Top Banner
Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics? ulya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo April 2010 ulya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?
97

Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics? › seminarpapers › et24062010.pdf · Huly a Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics? The environment (example)

Feb 02, 2021

Download

Documents

dariahiddleston
Welcome message from author
This document is posted to help you gain knowledge. Please leave a comment to let me know what you think about it! Share it to your friends and learn new things together.
Transcript
  • Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo

    April 2010

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • Introduction

    I Starting with the seminal work of Baron and Ferejohn (1989)noncooperative models of multilateral bargaining havebecome a staple of political economy and have been used innumerous applications.

    I The agreement rule (e.g., unanimity, majority, super-majority)is a key component of multilateral bargaining environments.

    I Large literature on comparing the performance of differentvoting rules in a variety of bargaining models.

    I Emphasis has been primarily on the efficiency of equilibriumoutcomes.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • Introduction

    I Starting with the seminal work of Baron and Ferejohn (1989)noncooperative models of multilateral bargaining havebecome a staple of political economy and have been used innumerous applications.

    I The agreement rule (e.g., unanimity, majority, super-majority)is a key component of multilateral bargaining environments.

    I Large literature on comparing the performance of differentvoting rules in a variety of bargaining models.

    I Emphasis has been primarily on the efficiency of equilibriumoutcomes.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • Introduction

    I Starting with the seminal work of Baron and Ferejohn (1989)noncooperative models of multilateral bargaining havebecome a staple of political economy and have been used innumerous applications.

    I The agreement rule (e.g., unanimity, majority, super-majority)is a key component of multilateral bargaining environments.

    I Large literature on comparing the performance of differentvoting rules in a variety of bargaining models.

    I Emphasis has been primarily on the efficiency of equilibriumoutcomes.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • Introduction

    I Starting with the seminal work of Baron and Ferejohn (1989)noncooperative models of multilateral bargaining havebecome a staple of political economy and have been used innumerous applications.

    I The agreement rule (e.g., unanimity, majority, super-majority)is a key component of multilateral bargaining environments.

    I Large literature on comparing the performance of differentvoting rules in a variety of bargaining models.

    I Emphasis has been primarily on the efficiency of equilibriumoutcomes.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • Introduction

    I Starting with the seminal work of Baron and Ferejohn (1989)noncooperative models of multilateral bargaining havebecome a staple of political economy and have been used innumerous applications.

    I The agreement rule (e.g., unanimity, majority, super-majority)is a key component of multilateral bargaining environments.

    I Large literature on comparing the performance of differentvoting rules in a variety of bargaining models.

    I Emphasis has been primarily on the efficiency of equilibriumoutcomes.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • This paper

    I We focus on comparing the distributional consequences(equity properties) of alternative voting rules in a simplebargaining environment.

    I It is commonly believed that, contrary to majority rule,unanimity rule protects minorities from the possibility ofexpropriation and is therefore more equitable.

    I We show that this is not necessarily the case in bargaining:unanimity rule can induce equilibrium outcomes that are moreunequal (or less equitable) than equilibrium outcomes undermajority rule.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • This paper

    I We focus on comparing the distributional consequences(equity properties) of alternative voting rules in a simplebargaining environment.

    I It is commonly believed that, contrary to majority rule,unanimity rule protects minorities from the possibility ofexpropriation and is therefore more equitable.

    I We show that this is not necessarily the case in bargaining:unanimity rule can induce equilibrium outcomes that are moreunequal (or less equitable) than equilibrium outcomes undermajority rule.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • This paper

    I We focus on comparing the distributional consequences(equity properties) of alternative voting rules in a simplebargaining environment.

    I It is commonly believed that, contrary to majority rule,unanimity rule protects minorities from the possibility ofexpropriation and is therefore more equitable.

    I We show that this is not necessarily the case in bargaining:unanimity rule can induce equilibrium outcomes that are moreunequal (or less equitable) than equilibrium outcomes undermajority rule.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • This paper

    I We focus on comparing the distributional consequences(equity properties) of alternative voting rules in a simplebargaining environment.

    I It is commonly believed that, contrary to majority rule,unanimity rule protects minorities from the possibility ofexpropriation and is therefore more equitable.

    I We show that this is not necessarily the case in bargaining:unanimity rule can induce equilibrium outcomes that are moreunequal (or less equitable) than equilibrium outcomes undermajority rule.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • The environment

    I There are n ≥ 2 players, who are endowed with differenttechnologies for providing some perfectly divisible surplus.

    I If player i were to provide, the amount of surplus potentiallyavailable for distribution would be yi , with y1 ≤ y2... ≤ yn.

    I At most one project can be implemented.

    I The players have to collectively decide which project toimplement (if any), and how to distribute the availablesurplus.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • The environment

    I There are n ≥ 2 players, who are endowed with differenttechnologies for providing some perfectly divisible surplus.

    I If player i were to provide, the amount of surplus potentiallyavailable for distribution would be yi , with y1 ≤ y2... ≤ yn.

    I At most one project can be implemented.

    I The players have to collectively decide which project toimplement (if any), and how to distribute the availablesurplus.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • The environment

    I There are n ≥ 2 players, who are endowed with differenttechnologies for providing some perfectly divisible surplus.

    I If player i were to provide, the amount of surplus potentiallyavailable for distribution would be yi , with y1 ≤ y2... ≤ yn.

    I At most one project can be implemented.

    I The players have to collectively decide which project toimplement (if any), and how to distribute the availablesurplus.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • The environment

    I There are n ≥ 2 players, who are endowed with differenttechnologies for providing some perfectly divisible surplus.

    I If player i were to provide, the amount of surplus potentiallyavailable for distribution would be yi , with y1 ≤ y2... ≤ yn.

    I At most one project can be implemented.

    I The players have to collectively decide which project toimplement (if any), and how to distribute the availablesurplus.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • The environment

    I There are n ≥ 2 players, who are endowed with differenttechnologies for providing some perfectly divisible surplus.

    I If player i were to provide, the amount of surplus potentiallyavailable for distribution would be yi , with y1 ≤ y2... ≤ yn.

    I At most one project can be implemented.

    I The players have to collectively decide which project toimplement (if any), and how to distribute the availablesurplus.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • The environment (example)

    I There is a single project that needs to be completed, whichentails the production of a unitary level of a perfectly divisible(private) good, x = 1.

    I The surplus generated (i.e., the amount of x net ofproduction costs) is then available for distribution.

    I There are n ≥ 2 players, who are endowed with differenttechnologies for producing x .

    I Player i ∈ {1, ..., n} can produce x = 1 at cost ci ∈ [0, 1].Without loss of generality let c1 ≥ c2... ≥ cn.

    I This implies that if i were to produce x , the amount ofsurplus potentially available for distribution would beyi = 1− ci , with y1 ≤ y2... ≤ yn.

    I The players have to collectively decide who (if anybody) willproduce x , and how to distribute the surplus y generated inthe event that production takes place.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • The environment (example)

    I There is a single project that needs to be completed, whichentails the production of a unitary level of a perfectly divisible(private) good, x = 1.

    I The surplus generated (i.e., the amount of x net ofproduction costs) is then available for distribution.

    I There are n ≥ 2 players, who are endowed with differenttechnologies for producing x .

    I Player i ∈ {1, ..., n} can produce x = 1 at cost ci ∈ [0, 1].Without loss of generality let c1 ≥ c2... ≥ cn.

    I This implies that if i were to produce x , the amount ofsurplus potentially available for distribution would beyi = 1− ci , with y1 ≤ y2... ≤ yn.

    I The players have to collectively decide who (if anybody) willproduce x , and how to distribute the surplus y generated inthe event that production takes place.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • The environment (example)

    I There is a single project that needs to be completed, whichentails the production of a unitary level of a perfectly divisible(private) good, x = 1.

    I The surplus generated (i.e., the amount of x net ofproduction costs) is then available for distribution.

    I There are n ≥ 2 players, who are endowed with differenttechnologies for producing x .

    I Player i ∈ {1, ..., n} can produce x = 1 at cost ci ∈ [0, 1].Without loss of generality let c1 ≥ c2... ≥ cn.

    I This implies that if i were to produce x , the amount ofsurplus potentially available for distribution would beyi = 1− ci , with y1 ≤ y2... ≤ yn.

    I The players have to collectively decide who (if anybody) willproduce x , and how to distribute the surplus y generated inthe event that production takes place.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • The environment (example)

    I There is a single project that needs to be completed, whichentails the production of a unitary level of a perfectly divisible(private) good, x = 1.

    I The surplus generated (i.e., the amount of x net ofproduction costs) is then available for distribution.

    I There are n ≥ 2 players, who are endowed with differenttechnologies for producing x .

    I Player i ∈ {1, ..., n} can produce x = 1 at cost ci ∈ [0, 1].Without loss of generality let c1 ≥ c2... ≥ cn.

    I This implies that if i were to produce x , the amount ofsurplus potentially available for distribution would beyi = 1− ci , with y1 ≤ y2... ≤ yn.

    I The players have to collectively decide who (if anybody) willproduce x , and how to distribute the surplus y generated inthe event that production takes place.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • The environment (example)

    I There is a single project that needs to be completed, whichentails the production of a unitary level of a perfectly divisible(private) good, x = 1.

    I The surplus generated (i.e., the amount of x net ofproduction costs) is then available for distribution.

    I There are n ≥ 2 players, who are endowed with differenttechnologies for producing x .

    I Player i ∈ {1, ..., n} can produce x = 1 at cost ci ∈ [0, 1].Without loss of generality let c1 ≥ c2... ≥ cn.

    I This implies that if i were to produce x , the amount ofsurplus potentially available for distribution would beyi = 1− ci , with y1 ≤ y2... ≤ yn.

    I The players have to collectively decide who (if anybody) willproduce x , and how to distribute the surplus y generated inthe event that production takes place.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • The environment (example)

    I There is a single project that needs to be completed, whichentails the production of a unitary level of a perfectly divisible(private) good, x = 1.

    I The surplus generated (i.e., the amount of x net ofproduction costs) is then available for distribution.

    I There are n ≥ 2 players, who are endowed with differenttechnologies for producing x .

    I Player i ∈ {1, ..., n} can produce x = 1 at cost ci ∈ [0, 1].Without loss of generality let c1 ≥ c2... ≥ cn.

    I This implies that if i were to produce x , the amount ofsurplus potentially available for distribution would beyi = 1− ci , with y1 ≤ y2... ≤ yn.

    I The players have to collectively decide who (if anybody) willproduce x , and how to distribute the surplus y generated inthe event that production takes place.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • The environment (example)

    I There is a single project that needs to be completed, whichentails the production of a unitary level of a perfectly divisible(private) good, x = 1.

    I The surplus generated (i.e., the amount of x net ofproduction costs) is then available for distribution.

    I There are n ≥ 2 players, who are endowed with differenttechnologies for producing x .

    I Player i ∈ {1, ..., n} can produce x = 1 at cost ci ∈ [0, 1].Without loss of generality let c1 ≥ c2... ≥ cn.

    I This implies that if i were to produce x , the amount ofsurplus potentially available for distribution would beyi = 1− ci , with y1 ≤ y2... ≤ yn.

    I The players have to collectively decide who (if anybody) willproduce x , and how to distribute the surplus y generated inthe event that production takes place.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • The environment (con’d)

    I Players have an identical single date payoff function which islinear in their share of the surplus, and discount the future ata common discount factor δ ∈ (0, 1).

    I In the event that agreement is never reached, all playersreceive a payoff of zero.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • The environment (con’d)

    I Players have an identical single date payoff function which islinear in their share of the surplus, and discount the future ata common discount factor δ ∈ (0, 1).

    I In the event that agreement is never reached, all playersreceive a payoff of zero.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • The environment (con’d)

    I Players have an identical single date payoff function which islinear in their share of the surplus, and discount the future ata common discount factor δ ∈ (0, 1).

    I In the event that agreement is never reached, all playersreceive a payoff of zero.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • The environment (cont’d)

    I We model the collective decision-making process as abargaining problem.

    I The protocol we consider is as follows:I In each period, a player is randomly offered the possibility of

    submitting a proposal for completing the project withprobability 1/n.

    I The selected player j may then make a (binding) proposalspecifying the way the surplus generated yj would bedistributed among all the players if her project were chosen, orforego the opportunity.

    I If a proposal is submitted, all players then vote (sequentially)on whether or not to approve it.

    I If q players vote in favor, then the proposal is implementedand the game ends. Otherwise, a new player is selected andthe process repeats itself (possibly ad infinitum).

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • The environment (cont’d)

    I We model the collective decision-making process as abargaining problem.

    I The protocol we consider is as follows:I In each period, a player is randomly offered the possibility of

    submitting a proposal for completing the project withprobability 1/n.

    I The selected player j may then make a (binding) proposalspecifying the way the surplus generated yj would bedistributed among all the players if her project were chosen, orforego the opportunity.

    I If a proposal is submitted, all players then vote (sequentially)on whether or not to approve it.

    I If q players vote in favor, then the proposal is implementedand the game ends. Otherwise, a new player is selected andthe process repeats itself (possibly ad infinitum).

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • The environment (cont’d)

    I We model the collective decision-making process as abargaining problem.

    I The protocol we consider is as follows:

    I In each period, a player is randomly offered the possibility ofsubmitting a proposal for completing the project withprobability 1/n.

    I The selected player j may then make a (binding) proposalspecifying the way the surplus generated yj would bedistributed among all the players if her project were chosen, orforego the opportunity.

    I If a proposal is submitted, all players then vote (sequentially)on whether or not to approve it.

    I If q players vote in favor, then the proposal is implementedand the game ends. Otherwise, a new player is selected andthe process repeats itself (possibly ad infinitum).

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • The environment (cont’d)

    I We model the collective decision-making process as abargaining problem.

    I The protocol we consider is as follows:I In each period, a player is randomly offered the possibility of

    submitting a proposal for completing the project withprobability 1/n.

    I The selected player j may then make a (binding) proposalspecifying the way the surplus generated yj would bedistributed among all the players if her project were chosen, orforego the opportunity.

    I If a proposal is submitted, all players then vote (sequentially)on whether or not to approve it.

    I If q players vote in favor, then the proposal is implementedand the game ends. Otherwise, a new player is selected andthe process repeats itself (possibly ad infinitum).

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • The environment (cont’d)

    I We model the collective decision-making process as abargaining problem.

    I The protocol we consider is as follows:I In each period, a player is randomly offered the possibility of

    submitting a proposal for completing the project withprobability 1/n.

    I The selected player j may then make a (binding) proposalspecifying the way the surplus generated yj would bedistributed among all the players if her project were chosen, orforego the opportunity.

    I If a proposal is submitted, all players then vote (sequentially)on whether or not to approve it.

    I If q players vote in favor, then the proposal is implementedand the game ends. Otherwise, a new player is selected andthe process repeats itself (possibly ad infinitum).

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • The environment (cont’d)

    I We model the collective decision-making process as abargaining problem.

    I The protocol we consider is as follows:I In each period, a player is randomly offered the possibility of

    submitting a proposal for completing the project withprobability 1/n.

    I The selected player j may then make a (binding) proposalspecifying the way the surplus generated yj would bedistributed among all the players if her project were chosen, orforego the opportunity.

    I If a proposal is submitted, all players then vote (sequentially)on whether or not to approve it.

    I If q players vote in favor, then the proposal is implementedand the game ends. Otherwise, a new player is selected andthe process repeats itself (possibly ad infinitum).

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • The environment (cont’d)

    I We model the collective decision-making process as abargaining problem.

    I The protocol we consider is as follows:I In each period, a player is randomly offered the possibility of

    submitting a proposal for completing the project withprobability 1/n.

    I The selected player j may then make a (binding) proposalspecifying the way the surplus generated yj would bedistributed among all the players if her project were chosen, orforego the opportunity.

    I If a proposal is submitted, all players then vote (sequentially)on whether or not to approve it.

    I If q players vote in favor, then the proposal is implementedand the game ends. Otherwise, a new player is selected andthe process repeats itself (possibly ad infinitum).

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • The environment (cont’d)

    I q ∈ {1, ..., n} specifies the voting rule (e.g., q = n denotesunanimity and q = (n + 1)/2 majority rule), and hence thegame.

    I i ∈ {1, ..., n} specifies each player’s ranking in the endowmentdistribution (with 1 denoting the least productive and n themost productive player).

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • The environment (cont’d)

    I q ∈ {1, ..., n} specifies the voting rule (e.g., q = n denotesunanimity and q = (n + 1)/2 majority rule), and hence thegame.

    I i ∈ {1, ..., n} specifies each player’s ranking in the endowmentdistribution (with 1 denoting the least productive and n themost productive player).

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • The environment (cont’d)

    I q ∈ {1, ..., n} specifies the voting rule (e.g., q = n denotesunanimity and q = (n + 1)/2 majority rule), and hence thegame.

    I i ∈ {1, ..., n} specifies each player’s ranking in the endowmentdistribution (with 1 denoting the least productive and n themost productive player).

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • Comments on the model environment

    I Baron and Ferejohn (1989) with heterogeneous “cakes”.

    I Merlo and Wilson (1995, 1998) and Eraslan and Merlo (2002)with perfect correlation between the “cake” and the“proposer” processes.

    I Deliberately “egalitarian” protocol, and no additionaldimensions of heterogeneity other than in the players’technology endowments.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • Comments on the model environment

    I Baron and Ferejohn (1989) with heterogeneous “cakes”.

    I Merlo and Wilson (1995, 1998) and Eraslan and Merlo (2002)with perfect correlation between the “cake” and the“proposer” processes.

    I Deliberately “egalitarian” protocol, and no additionaldimensions of heterogeneity other than in the players’technology endowments.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • Comments on the model environment

    I Baron and Ferejohn (1989) with heterogeneous “cakes”.

    I Merlo and Wilson (1995, 1998) and Eraslan and Merlo (2002)with perfect correlation between the “cake” and the“proposer” processes.

    I Deliberately “egalitarian” protocol, and no additionaldimensions of heterogeneity other than in the players’technology endowments.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • Comments on the model environment

    I Baron and Ferejohn (1989) with heterogeneous “cakes”.

    I Merlo and Wilson (1995, 1998) and Eraslan and Merlo (2002)with perfect correlation between the “cake” and the“proposer” processes.

    I Deliberately “egalitarian” protocol, and no additionaldimensions of heterogeneity other than in the players’technology endowments.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • Notation and some useful definitions

    I Restrict attention to stationary subgame perfect (SSP)equilibria.

    I Let vq = (vq1 , ..., vqn ) denote the payoff vector generated by an

    SSP strategy profile in the q-game.

    I Let

    G =2

    ∑ni=1 iyi

    n∑n

    i=1 yi− n + 1

    n

    denote the Gini coefficient for the endowment distribution.

    I Let

    Gq =2

    ∑ni=1 iv

    qi

    n∑n

    i=1 vqi

    − n + 1n

    denote the Gini coefficient for the equilibrium payoffdistribution in the q-game.

    I Let GU and GM denote the Gini coefficients for theequilibrium payoff distribution under unanimity and majorityrule.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • Notation and some useful definitions

    I Restrict attention to stationary subgame perfect (SSP)equilibria.

    I Let vq = (vq1 , ..., vqn ) denote the payoff vector generated by an

    SSP strategy profile in the q-game.

    I Let

    G =2

    ∑ni=1 iyi

    n∑n

    i=1 yi− n + 1

    n

    denote the Gini coefficient for the endowment distribution.

    I Let

    Gq =2

    ∑ni=1 iv

    qi

    n∑n

    i=1 vqi

    − n + 1n

    denote the Gini coefficient for the equilibrium payoffdistribution in the q-game.

    I Let GU and GM denote the Gini coefficients for theequilibrium payoff distribution under unanimity and majorityrule.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • Notation and some useful definitions

    I Restrict attention to stationary subgame perfect (SSP)equilibria.

    I Let vq = (vq1 , ..., vqn ) denote the payoff vector generated by an

    SSP strategy profile in the q-game.

    I Let

    G =2

    ∑ni=1 iyi

    n∑n

    i=1 yi− n + 1

    n

    denote the Gini coefficient for the endowment distribution.

    I Let

    Gq =2

    ∑ni=1 iv

    qi

    n∑n

    i=1 vqi

    − n + 1n

    denote the Gini coefficient for the equilibrium payoffdistribution in the q-game.

    I Let GU and GM denote the Gini coefficients for theequilibrium payoff distribution under unanimity and majorityrule.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • Notation and some useful definitions

    I Restrict attention to stationary subgame perfect (SSP)equilibria.

    I Let vq = (vq1 , ..., vqn ) denote the payoff vector generated by an

    SSP strategy profile in the q-game.

    I Let

    G =2

    ∑ni=1 iyi

    n∑n

    i=1 yi− n + 1

    n

    denote the Gini coefficient for the endowment distribution.

    I Let

    Gq =2

    ∑ni=1 iv

    qi

    n∑n

    i=1 vqi

    − n + 1n

    denote the Gini coefficient for the equilibrium payoffdistribution in the q-game.

    I Let GU and GM denote the Gini coefficients for theequilibrium payoff distribution under unanimity and majorityrule.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • Notation and some useful definitions

    I Restrict attention to stationary subgame perfect (SSP)equilibria.

    I Let vq = (vq1 , ..., vqn ) denote the payoff vector generated by an

    SSP strategy profile in the q-game.

    I Let

    G =2

    ∑ni=1 iyi

    n∑n

    i=1 yi− n + 1

    n

    denote the Gini coefficient for the endowment distribution.

    I Let

    Gq =2

    ∑ni=1 iv

    qi

    n∑n

    i=1 vqi

    − n + 1n

    denote the Gini coefficient for the equilibrium payoffdistribution in the q-game.

    I Let GU and GM denote the Gini coefficients for theequilibrium payoff distribution under unanimity and majorityrule.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • Notation and some useful definitions

    I Restrict attention to stationary subgame perfect (SSP)equilibria.

    I Let vq = (vq1 , ..., vqn ) denote the payoff vector generated by an

    SSP strategy profile in the q-game.

    I Let

    G =2

    ∑ni=1 iyi

    n∑n

    i=1 yi− n + 1

    n

    denote the Gini coefficient for the endowment distribution.

    I Let

    Gq =2

    ∑ni=1 iv

    qi

    n∑n

    i=1 vqi

    − n + 1n

    denote the Gini coefficient for the equilibrium payoffdistribution in the q-game.

    I Let GU and GM denote the Gini coefficients for theequilibrium payoff distribution under unanimity and majorityrule.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • A leading example

    I Suppose c1 = c2 = ... = cn−1 = � and cn = 0, ory1 = y2 = ... = yn−1 = 1− � and yn = 1.

    I For every � > 0, if δ > (1−�)n(1−�)n+� , in the unique SSPequilibrium of the unanimity game

    vUn =1

    n − δ(n − 1)and vU1 = v

    U2 = ... = v

    Un−1 = 0.

    I Verify that this is (an) equilibrium:I Player n’s payoff is the solution to vUn =

    1n +

    n−1n δv

    Un .

    I If i ≤ n − 1 is the proposer, he cannot obtain approval ofplayer n because 1− � < δvUn = δ 1n−δ(n−1) .

    I So player i ’s payoff is 0.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • A leading example

    I Suppose c1 = c2 = ... = cn−1 = � and cn = 0, ory1 = y2 = ... = yn−1 = 1− � and yn = 1.

    I For every � > 0, if δ > (1−�)n(1−�)n+� , in the unique SSPequilibrium of the unanimity game

    vUn =1

    n − δ(n − 1)and vU1 = v

    U2 = ... = v

    Un−1 = 0.

    I Verify that this is (an) equilibrium:I Player n’s payoff is the solution to vUn =

    1n +

    n−1n δv

    Un .

    I If i ≤ n − 1 is the proposer, he cannot obtain approval ofplayer n because 1− � < δvUn = δ 1n−δ(n−1) .

    I So player i ’s payoff is 0.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • A leading example

    I Suppose c1 = c2 = ... = cn−1 = � and cn = 0, ory1 = y2 = ... = yn−1 = 1− � and yn = 1.

    I For every � > 0, if δ > (1−�)n(1−�)n+� , in the unique SSPequilibrium of the unanimity game

    vUn =1

    n − δ(n − 1)and vU1 = v

    U2 = ... = v

    Un−1 = 0.

    I Verify that this is (an) equilibrium:I Player n’s payoff is the solution to vUn =

    1n +

    n−1n δv

    Un .

    I If i ≤ n − 1 is the proposer, he cannot obtain approval ofplayer n because 1− � < δvUn = δ 1n−δ(n−1) .

    I So player i ’s payoff is 0.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • A leading example

    I Suppose c1 = c2 = ... = cn−1 = � and cn = 0, ory1 = y2 = ... = yn−1 = 1− � and yn = 1.

    I For every � > 0, if δ > (1−�)n(1−�)n+� , in the unique SSPequilibrium of the unanimity game

    vUn =1

    n − δ(n − 1)and vU1 = v

    U2 = ... = v

    Un−1 = 0.

    I Verify that this is (an) equilibrium:

    I Player n’s payoff is the solution to vUn =1n +

    n−1n δv

    Un .

    I If i ≤ n − 1 is the proposer, he cannot obtain approval ofplayer n because 1− � < δvUn = δ 1n−δ(n−1) .

    I So player i ’s payoff is 0.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • A leading example

    I Suppose c1 = c2 = ... = cn−1 = � and cn = 0, ory1 = y2 = ... = yn−1 = 1− � and yn = 1.

    I For every � > 0, if δ > (1−�)n(1−�)n+� , in the unique SSPequilibrium of the unanimity game

    vUn =1

    n − δ(n − 1)and vU1 = v

    U2 = ... = v

    Un−1 = 0.

    I Verify that this is (an) equilibrium:I Player n’s payoff is the solution to vUn =

    1n +

    n−1n δv

    Un .

    I If i ≤ n − 1 is the proposer, he cannot obtain approval ofplayer n because 1− � < δvUn = δ 1n−δ(n−1) .

    I So player i ’s payoff is 0.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • A leading example

    I Suppose c1 = c2 = ... = cn−1 = � and cn = 0, ory1 = y2 = ... = yn−1 = 1− � and yn = 1.

    I For every � > 0, if δ > (1−�)n(1−�)n+� , in the unique SSPequilibrium of the unanimity game

    vUn =1

    n − δ(n − 1)and vU1 = v

    U2 = ... = v

    Un−1 = 0.

    I Verify that this is (an) equilibrium:I Player n’s payoff is the solution to vUn =

    1n +

    n−1n δv

    Un .

    I If i ≤ n − 1 is the proposer, he cannot obtain approval ofplayer n because 1− � < δvUn = δ 1n−δ(n−1) .

    I So player i ’s payoff is 0.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • A leading example

    I Suppose c1 = c2 = ... = cn−1 = � and cn = 0, ory1 = y2 = ... = yn−1 = 1− � and yn = 1.

    I For every � > 0, if δ > (1−�)n(1−�)n+� , in the unique SSPequilibrium of the unanimity game

    vUn =1

    n − δ(n − 1)and vU1 = v

    U2 = ... = v

    Un−1 = 0.

    I Verify that this is (an) equilibrium:I Player n’s payoff is the solution to vUn =

    1n +

    n−1n δv

    Un .

    I If i ≤ n − 1 is the proposer, he cannot obtain approval ofplayer n because 1− � < δvUn = δ 1n−δ(n−1) .

    I So player i ’s payoff is 0.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • A leading example (cont’d)

    I For every � < δ2+δ n−1

    n

    , in the unique SSP equilibrium of the

    majority game

    vM1 = vM2 = ... = v

    Mn =

    1 + (n − 1)(1− �)n2

    = vM .

    I Verify that this is (an) equilibrium:I If i is the proposer, he offers δvM to q − 1 other players and

    keeps yi − δ(q − 1)vM .I Let µi denote the (endogenous) probability that i receives his

    continuation payoff when someone else is the proposer.I So player i ’s payoff must satisfy

    vM = 1n (yi − δ(q − 1)vM) + µiδv

    M .I In equilibrium, we must have µi ≥ 0 and µi ≤ 1− 1n for all i ;

    y1 − (q − 1)δvM ≥ δvM ; and∑n

    i=1 µi = q − 1.I Since � < δ

    2+δ n−1n, we can find µ1, . . . , µn satisfying these.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • A leading example (cont’d)

    I For every � < δ2+δ n−1

    n

    , in the unique SSP equilibrium of the

    majority game

    vM1 = vM2 = ... = v

    Mn =

    1 + (n − 1)(1− �)n2

    = vM .

    I Verify that this is (an) equilibrium:I If i is the proposer, he offers δvM to q − 1 other players and

    keeps yi − δ(q − 1)vM .I Let µi denote the (endogenous) probability that i receives his

    continuation payoff when someone else is the proposer.I So player i ’s payoff must satisfy

    vM = 1n (yi − δ(q − 1)vM) + µiδv

    M .I In equilibrium, we must have µi ≥ 0 and µi ≤ 1− 1n for all i ;

    y1 − (q − 1)δvM ≥ δvM ; and∑n

    i=1 µi = q − 1.I Since � < δ

    2+δ n−1n, we can find µ1, . . . , µn satisfying these.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • A leading example (cont’d)

    I For every � < δ2+δ n−1

    n

    , in the unique SSP equilibrium of the

    majority game

    vM1 = vM2 = ... = v

    Mn =

    1 + (n − 1)(1− �)n2

    = vM .

    I Verify that this is (an) equilibrium:

    I If i is the proposer, he offers δvM to q − 1 other players andkeeps yi − δ(q − 1)vM .

    I Let µi denote the (endogenous) probability that i receives hiscontinuation payoff when someone else is the proposer.

    I So player i ’s payoff must satisfyvM = 1n (yi − δ(q − 1)v

    M) + µiδvM .

    I In equilibrium, we must have µi ≥ 0 and µi ≤ 1− 1n for all i ;y1 − (q − 1)δvM ≥ δvM ; and

    ∑ni=1 µi = q − 1.

    I Since � < δ2+δ n−1n

    , we can find µ1, . . . , µn satisfying these.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • A leading example (cont’d)

    I For every � < δ2+δ n−1

    n

    , in the unique SSP equilibrium of the

    majority game

    vM1 = vM2 = ... = v

    Mn =

    1 + (n − 1)(1− �)n2

    = vM .

    I Verify that this is (an) equilibrium:I If i is the proposer, he offers δvM to q − 1 other players and

    keeps yi − δ(q − 1)vM .

    I Let µi denote the (endogenous) probability that i receives hiscontinuation payoff when someone else is the proposer.

    I So player i ’s payoff must satisfyvM = 1n (yi − δ(q − 1)v

    M) + µiδvM .

    I In equilibrium, we must have µi ≥ 0 and µi ≤ 1− 1n for all i ;y1 − (q − 1)δvM ≥ δvM ; and

    ∑ni=1 µi = q − 1.

    I Since � < δ2+δ n−1n

    , we can find µ1, . . . , µn satisfying these.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • A leading example (cont’d)

    I For every � < δ2+δ n−1

    n

    , in the unique SSP equilibrium of the

    majority game

    vM1 = vM2 = ... = v

    Mn =

    1 + (n − 1)(1− �)n2

    = vM .

    I Verify that this is (an) equilibrium:I If i is the proposer, he offers δvM to q − 1 other players and

    keeps yi − δ(q − 1)vM .I Let µi denote the (endogenous) probability that i receives his

    continuation payoff when someone else is the proposer.

    I So player i ’s payoff must satisfyvM = 1n (yi − δ(q − 1)v

    M) + µiδvM .

    I In equilibrium, we must have µi ≥ 0 and µi ≤ 1− 1n for all i ;y1 − (q − 1)δvM ≥ δvM ; and

    ∑ni=1 µi = q − 1.

    I Since � < δ2+δ n−1n

    , we can find µ1, . . . , µn satisfying these.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • A leading example (cont’d)

    I For every � < δ2+δ n−1

    n

    , in the unique SSP equilibrium of the

    majority game

    vM1 = vM2 = ... = v

    Mn =

    1 + (n − 1)(1− �)n2

    = vM .

    I Verify that this is (an) equilibrium:I If i is the proposer, he offers δvM to q − 1 other players and

    keeps yi − δ(q − 1)vM .I Let µi denote the (endogenous) probability that i receives his

    continuation payoff when someone else is the proposer.I So player i ’s payoff must satisfy

    vM = 1n (yi − δ(q − 1)vM) + µiδv

    M .

    I In equilibrium, we must have µi ≥ 0 and µi ≤ 1− 1n for all i ;y1 − (q − 1)δvM ≥ δvM ; and

    ∑ni=1 µi = q − 1.

    I Since � < δ2+δ n−1n

    , we can find µ1, . . . , µn satisfying these.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • A leading example (cont’d)

    I For every � < δ2+δ n−1

    n

    , in the unique SSP equilibrium of the

    majority game

    vM1 = vM2 = ... = v

    Mn =

    1 + (n − 1)(1− �)n2

    = vM .

    I Verify that this is (an) equilibrium:I If i is the proposer, he offers δvM to q − 1 other players and

    keeps yi − δ(q − 1)vM .I Let µi denote the (endogenous) probability that i receives his

    continuation payoff when someone else is the proposer.I So player i ’s payoff must satisfy

    vM = 1n (yi − δ(q − 1)vM) + µiδv

    M .I In equilibrium, we must have µi ≥ 0 and µi ≤ 1− 1n for all i ;

    y1 − (q − 1)δvM ≥ δvM ; and∑n

    i=1 µi = q − 1.

    I Since � < δ2+δ n−1n

    , we can find µ1, . . . , µn satisfying these.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • A leading example (cont’d)

    I For every � < δ2+δ n−1

    n

    , in the unique SSP equilibrium of the

    majority game

    vM1 = vM2 = ... = v

    Mn =

    1 + (n − 1)(1− �)n2

    = vM .

    I Verify that this is (an) equilibrium:I If i is the proposer, he offers δvM to q − 1 other players and

    keeps yi − δ(q − 1)vM .I Let µi denote the (endogenous) probability that i receives his

    continuation payoff when someone else is the proposer.I So player i ’s payoff must satisfy

    vM = 1n (yi − δ(q − 1)vM) + µiδv

    M .I In equilibrium, we must have µi ≥ 0 and µi ≤ 1− 1n for all i ;

    y1 − (q − 1)δvM ≥ δvM ; and∑n

    i=1 µi = q − 1.I Since � < δ

    2+δ n−1n, we can find µ1, . . . , µn satisfying these.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • A leading example (cont’d)

    I In this environment

    0 = GM < G < GU .

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • A leading example (cont’d)

    I In this environment

    0 = GM < G < GU .

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • Intuition

    Under unanimity rule:

    I Equilibrium is efficient.

    I If players are patient enough, efficiency requires agreementonly when player n proposes.

    I Since all other players can never obtain unanimous approval(player n would never say yes), it is “as if” they neverpropose. Hence, their equilibrium payoff must be zero.

    Under majority rule:

    I All proposals are accepted (it only takes a majority in favor toapprove a project).

    I Player n loses his advantage.

    I This “egalitarian” force generates regression toward the meanthat equalizes expected equilibrium payoffs.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • Intuition

    Under unanimity rule:

    I Equilibrium is efficient.

    I If players are patient enough, efficiency requires agreementonly when player n proposes.

    I Since all other players can never obtain unanimous approval(player n would never say yes), it is “as if” they neverpropose. Hence, their equilibrium payoff must be zero.

    Under majority rule:

    I All proposals are accepted (it only takes a majority in favor toapprove a project).

    I Player n loses his advantage.

    I This “egalitarian” force generates regression toward the meanthat equalizes expected equilibrium payoffs.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • Intuition

    Under unanimity rule:

    I Equilibrium is efficient.

    I If players are patient enough, efficiency requires agreementonly when player n proposes.

    I Since all other players can never obtain unanimous approval(player n would never say yes), it is “as if” they neverpropose. Hence, their equilibrium payoff must be zero.

    Under majority rule:

    I All proposals are accepted (it only takes a majority in favor toapprove a project).

    I Player n loses his advantage.

    I This “egalitarian” force generates regression toward the meanthat equalizes expected equilibrium payoffs.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • Intuition

    Under unanimity rule:

    I Equilibrium is efficient.

    I If players are patient enough, efficiency requires agreementonly when player n proposes.

    I Since all other players can never obtain unanimous approval(player n would never say yes), it is “as if” they neverpropose. Hence, their equilibrium payoff must be zero.

    Under majority rule:

    I All proposals are accepted (it only takes a majority in favor toapprove a project).

    I Player n loses his advantage.

    I This “egalitarian” force generates regression toward the meanthat equalizes expected equilibrium payoffs.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • Intuition

    Under unanimity rule:

    I Equilibrium is efficient.

    I If players are patient enough, efficiency requires agreementonly when player n proposes.

    I Since all other players can never obtain unanimous approval(player n would never say yes), it is “as if” they neverpropose. Hence, their equilibrium payoff must be zero.

    Under majority rule:

    I All proposals are accepted (it only takes a majority in favor toapprove a project).

    I Player n loses his advantage.

    I This “egalitarian” force generates regression toward the meanthat equalizes expected equilibrium payoffs.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • Intuition

    Under unanimity rule:

    I Equilibrium is efficient.

    I If players are patient enough, efficiency requires agreementonly when player n proposes.

    I Since all other players can never obtain unanimous approval(player n would never say yes), it is “as if” they neverpropose. Hence, their equilibrium payoff must be zero.

    Under majority rule:

    I All proposals are accepted (it only takes a majority in favor toapprove a project).

    I Player n loses his advantage.

    I This “egalitarian” force generates regression toward the meanthat equalizes expected equilibrium payoffs.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • Intuition

    Under unanimity rule:

    I Equilibrium is efficient.

    I If players are patient enough, efficiency requires agreementonly when player n proposes.

    I Since all other players can never obtain unanimous approval(player n would never say yes), it is “as if” they neverpropose. Hence, their equilibrium payoff must be zero.

    Under majority rule:

    I All proposals are accepted (it only takes a majority in favor toapprove a project).

    I Player n loses his advantage.

    I This “egalitarian” force generates regression toward the meanthat equalizes expected equilibrium payoffs.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • Intuition

    Under unanimity rule:

    I Equilibrium is efficient.

    I If players are patient enough, efficiency requires agreementonly when player n proposes.

    I Since all other players can never obtain unanimous approval(player n would never say yes), it is “as if” they neverpropose. Hence, their equilibrium payoff must be zero.

    Under majority rule:

    I All proposals are accepted (it only takes a majority in favor toapprove a project).

    I Player n loses his advantage.

    I This “egalitarian” force generates regression toward the meanthat equalizes expected equilibrium payoffs.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • Intuition

    Under unanimity rule:

    I Equilibrium is efficient.

    I If players are patient enough, efficiency requires agreementonly when player n proposes.

    I Since all other players can never obtain unanimous approval(player n would never say yes), it is “as if” they neverpropose. Hence, their equilibrium payoff must be zero.

    Under majority rule:

    I All proposals are accepted (it only takes a majority in favor toapprove a project).

    I Player n loses his advantage.

    I This “egalitarian” force generates regression toward the meanthat equalizes expected equilibrium payoffs.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • General results

    I If there is agreement is reached when the cake size is yi , thenthere is agreement when the cake size is yi+1.

    I Payoffs are monotone: vqi ≤ vqi+1.

    I In the q-game, there is always agreement when player qproposes.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • General results

    I If there is agreement is reached when the cake size is yi , thenthere is agreement when the cake size is yi+1.

    I Payoffs are monotone: vqi ≤ vqi+1.

    I In the q-game, there is always agreement when player qproposes.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • General results

    I If there is agreement is reached when the cake size is yi , thenthere is agreement when the cake size is yi+1.

    I Payoffs are monotone: vqi ≤ vqi+1.

    I In the q-game, there is always agreement when player qproposes.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • General results

    I If there is agreement is reached when the cake size is yi , thenthere is agreement when the cake size is yi+1.

    I Payoffs are monotone: vqi ≤ vqi+1.

    I In the q-game, there is always agreement when player qproposes.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • General results (cont’d)

    I Under unanimity rule, there exists a unique SSP payoff:

    vUi = max{0,1

    n(1− δ)(yi −

    δ

    n − δ(κU − 1)

    n∑j=κU

    yj)}.

    whereκU = min{i : yi − δ

    ∑j

    vUj ≥ 0}.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • General results (cont’d)

    I Under unanimity rule, there exists a unique SSP payoff:

    vUi = max{0,1

    n(1− δ)(yi −

    δ

    n − δ(κU − 1)

    n∑j=κU

    yj)}.

    whereκU = min{i : yi − δ

    ∑j

    vUj ≥ 0}.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • General results (cont’d)

    I Under unanimity rule, there exists a unique SSP payoff:

    vUi = max{0,1

    n(1− δ)(yi −

    δ

    n − δ(κU − 1)

    n∑j=κU

    yj)}.

    whereκU = min{i : yi − δ

    ∑j

    vUj ≥ 0}.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • General results (cont’d)

    I Under majority rule, we have sufficient conditions foruniqueness but the equilibrium need not be unique.

    I 3 players, δ = 0.9, y1 = 0.4, y2 = y3 = 1

    I Equilibrium payoffs:

    vM1 =1

    3max{(0.4− δvMj ), δvM1 }+

    2

    3δvM1

    vMj =1

    3(1− δvM1 ) + µjδvMj , j = 2, 3

    I Player 1 needs the approval of either player 2 or 3 but notboth: µ2 = µ3 =1/6 if 0.4 ≥ δvMj

    I If there is no agreement then players 2 and 3 both receive theircontinuation payoffs with probability 1/3: µ2 = µ3 = 1/3 if0.4 < δvMj

    I One equilibrium: vM1 = 0, vM2 = v

    M3 = 0.476

    I Another equilibrium: vM1 = 0.0533, vM2 = v

    M3 = 0.3733

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • General results (cont’d)

    I Under majority rule, we have sufficient conditions foruniqueness but the equilibrium need not be unique.

    I 3 players, δ = 0.9, y1 = 0.4, y2 = y3 = 1

    I Equilibrium payoffs:

    vM1 =1

    3max{(0.4− δvMj ), δvM1 }+

    2

    3δvM1

    vMj =1

    3(1− δvM1 ) + µjδvMj , j = 2, 3

    I Player 1 needs the approval of either player 2 or 3 but notboth: µ2 = µ3 =1/6 if 0.4 ≥ δvMj

    I If there is no agreement then players 2 and 3 both receive theircontinuation payoffs with probability 1/3: µ2 = µ3 = 1/3 if0.4 < δvMj

    I One equilibrium: vM1 = 0, vM2 = v

    M3 = 0.476

    I Another equilibrium: vM1 = 0.0533, vM2 = v

    M3 = 0.3733

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • General results (cont’d)

    I Under majority rule, we have sufficient conditions foruniqueness but the equilibrium need not be unique.

    I 3 players, δ = 0.9, y1 = 0.4, y2 = y3 = 1

    I Equilibrium payoffs:

    vM1 =1

    3max{(0.4− δvMj ), δvM1 }+

    2

    3δvM1

    vMj =1

    3(1− δvM1 ) + µjδvMj , j = 2, 3

    I Player 1 needs the approval of either player 2 or 3 but notboth: µ2 = µ3 =1/6 if 0.4 ≥ δvMj

    I If there is no agreement then players 2 and 3 both receive theircontinuation payoffs with probability 1/3: µ2 = µ3 = 1/3 if0.4 < δvMj

    I One equilibrium: vM1 = 0, vM2 = v

    M3 = 0.476

    I Another equilibrium: vM1 = 0.0533, vM2 = v

    M3 = 0.3733

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • General results (cont’d)

    I Under majority rule, we have sufficient conditions foruniqueness but the equilibrium need not be unique.

    I 3 players, δ = 0.9, y1 = 0.4, y2 = y3 = 1

    I Equilibrium payoffs:

    vM1 =1

    3max{(0.4− δvMj ), δvM1 }+

    2

    3δvM1

    vMj =1

    3(1− δvM1 ) + µjδvMj , j = 2, 3

    I Player 1 needs the approval of either player 2 or 3 but notboth: µ2 = µ3 =1/6 if 0.4 ≥ δvMj

    I If there is no agreement then players 2 and 3 both receive theircontinuation payoffs with probability 1/3: µ2 = µ3 = 1/3 if0.4 < δvMj

    I One equilibrium: vM1 = 0, vM2 = v

    M3 = 0.476

    I Another equilibrium: vM1 = 0.0533, vM2 = v

    M3 = 0.3733

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • General results (cont’d)

    I Under majority rule, we have sufficient conditions foruniqueness but the equilibrium need not be unique.

    I 3 players, δ = 0.9, y1 = 0.4, y2 = y3 = 1

    I Equilibrium payoffs:

    vM1 =1

    3max{(0.4− δvMj ), δvM1 }+

    2

    3δvM1

    vMj =1

    3(1− δvM1 ) + µjδvMj , j = 2, 3

    I Player 1 needs the approval of either player 2 or 3 but notboth: µ2 = µ3 =1/6 if 0.4 ≥ δvMj

    I If there is no agreement then players 2 and 3 both receive theircontinuation payoffs with probability 1/3: µ2 = µ3 = 1/3 if0.4 < δvMj

    I One equilibrium: vM1 = 0, vM2 = v

    M3 = 0.476

    I Another equilibrium: vM1 = 0.0533, vM2 = v

    M3 = 0.3733

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • General results (cont’d)

    I Under majority rule, we have sufficient conditions foruniqueness but the equilibrium need not be unique.

    I 3 players, δ = 0.9, y1 = 0.4, y2 = y3 = 1

    I Equilibrium payoffs:

    vM1 =1

    3max{(0.4− δvMj ), δvM1 }+

    2

    3δvM1

    vMj =1

    3(1− δvM1 ) + µjδvMj , j = 2, 3

    I Player 1 needs the approval of either player 2 or 3 but notboth: µ2 = µ3 =1/6 if 0.4 ≥ δvMj

    I If there is no agreement then players 2 and 3 both receive theircontinuation payoffs with probability 1/3: µ2 = µ3 = 1/3 if0.4 < δvMj

    I One equilibrium: vM1 = 0, vM2 = v

    M3 = 0.476

    I Another equilibrium: vM1 = 0.0533, vM2 = v

    M3 = 0.3733

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • General results (cont’d)

    I Under majority rule, we have sufficient conditions foruniqueness but the equilibrium need not be unique.

    I 3 players, δ = 0.9, y1 = 0.4, y2 = y3 = 1

    I Equilibrium payoffs:

    vM1 =1

    3max{(0.4− δvMj ), δvM1 }+

    2

    3δvM1

    vMj =1

    3(1− δvM1 ) + µjδvMj , j = 2, 3

    I Player 1 needs the approval of either player 2 or 3 but notboth: µ2 = µ3 =1/6 if 0.4 ≥ δvMj

    I If there is no agreement then players 2 and 3 both receive theircontinuation payoffs with probability 1/3: µ2 = µ3 = 1/3 if0.4 < δvMj

    I One equilibrium: vM1 = 0, vM2 = v

    M3 = 0.476

    I Another equilibrium: vM1 = 0.0533, vM2 = v

    M3 = 0.3733

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • General results (cont’d)

    I Under majority rule, we have sufficient conditions foruniqueness but the equilibrium need not be unique.

    I 3 players, δ = 0.9, y1 = 0.4, y2 = y3 = 1

    I Equilibrium payoffs:

    vM1 =1

    3max{(0.4− δvMj ), δvM1 }+

    2

    3δvM1

    vMj =1

    3(1− δvM1 ) + µjδvMj , j = 2, 3

    I Player 1 needs the approval of either player 2 or 3 but notboth: µ2 = µ3 =1/6 if 0.4 ≥ δvMj

    I If there is no agreement then players 2 and 3 both receive theircontinuation payoffs with probability 1/3: µ2 = µ3 = 1/3 if0.4 < δvMj

    I One equilibrium: vM1 = 0, vM2 = v

    M3 = 0.476

    I Another equilibrium: vM1 = 0.0533, vM2 = v

    M3 = 0.3733

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • General results (cont’d)

    I Unanimity outcome is at most as equal as the fundamentals:GU ≥ G .

    I Under some conditions, unanimity outcome is strictly moreunequal than the fundamentals: If δ > y1ȳ where ȳ is the

    average surplus, then GU > G .

    I If (yn − y1) is “small” then there exists an equilibrium undermajority rule such that 0 = GM .

    I Under some conditions, GM ≤ G ≤ GU .

    I Gq is not monotonic in q (G 1 = G ).

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • General results (cont’d)

    I Unanimity outcome is at most as equal as the fundamentals:GU ≥ G .

    I Under some conditions, unanimity outcome is strictly moreunequal than the fundamentals: If δ > y1ȳ where ȳ is the

    average surplus, then GU > G .

    I If (yn − y1) is “small” then there exists an equilibrium undermajority rule such that 0 = GM .

    I Under some conditions, GM ≤ G ≤ GU .

    I Gq is not monotonic in q (G 1 = G ).

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • General results (cont’d)

    I Unanimity outcome is at most as equal as the fundamentals:GU ≥ G .

    I Under some conditions, unanimity outcome is strictly moreunequal than the fundamentals: If δ > y1ȳ where ȳ is the

    average surplus, then GU > G .

    I If (yn − y1) is “small” then there exists an equilibrium undermajority rule such that 0 = GM .

    I Under some conditions, GM ≤ G ≤ GU .

    I Gq is not monotonic in q (G 1 = G ).

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • General results (cont’d)

    I Unanimity outcome is at most as equal as the fundamentals:GU ≥ G .

    I Under some conditions, unanimity outcome is strictly moreunequal than the fundamentals: If δ > y1ȳ where ȳ is the

    average surplus, then GU > G .

    I If (yn − y1) is “small” then there exists an equilibrium undermajority rule such that 0 = GM .

    I Under some conditions, GM ≤ G ≤ GU .

    I Gq is not monotonic in q (G 1 = G ).

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • General results (cont’d)

    I Unanimity outcome is at most as equal as the fundamentals:GU ≥ G .

    I Under some conditions, unanimity outcome is strictly moreunequal than the fundamentals: If δ > y1ȳ where ȳ is the

    average surplus, then GU > G .

    I If (yn − y1) is “small” then there exists an equilibrium undermajority rule such that 0 = GM .

    I Under some conditions, GM ≤ G ≤ GU .

    I Gq is not monotonic in q (G 1 = G ).

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • General results (cont’d)

    I Unanimity outcome is at most as equal as the fundamentals:GU ≥ G .

    I Under some conditions, unanimity outcome is strictly moreunequal than the fundamentals: If δ > y1ȳ where ȳ is the

    average surplus, then GU > G .

    I If (yn − y1) is “small” then there exists an equilibrium undermajority rule such that 0 = GM .

    I Under some conditions, GM ≤ G ≤ GU .

    I Gq is not monotonic in q (G 1 = G ).

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • Conjecture

    I There exists a q̄ < n such that for any q < q̄ and q′ > q̄, andfor any equilibria of q-game and q′-game, we haveGq ≤ G ≤ Gq′ .

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • Conjecture

    I There exists a q̄ < n such that for any q < q̄ and q′ > q̄, andfor any equilibria of q-game and q′-game, we haveGq ≤ G ≤ Gq′ .

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • Concluding remarks

    I In the original Baron and Ferejohn (1989) environment,GM = G = GU . However, ex post, majority leads to moreinequality.

    I In our environment, GM ≤ G ≤ GU . Ex post it depends.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • Concluding remarks

    I In the original Baron and Ferejohn (1989) environment,GM = G = GU . However, ex post, majority leads to moreinequality.

    I In our environment, GM ≤ G ≤ GU . Ex post it depends.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?

  • Concluding remarks

    I In the original Baron and Ferejohn (1989) environment,GM = G = GU . However, ex post, majority leads to moreinequality.

    I In our environment, GM ≤ G ≤ GU . Ex post it depends.

    Hülya Eraslan and Antonio Merlo Some Unpleasant Bargaining Arithmetics?