1996), The Limits of Public Choice: A Sociological Critique of the Economic Theoryof Politics, London, Routledge.

    Ullman-Margalit, Edna (1977), The Emergence of Norms, Oxford, Clarendon.Vanberg, Viktor J. (1993), Rational Choice, Rule-Following and Institutions: An Evolutionary

    Perspective, in Gustafson, B., Knudsen, C. and Maki, U. (eds), Rationality, Institutions andEconomic Methodology, London, Routledge, 171-200.

    Vaughn, Karen I. (1982),Can Democratic Society Reform Itself: The Limits of Constructive Change,George Mason University Working Paper.

    Versteeg, J. Russell (1989), Law and the Security of Homeric Society (A Response to Richard A.Posner), 10Journal of Legal History, 265-284.

    Voigt, Stefan (1991), Die Evolutionsorientierte Theorie der Verfassung - Bemerkungen zum Ansatzvon Hayeks (The Evolutionary Theory of Constitution. Remarks on Hayeks Approach), 40Zeitschrift fr Wirtschaftspolitik, 93-107.

    Voigt, Stefan (1993), On the Internal Consistency of Hayeks Evolutionary oriented ConstitutionalEconomics - Some General Remarks, 3Journal des Economistes et des Etudes Humaines,

    461-476.Wagner, Richard E. (1992), Crafting Social Rules: Common Law vs. Statute Law, Once Again, 3Constitutional Political Economy, 381 ff.

    Walden, R.M. (1977), The Subjective Element in the Formation of Customary International Law, 12Israel Law Review, 344 ff.

  • 8/14/2019 Spontenaous Emergence of Law - Customary Law

    28/28

    630 Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law 9500

    Waldron, Jeremy (1993), Theoretical Foundations of Liberalism, in Waldron, Jeremy (ed.),LiberalRights: Collected Papers, 1981-1991, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.

    Wangenheim, Georg v. (1995), Die Evolution von Recht. Ursachen und Wirkungenhaeufigkeitsabhaengigen Verhaltens in der Rechtsfortbildung (The Evolution of Law. Causesand Effects of Frequency Dependend Behaviour in Legal Evolution), Tbingen, Mohr/Siebeck.

    Warren, Elizabeth (1981), Trade Usage and Parties in the Trade: An Economic Rationale for anInflexible Rule, 42University of Pittsburgh Law Review, 515 ff.

    Watrin, Christian (1996), Der Wettbewerb der Ordnungen als Entdeckungsverfahren fr einenachhaltige Entwicklung (Korreferat) (Sustainable Development and Competition AmongEconomic Systems as a Discovery Process), in Gerken, Lder (ed.), OrdnungspolitischeGrundfragen einer Politik der Nachhaltigkeit/Walter Eucken Institut, Baden-Baden, 103-113.

    Weber, M. (1978), Economy and Society, Berkeley, University of California Press.Weise, Peter (1996), Verhaltenskoordination durch soziale Normen und Krfte (Co-ordination of

    Behaviour by Social Norms and Forces), in Priddat, B.P. and Wegner, G. (eds), ZwischenInstitution und Evolution. Neue Anstze in der konomischen Theorie, Marburg, Metropolis,187-209.

    Weise, Peter and Eger, Thomas (1995), Die Evolution von Normen aus Unordnung, Ein synergetischesModell (The Evolution of Norms out of Disorder, A Synergetic Model), 11konomie undGesellschaft, 192-209.

    Williams, Stephen F. (1980), The Static Conception of the Common Law: A Comment, 9Journalof Legal Studies, 277-289.

    Williamson, O.E. (1983), Credible Commitments: Using Hostages to Support Exchange, 73American Economic Review, 519 ff.

    Wilson, James Q. (1993), The Moral Sense, New York, NY, Free Press.Witt, Ulrich (1986), Evolution and Stability of Cooperation without Enforceable Contracts, 39

    Kyklos, 245-266.Witt, Ulrich (1988), Eine Individualistische Theorie der Entwicklung konomischer Institutionen (AnIndividualistic Theory of the Evolution of Economic Institutions),9Jahrbuch fr Neue Politischekonomie, 72-95.

    Wolfke, K. (1993), Custom in Present International Law, 2nd edn, Amsterdam, Kluwer AcademicPublishers.

    Cases

    Fisheries Jurisdiction (U.K. v. Ice), 1974 I.C.J. 3 (July 25).North Sea Continental Shelf(F.R.G. v. Den.) (F.R.G. v. Neth.), 1969 I.C.J. 3 (Feb. 20).Asylum (Colom. v. Peru), 1950 I.C.J. 266, 275, 277 (Nov. 20).S.S. Wimbledon, 1923 P.C.I.J. (ser. A), No. 1, at 25.