Top Banner
Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Polical Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics David Rönnegard and N. Craig Smith INSEAD Abstract: The “basic debate” in business ethics between shareholder theory and stakeholder theory has underlined the field since its inception, with wide ranging nor- mative, descriptive, and instrumental arguments offered on both sides. We maintain that insofar as this is primarily a normative debate, clarity can be brought by elucidat- ing how it is framed by the political philosophies of liberalism and libertarianism. With liberalism represented by John Rawls’s theory of justice and libertarianism represented by the ideas of Milton Friedman and Robert Nozick, and (separately) Edward Freeman, the paper shows that both liberalism and libertarianism can be inter- preted to justify shareholder and stakeholder theory respectively. The debate between shareholder theory and stakeholder theory is framed by liberal and libertarian justifi- cations that hinge primarily on whether and to what extent one should have exogenous or endogenous safeguards on corporate behavior. Accordingly, political philosophy turns out to be highly relevant to both business ethics and corporate governance, not because the corporation resembles the state, but because of the potential safeguards placed on the corporation by the state. Key Words: stakeholder theory, shareholder theory, corporate social responsibility, CSR, business ethics, political philosophy, liberalism, libertarianism, John Rawls, Robert Nozick, Milton Friedman, Edward Freeman The “basic debate” in business ethics is often characterized as one between whether managers should focus primarily on the interests of shareholders and whether they © Business & Professional Ethics Journal. ISSN 0277-2027. Correspondence may be sent to David Rönnegard, [email protected]; and to N. Craig Smith, [email protected]. Business & Professional Ethics Journal, 32:3–4, 2013 pp. 183–220 doi: 10.5840/bpej201311185
38

Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

Jan 17, 2023

Download

Documents

Welcome message from author
This document is posted to help you gain knowledge. Please leave a comment to let me know what you think about it! Share it to your friends and learn new things together.
Transcript
Page 1: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

David Rönnegard and N. Craig SmithINSEAD

Abstract: The “basic debate” in business ethics between shareholder theory and stakeholder theory has underlined the field since its inception, with wide ranging nor-mative, descriptive, and instrumental arguments offered on both sides. We maintain that insofar as this is primarily a normative debate, clarity can be brought by elucidat-ing how it is framed by the political philosophies of liberalism and libertarianism.

With liberalism represented by John Rawls’s theory of justice and libertarianism represented by the ideas of Milton Friedman and Robert Nozick, and (separately) Edward Freeman, the paper shows that both liberalism and libertarianism can be inter-preted to justify shareholder and stakeholder theory respectively. The debate between shareholder theory and stakeholder theory is framed by liberal and libertarian justifi-cations that hinge primarily on whether and to what extent one should have exogenous or endogenous safeguards on corporate behavior. Accordingly, political philosophy turns out to be highly relevant to both business ethics and corporate governance, not because the corporation resembles the state, but because of the potential safeguards placed on the corporation by the state.

Key Words: stakeholder theory, shareholder theory, corporate social responsibility, CSR, business ethics, political philosophy, liberalism, libertarianism, John Rawls, Robert Nozick, Milton Friedman, Edward Freeman

The “basic debate” in business ethics is often characterized as one between whether managers should focus primarily on the interests of shareholders and whether they

© Business & Professional Ethics Journal. ISSN 0277-2027.Correspondence may be sent to David Rönnegard, [email protected]; and to N. Craig Smith, [email protected].

Business & Professional Ethics Journal, 32:3–4, 2013 pp. 183–220

doi: 10.5840/bpej201311185

Page 2: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

184 Business and Professional Ethics Journal

should consider or balance the interests of a wider group of stakeholders (Agle and Mitchell 2008; Boatright 2002; Campbell 2007; Freeman 1994; Phillips 1997). This has also become known as the “Friedman-Freeman debate,” though it should be noted that Freeman himself rejects this characterization (Freeman 2008).1 Nonetheless, business ethics as an academic field has reacted disapprovingly to the managerial focus on shareholder interests of the so-called shareholder theory of Milton Friedman, who asserted that the social responsibility of business is “to use its resources and engage in activities designed to increase its profits so long as it stays within the rules of the game” (1962, 133). In contrast, Freeman’s (1984) seminal formulation of stakeholder theory, while not denying that profitability should be a goal of corporations, sees the primary purpose of the corporation as being a vehicle to manage stakeholder interests. This has become one of the most prominent theories both within business ethics (Phillips 2003) and the wider field of management, as well as a dominant paradigm for Corporate Social Responsibil-ity (McWilliams and Siegel 2001).

The shareholders vs. stakeholders debate has underlined the field of business ethics since its inception with wide ranging normative, descriptive, and instrumen-tal arguments offered on both sides. We shall argue that insofar as this is primarily a normative debate, clarity can be brought by elucidating how it is framed by the political philosophies of liberalism and libertarianism. By clarifying the political normative arguments that are at stake, we lay out the ground upon which this de-bate needs to be conducted. The aim is not to argue in favor of one position over the other, but rather to lay bare the underlying political justifications of each camp. The prescription that managers should focus primarily on shareholder interests has been closely tied to the Shareholder Primacy Norm (SPN). The SPN is the part of a manager’s legal fiduciary duty that requires managers to make decisions on behalf of the corporation that furthers the interests of shareholders. It has been treated as a major obstacle to corporate social responsibility (CSR) because it is said to hinder managers from considering the interests of other corporate stakehold-ers besides shareholders (Boatright 1994; Campbell 2007; Dodd 1932; Evan and Freeman 2003; Hinkley 2002; Phillips, Freeman and Wicks 2003; Testy 2002).

CSR has been defined in many ways. In general, however, “it means that the private corporation has responsibilities to society that go beyond the production of goods and services at a profit . . . a corporation has a broader constituency to serve than stockholders alone” (Buchholz and Rosenthal 2002, 303). In other words, CSR contains a prescription for corporations to pursue ends that go beyond merely pursuing the interests of shareholders. Thus the definitions of the SPN and CSR

Page 3: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy and Business Ethics 185

suggest that they are in conflict as prescriptive concepts. As a consequence, the legitimacy of the SPN is at the core of the basic debate in business ethics (Agle and Mitchell 2008; Boatright 2002; Campbell 2007; Freeman 1994; Phillips 1997). By “legitimacy” in this context we mean that the norm based actions of corporations “are desirable, proper, or appropriate within some socially constructed system of norms, values, beliefs, and definitions” (Suchman 1995, 574).

The SPN is closely associated with the notion of Shareholder Value Maximi-zation (SVM), because if one merges the SPN with an assumption that the interests of shareholders is to maximize their return on investment, then this results in a prescription to managers to maximize shareholder value. Thus the legitimacy of the SPN also has an important bearing on the goal of the corporation and whether it should be a vehicle for the pursuit of shareholder interests (Friedman 1970; Jen-sen 2002) or for managing stakeholder interests (Freeman, Harrison, and Wicks 2007; Freeman et al. 2010). If the interests of shareholders are primary, then their interests will decide what goal the corporation should pursue, whether it is SVM or something else.

We start by maintaining that the SPN is perpetuated as a norm among man-agers due to the importance of shareholders’ sole voting rights for the board of directors. This places shareholders in a privileged position for managerial consid-eration among stakeholders. We then consider the prescriptive issue of whether or not such voting rights should be extended to a wider group of stakeholders along the lines of stakeholder theory. In order to represent stakeholder theory, we introduce the Stakeholder Equality Norm (SEN) as a norm of governance which is characterized by extending equal voting rights for the board to a broader group of stakeholders (thus removing the primacy of shareholders as found under the SPN). Acknowledging that all business is conducted within a political context for ad-dressing social harms and goods we apply political philosophy to demonstrate that the choice between the SPN and the SEN is primarily based on the justifications of liberalism vs. libertarianism. Our aim is to show that each of these positions within political philosophy can serve as the justification for shareholder primacy and stakeholder theory respectively.

We apply Rawls’s theory of justice and demonstrate how his liberal theory would arbitrate between the SPN and the SEN based on empirical issues of eco-nomic efficiency. However, we maintain that neither norm would be unfettered in a putative Rawlsian society because justice considerations impose extensive exog-enous safeguards on the corporation, primarily in the form of legislation. On the other hand, the libertarian foundations of stakeholder theory based on individual

Page 4: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

186 Business and Professional Ethics Journal

rights is contingent on whether the focus is on the equal rights of self-determina-tion of stakeholders rather than the property rights of shareholders. We conclude that a focus on shareholder’s property rights along the lines of Friedman/Nozick (Friedman 1970; Nozick 1974) leads to an endorsement of the SPN with weak exogenous safeguards, while a focus on the equal rights of self-determination of stakeholders along the lines of Freeman (Evan and Freeman 2003; Freeman and Evan 1990; Freeman and Phillips 2002) would lead to an endorsement of the SEN as an endogenous safeguard.

The basic debate about shareholder theory vs. stakeholder theory becomes largely a debate about how one interprets liberalism and libertarianism, where liberalism tends towards strong exogenous safeguards and libertarianism tends towards weak exogenous safeguards or endogenous safeguards. Accordingly, political philosophy turns out to be highly relevant to both business ethics and cor-porate governance, not because the corporation resembles the state, but because of the potential constraints placed on the corporation by the state. By regarding the debate as one founded on political philosophy this offers needed insight and a practical resolution to the conflict through an acceptance of the outcome of the democratic political process.

The Shareholder Primacy Norm

Corporate law in the US and UK, comprising both common law and statutory law, is structured to ensure that corporations work in the interest of shareholders. How-ever, this primacy of shareholders has not been formally identified in statutory law (Fisch 2006). The SPN’s most famous articulation comes from the US case of Dodge v. Ford Motor Co. in 1919, wherein Chief Justice Ostrander said:

A business corporation is organized and carried on primarily for the profit of the stockholders. The powers of the directors are to be employed for that end. The discretion of directors is to be exercised in the choice of means to attain that end, and does not extend to a change in the end itself, to the reduction of profits, or to the non-distribution of profits among shareholders in order to devote them to other purposes.2

The SPN is the part of managers’ legal fiduciary duty which obliges them to consider primarily the interests of shareholders in their decision-making. Tech-nically, shareholders can launch derivative suits against directors on claims of breaching the SPN, but these rarely if ever succeed. Therefore, the view of CSR

Page 5: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy and Business Ethics 187

advocates (see e.g., Boatright 1994; Campbell 2007) that the SPN legally inhibits managers from considering the interests of multiple stakeholders lacks credence.

The reason for this is that the SPN has become muted within the law. The first step in this direction was the US mid-twentieth-century development of the business judgment rule, which hinders the courts from making evaluations about the quality of business decisions. The courts may evaluate a director’s duty of loyalty or care towards shareholder interests, but this in practice becomes very dif-ficult to prove as any decision can be justified as an unsuccessful business decision which the court must not evaluate (Smith 1998). More recently, on both sides of the Atlantic, there have been statutory developments that explicitly allow direc-tors to consider non-shareholder interests. In the US, most states have adopted “non-shareholder constituency statutes” that explicitly allow managers to consider the interests of non-shareholder constituencies when making decisions (McDon-nell 2004). In the UK, the 1985 and 2006 Companies Acts require directors to take into account the interests of employees and other stakeholders, although non-shareholder stakeholders have no judicial means to challenge directors’ decisions. Thus potential common law restrictions on managerial discretion for considering non-shareholder interests have largely disappeared.3

Although the SPN is muted as a legally enforceable norm it is still very much alive among directors and managers as a social norm.4 A significant reason for this is that corporate law is structured towards shareholder primacy.5 Shares confer voting rights to shareholders, which gives them the power to elect and dismiss the board of directors, and therefore there is a real sense in which the directors of the corporation act as agents representing the interests of the shareholders (Kraakman et al. 2004). Quite simply, if directors do not please shareholders they may be dismissed. It should be acknowledged that although dismissal/non-reelection of a board member is a real threat, it rarely happens in practice in large public corpora-tions (Benz and Frey 2007). However, there are usually other incentive structures in place that aim to align management interests with corporate financial perfor-mance; for example, the issuing of shares, stock options, and/or bonuses. Voting rights matter even in this context because it is common practice for shareholders to approve top management’s remuneration by voting. The legal power of sharehold-ers to vote for the board of directors and their remuneration helps perpetuate the SPN as a social norm, not as a principle of law likely to be upheld in court.

We now turn to whether such voting rights should be extended to a wider group of stakeholders along the lines of stakeholder theory. We do not take sides,

Page 6: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

188 Business and Professional Ethics Journal

but lay bare the basis for liberal and libertarian lines of argumentation regarding the legitimacy of extending such rights.

Liberalism and the Legitimacy of the SPN

Any evaluation of legitimacy requires a “constructed system of norms” (Suchman 1995, 574) within which that evaluation takes place. Liberal and libertarian posi-tions within political philosophy represent two such constructed systems of norms. Broadly speaking, liberalism is the view that political and social institutions are justified on the basis that they help further the interests of individuals by upholding both negative and positive individual rights. Since the interests of individuals may often conflict “a framework of rules may be necessary so that individuals know what they can count on for their own purposes and what they must concede to the purposes of others” (Waldron 2000, 486). On the other hand libertarianism pro-motes a conception of liberty that is “identified with the absence of interferences by the state or by others. The legitimate state exists purely to guard individual rights, protecting people and their property. . . . [Activities to further the common good are] illegitimate interferences with an individual’s right to do as they wish with their own person or property” (Wolff 2000, 488).

Letting Rawls’s political theory (Rawls 1996; 1999; 2001) represent the lib-eral system of norms seems obvious given that he is the most influential political philosopher of the twentieth century. We also employ Rawls because his theory aims to develop the fundamental principles that are to govern the basic institutions of society and the corporate legal form may be regarded as such a basic institution. Furthermore, Rawls theory is a social contract theory (SCT) and such theorizing is becoming established as a core theory within business ethics (Wempe 2005). In contrast to previous applications of Rawls’s theory within business ethics (Freeman and Evan 1990; Hartman 1994; Moriarty 2005) that have been said to misapply his political theory directly to the governance of corporate organizations (Phillips and Margolis, 1999), we look at the governance implications of Rawls’s theory for the corporation as an institution that is part of the basic structure of society.

Justice as Fairness

Rawls’s (2001) “Justice as Fairness” theory is a form of political liberalism that as-sumes as fundamental the fact of reasonable pluralism, which is to say that citizens in any society will have profound and irreconcilable differences in their reasonable comprehensive religious and philosophical conceptions of the world. It is thus the task of political liberalism, and Justice as Fairness especially, to put forward

Page 7: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy and Business Ethics 189

a view of political justice that the spectrum of reasonable comprehensive concep-tions can endorse. For this to be realized, Rawls suggests that we should reason as if we are putting together a social contract.

According to Rawls, the “basic structure” of society is the primary subject that should concern the contracting parties, which is to say how the main political and social institutions in society fit together into one system of social cooperation. Importantly, for our purposes, this includes not only the political constitution with an independent judiciary, but also the legally recognized forms of property and the structure of the economy. The most fundamental idea in Justice as Fairness is that society is regarded as a system of social cooperation and therefore it is the goal of the contracting parties to specify the principles of justice that are to govern the basic structure so that they fairly “assign basic rights and duties and regulate the division of advantages that arise from social cooperation over time” (Rawls 2001, 10).6

To explicate the reasoning for his principles, Rawls introduces a represen-tation device called the original position. This is a hypothetical state of nature scenario (an approach also employed by philosophers such as Hobbes, Locke and Rousseau) where we are asked to envision a state of affairs before individu-als started cooperating. Under Rawls, we imagine that the representatives of the relevant social positions in society come together to contractually agree on the principles of justice. In order to reach an agreement that would be acceptable to the spectrum of comprehensive views, the parties are placed behind a “veil of ignorance” in order to model impartiality. The veil of ignorance keeps the par-ties from knowing things that would make them partial in a contracting situation such as their social status, gender, race, natural assets and their conception of the good. Instead of their own comprehensive conception of the good, the parties are assumed to want as much as possible of social primary goods, which are liberties, opportunities, wealth, income and a social basis for self-respect. These are all-purpose means that, Rawls asserts, anyone would want irrespective of their goals in life. Rawls (2001, 42) argues that the contracting parties would reach agreement on the following two principles of justice:

1. Each person has the same indefeasible claim to a fully adequate scheme of liberties, which is compatible with the same scheme of liberties for all (liberty principle); and

2. Social and economic inequities are to satisfy two conditions: first, they are to be attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions

Page 8: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

190 Business and Professional Ethics Journal

of fair equality of opportunity (equality of opportunity principle); and second, they are to be to the greatest benefit of the least-advantaged members of society (the difference principle).

The first principle is prior to the second, and in the second principle “equality of opportunity” is prior to the “difference principle.” These priorities signify that each principle is fully realized by the basic structure of society before the next is applied. In short, Justice as Fairness is an egalitarian conception of rights, liberties and distributive shares, where inequalities of income and wealth are only justifi-able if they are to the benefit of the least advantaged members of society.

How Justice as Fairness Relates to the SPN

To evaluate the legitimacy of the SPN using Justice as Fairness, we must first dem-onstrate its appropriateness to the task. This includes establishing that a “Rawlsian society” would have private ownership as part of the means of production and the corporate legal form, as well as identifying the main criterion for choosing among alternative norms of corporate governance under Rawls’s theory.

Rawls insists on competitive markets in part because they “allow for more efficient allocation of factors of production” (S. Freeman 2008, 222), but more im-portantly because “markets provide an essential means for ensuring equal liberty and fair equality of opportunity” (Krouse and McPherson 1988, 81). However, a market economy is compatible with both private and public ownership of the means of production. Rawls’s (2001, 177) theory is strictly speaking indetermi-nate as regards the public or private ownership of the means of production, but “in existing conditions it [private ownership of the means of production] is the most effective way to meet the principles of justice.” Hence, for the purposes of this paper, we assume a Rawlsian society in which the means of production may be privately owned.

Given that Justice as Fairness allows and “in existing conditions” even en-dorses private ownership in the means of production, some form of legal vehicle is needed through which citizens own (and organize) productive means as distinct from their private property. In our current societies there are several legal forms that enable the economic enterprise of citizens, such as sole proprietorship or part-nerships, but by far the most dominant are corporations. “They [corporations] are the grand social institutions of our time” (Phillips and Margolis 1999, 619). The success of the corporation as a vehicle for production and economic growth has been evident since the industrial revolution. In particular the legal attributes of

Page 9: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy and Business Ethics 191

limited liability and the transferability of shares have been instrumental to facili-tate the pooling of capital necessary for large scale investments and enabling liquid stock markets (Easterbrook and Fischel 1985). Rawls’s theory does not specify the exact attributes of the corporate legal form, but given the proven benefits of this form of productive association there seems little reason to think that a vehicle of this type should not be made available to citizens to engage in commercial en-terprise. Therefore, we assume that a vehicle like the corporate legal form would exist in a Rawlsian society (i.e., with at least the central characteristics as we know it: corporate personality, delegated management, transferability of shares, limited liability, and investor ownership (Kraakman et al. 2004)).

Thus, while Rawls (2001, 12) observes that “the basic structure does not provide a sharp definition, or criterion, from which we can tell what social ar-rangements, or aspects thereof, belong to it,” it does include the legally recognized forms of property. Given that the corporate legal form is a legal vehicle through which citizens can own means of production this should make it a manifestation of the basic structure and, therefore, it needs to comply with the principles of justice. Hence Justice as Fairness is relevant to an evaluation of the legitimacy of the SPN because, as we have shown, this norm is contingent on the voting rights that are conferred upon shareholders as a part of the corporate legal form, which is part of the basic structure.7 With the appropriateness of using Rawls’s theory established, we now turn to identifying the main criterion for choosing among alternative norms of corporate governance.

Justice and the Criterion of Economic Efficiency

A common approach when employing Rawls in business ethics is to take the rep-resentation device of the original position and apply it to corporate stakeholders. For example, one method is to place all stakeholders behind a veil of ignorance, depriving them of the knowledge of what stakes they have, to determine the rules of “fair contracting” among them (Freeman and Evan 1990). However, this is more accurately seen as using the original position as a device for one’s own purposes rather than as an exercise in applying Rawls’s theory. Under Rawls, the relevant contracting parties are citizens, not corporate stakeholders. Rawls’s theory applies to the basic structure seen as a coherent system of social cooperation and therefore the relevant contracting parties are defined in terms of free and equal citizens dis-tinguished by their “different expectations for the unequally distributed primary goods” (1999, 82).

Page 10: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

192 Business and Professional Ethics Journal

While Rawls’s theory does not speak directly to stakeholders, it is relevant to the norm for corporate governance because the norm has consequences for citizens (and thus indirectly for stakeholders) as it affects the efficiency of the en-tire economic system in society. This is accounted for in the difference principle. Rawls (2001, 63) says that “a scheme of cooperation is given in large part by how its public rules organize productive activity” and that, other things being equal, the difference principle directs society to aim for a system that is to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged members in society (defined in terms of the primary goods of income and wealth).

The lexical priority of the principles of justice guarantees that the liberty principle and the equality of opportunity principle are fully realized before the difference principle is applied.8 However, as Rawls (2001, 123) states, “a political conception of justice must take into account the requirements of social orga-nizations and economic efficiency.” The difference principle is part of a broad conception asserting that a theory of justice must incorporate issues of efficiency. For Rawls (1999, 69) “justice is defined so that it is consistent with efficiency, at least when the two principles of justice are fulfilled.” When the basic liberties and equal opportunities are satisfied, a more “efficient system” of cooperation that is to the benefit of the least advantaged is preferable to a less efficient one.

The difference principle is a type of efficiency principle. It is similar to the principle of Pareto-optimality in that it seeks distributive shares (of income and wealth) in society that are such that no representative man can improve his position without making some other representative man worse off. However, Pareto-opti-mality is indifferent to how unequally the shares are distributed and thus it “cannot serve alone as a conception of justice” (Rawls 1999, 62). The difference principle adds to Pareto-optimality “by singling out a particular position [of distributive shares] from which the social and economic inequalities of the basic structure are to be judged. .  .  . The difference principle is a strong egalitarian conception in the sense that unless there is a distribution that makes both persons better off (limiting ourselves to the two-person case for simplicity), an equal distribution is preferred” (Rawls 1999, 65–66).9 Departures from an equal distribution, i.e., “differences,” are permissible if they are to the benefit of the least advantaged members of society. Such differences between representative people are seen as capable of benefitting the least advantaged because the better prospects of the ad-vantaged “act as incentives so that the economic process is more efficient” (Rawls 1999, 68). In Justice as Fairness, issues of justice are prior to efficiency, but other things remaining equal, a more efficient system is preferable to a less efficient one.

Page 11: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy and Business Ethics 193

Rawls says that “the difference principle is, strictly speaking, a maximizing principle” (1999, 68). A simple way to understand it is to think of it as a principle of constrained maximization; i.e., a principle that strives for the most efficient economic system constrained by the liberty principle and the equal opportunity principle, as well as the constraint that departures from equal distribution should be to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged. The first two constraints are set forth by basic institutions through rules and resources to guarantee liberties and opportunities while the last constraint can be implemented through redistribution of income and wealth. These constraints act on the level of society and as such are external to the corporation. These constraints do not directly decide which internal norm of governance should govern corporations. But with these constraints in place, the corporation should have the most economically efficient norm of gov-ernance in order that the greater wealth will benefit everyone, especially the least advantaged.

The efficiency of a macroeconomic system is in part given by the efficiency of the microeconomic systems of corporations within it. An economic system is more efficient if it can provide more goods and services without using proportion-ately more resources. Thus, central to our Rawlsian analysis of the legitimacy of the SPN is whether it is more efficient to give all corporate stakeholders a right to vote or to only give this right to shareholders.

The Stakeholder Equality Norm

We have argued that a Rawlsian society would likely have a legal vehicle for pri-vate ownership of the means of production with the central legal attributes of the corporate legal form as we know it, such as limited liability and the transferability of shares. Yet when it comes to the goal for which the means of production are put to use, what type of norm should govern such a vehicle? Would the SPN or some alternative norm be endorsed by Justice as Fairness? With economic efficiency identified as the main criterion for choosing a norm of corporate governance, we now need at least one alternative to the SPN that can be used to evaluate if it is more efficient.

With the SPN allied to shareholder theory, we turn to stakeholder theory to identify a competing norm of governance. As earlier noted, these contrasting theories cut to the heart of the basic debate in business ethics regarding whether managers should focus on satisfying shareholder or stakeholder interests. Hence the most appropriate alternative against which we might evaluate the SPN would appear to be a norm of governance that reflects the content of stakeholder theory.

Page 12: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

194 Business and Professional Ethics Journal

Shareholder theory holds that the purpose of the corporation is to be a ve-hicle for pursuing shareholder interests (Friedman 1970). In contrast, stakeholder theory holds, as a normative theory and not merely an instrumental theory—and Donaldson and Preston (1995, 86) assert that it is “fundamentally normative”—that the purpose of the corporation is to be a vehicle for managing stakeholder interests (Evan and Freeman 2003). Donaldson and Preston (1995) categorize stakeholder theory into normative, descriptive, and instrumental accounts. Free-man et al. (2010, 213) do not deny that these categories can be useful, but suggest that they are by no means mutually exclusive: “for Freeman, it may require other elements of stakeholder theory (e.g., instrumental, descriptive, managerial) to de-rive a sound normative core.” They regard the “separation thesis” to be a fallacy. (The separation thesis, simply put, is the view that one can separate positive and normative accounts in business.) Instead they adhere to the “integration thesis” which says that positive and normative accounts need to be integrated. In this paper, we regard the purpose of stakeholder theory as fundamentally normative, not because we disregard its descriptive and instrumental aspects, but because our interest is to explore its potential normative foundations from the perspective of political philosophy.

Under the stakeholder view, it is often said that the discretion of decision-making should lie with management together with stakeholder representatives (Melé 2008). However, unless these representatives are given real power, such as an equal right to vote, ultimately we still have a situation of shareholder primacy (even if it is informed by the different interests of the firm’s constituencies). Ac-cordingly, a viable formulation of a norm of governance for stakeholder theory would seem to lie in the idea of a Stakeholder Equality Norm (SEN). The SEN, as we propose it, would be a norm enforced by the fact that all stakeholders have representatives as members of the board with an equal right to vote (equal other-wise one stakeholder group will have primacy). Indeed, Freeman and Evan (1990, 353) argue in their application of the original position to the contracting of stake-holders that “it is rational for stakeholders to choose voting membership on the board” to avoid unilateral policies that are detrimental to stakeholders. Moreover, Donaldson and Preston (1995, 87) note that stakeholder theory “prohibits any un-due attention to the interests of any single constituency.” Therefore the notion of equality seems appropriate for a norm representing stakeholder theory because if stakeholders are not equal in the eyes of management, one group must be primary.

The SEN would presumably include a right for stakeholders to vote for their representatives on the board (in order to achieve proper representation) which

Page 13: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy and Business Ethics 195

would lead to the removal of shareholder primacy (as it is the unique right to vote for the board that establishes shareholders’s current primacy). This would have the effect of extending the fiduciary duties of directors and managers to all stakehold-ers, thus charging them with the task of managing and balancing the pursuit of stakeholder interests.

Implementing stakeholder theory has received insufficient attention in the literature to date. Our formulation is not intended to be a “straw-person”—a mis-representation of stakeholder theory that is easily shot down and an approach often used by its critics (Phillips et al. 2003). Numerous authors over the years (Evan and Freeman 2003; Bonnafous-Bocher 2005; Chilosi and Damiani 2007; Galai and Wiener 2008) have suggested consideration be given to non-shareholder stake-holders in corporate governance, particularly by the board of directors. Common to all these conceptions of stakeholder consideration is that none of them articulate how non-shareholder stakeholders (beyond employees) are to be identified, nor how such stakeholders are to vote for their board representatives when such a view is advocated.10

The reason why no one has suggested how to operationalize stakeholder vot-ing rights for board representation is that there are significant practical difficulties to be overcome. These difficulties come primarily in two forms. First, how do we identify who the relevant stakeholders are? Are we concerned with relevant stakeholder organizations, groups, or individuals? Are suppliers and customers relevant stakeholders if they make a single transaction or should they have a work-ing relationship over time in order to have a relevant stake? Also, who is meant to represent “society” as a stakeholder? Second, how do stakeholders vote for their representatives on the board? Does each member of a stakeholder organization get to vote on board decisions or does only the organization as a whole get a vote? Is the size of the stakeholder organization important? Should all stakeholders’s votes receive equal weight or do some groups have priority interests? Thus, in abstract, the idea of stakeholder representation on corporate boards is appealing; in practice, it is difficult to realize. Nonetheless, provided the SEN is a faithful representation of stakeholder theory (once the importance of voting rights is appreciated), these practical difficulties are not crucial for our present purposes. Our aim is not to solve the problem of how to operationalize stakeholder theory but rather to offer a norm of governance that does not give primacy to any stakeholder group.11

The SEN extends an equal right to vote to stakeholder representatives on the board which guarantees equal representation for each constituency. However, this does not necessarily mean that they are given equal consideration in every

Page 14: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

196 Business and Professional Ethics Journal

corporate decision that is made. The board (with its stakeholder representatives) chooses the CEO who is given the task of running the daily operations of the corporation and whose responsibility it is to balance the interests of stakeholders depending on the particular circumstances at hand, which does not necessarily de-mand equal consideration of all stakeholders in all circumstances. In this way, the SEN is consistent with the usual depiction of stakeholder theory (Boatright 2002, 1839), in that: “1) all stakeholders have a right to participate in the corporate deci-sions that affect them, 2) managers have a fiduciary duty to serve the interests of all stakeholder groups, and 3) the objective of the firm ought to be the promotion of all interests and not those of shareholders alone.” Further, it “does not imply that all stakeholders should be equally involved in all processes and decisions” (Freeman and Phillips 2002, 340). The SEN adds to this depiction the equal voting rights for stakeholder board representatives because, in our view, previous scholars have not sufficiently appreciated the importance of voting rights for maintaining the primacy of shareholders among stakeholders.12

The intuitive appeal of the SEN as a principle of corporate governance is that it seems fair to let stakeholders have a right to voice their concern and be part of the decision process for issues that affect them. It seems justified on the grounds that Justice as Fairness is to be understood as a broad egalitarian conception only to be departed from when it is to the benefit of the least advantaged. However, it is essential to recognize that Rawls’s theory is narrow in scope and only applies to the basic structure. Justice as fairness does not concern itself with inequalities among stakeholders, but rather potential inequalities among relevant parties in the original position who view the most and least advantaged in terms of access to social primary goods, not what stakeholder group they belong to. From the perspective of the original position, the equal basic liberties of all stakeholders are guaranteed by the basic structure for all citizens.

Phillips et al. (2003, 493) note that “organizations are, to use Rawls’s (1993) terms, voluntary associations rather than a part of the basic structure of society.” This is correct. However there is a difference between the corporate legal form, which is part of the basic structure, and the “associations” (organizations) that citi-zens create when they engage in commercial enterprise through the corporate legal form. Rawls (2001, 11) writes: “One should not assume in advance that principles that are reasonable and just for the basic structure are also reasonable and just for institutions, associations, and social practices generally. While the principles of justice as fairness impose limits on these social arrangements within the basic

Page 15: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy and Business Ethics 197

structure, the basic structure and the associations and social forms within it are each governed by distinct principles in view of their different aims and purposes.”

The appeal of the SEN as an egalitarian and fair principle among stakehold-ers is misplaced in the context of Rawls’s theory. Inequalities of status among members of private associations are entirely permissible, and furthermore it is this which the difference principle sanctions to create the necessary incentives in society for productivity. In a Rawlsian society what matters in arbitrating between the SEN and the SPN is which one is more efficient.

However, it is not our task here to evaluate which of the two norms of gov-ernance is most efficient. This is an empirical matter. Arguments have been put forward on both sides. For example, in favor of the superior efficiency of the SPN (generally construed as SVM) Jensen (2002) has argued that economic efficiency requires governance with a single objective function; Sundaram and Inkpen (2004a; 2004b) have argued that control is best exercised by shareholders as residual claim-ants; and Williamson (1984) has argued that public representation on the board “would come at a high cost if the corporation were thereby politicized or deflected from its chief purpose of serving as an economizing instrument.”

On the other hand, Freeman has argued that corporate management accord-ing to stakeholder theory would be more efficient. Freeman (2008, 18) observes that, “If a business tries to maximize profits, in fact, profits don’t get maximized, at least in the real world.” Freeman et al. (2010, 11–12) say: “We believe that trying to maximize profits is counterproductive because it takes attention away from the fundamental drivers of value—stakeholder relationships. There has been consider-able research that shows that profitable firms have a purpose and values beyond profit maximization.” The central idea here is that members of an organization will not be inspired or motivated by an explicit goal of profit maximization and that for the most profitable corporations profit maximization in this regard is incidental.13

In sum, our analysis suggests that from a position of liberal political philoso-phy (in this instance represented by Rawls’s Justice as Fairness) the main arbiter in the debate between shareholder theory and stakeholder theory is not an ethical or political criterion, but which norm of governance is more economically efficient.14

Libertarianism and the Legitimacy of the SPN

The starting point for libertarian political thinking differs starkly from the liberal one. Where liberalism regards society as fundamentally a cooperative exercise where the state has a central role in administrating that cooperation (both positive and negative rights), libertarianism starts from the negative rights of the atomistic

Page 16: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

198 Business and Professional Ethics Journal

individual outside a social context and then argues towards the limited role of the state in protecting those negative rights.

Friedman / Nozick

Friedman, who advocated shareholder theory (and thus the SPN), was a noted libertarian (Arnold 2003). One of his primary arguments in favor of the SPN was that “[i]n a free-enterprise, private-property system, a corporate executive is an employee of the owners of the business” (1970), and thus executives should act in the interest of their employers. According to Friedman, to act contrary to share-holder interests “would constitute a violation of the liberty rights of stockholders” who are entitled to dispose of their property as they see fit (Nunan 1988, 891). The concept of ownership and the rights attached to private property thus carry much weight in his advocacy of shareholder primacy. He says that property rights are “the most basic of human rights and an essential foundation for other human rights” (R. D. Friedman and M. Friedman 1998, 605). However, for our pres-ent purposes “the key point is that, in his capacity as a corporate executive, the manager is the agent of the individuals who own the corporation or establish the eleemosynary institution, and his primary responsibility is to them” (1970).

The starting point for Friedman’s thinking on the role of the state was that of the atomistic individual. Friedman’s (1962) argumentation rhetorically appeals to the lone and self-sufficient “Robinson Crusoe” on his island where social co-operation is primarily in the form of economic exchanges among a collection of Robinson Crusoes on other islands. This conjures up images of man unto himself with dominion of his surroundings. Friedman firmly believed in the importance of strong private property rights but primarily argued for them on the basis of their instrumental importance for other rights that would leave the individual “free to choose.” He says that “economic freedom is an end in itself” and an “indis-pensible means in the achievement of political freedom” (1962, 8). However his justification for economic freedom being an end in itself (and thus presumably requiring strong private property rights to dispose of property freely) is quite thin. It primarily rests on the assertion that “economic freedom, in and of itself, is an extremely important part of total freedom” (1962, 9). In fact, his main argument is instrumental on the grounds that economic freedom “promotes political free-dom because it separates economic power from political power and in this way enables one to offset the other” (1962, 9). In other words, private property is the cornerstone of economic freedom which in turn is also necessary for political free-dom because only then can empowered dissent against the government exist. This

Page 17: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy and Business Ethics 199

instrumental justification for economic freedom is also consistent with his view on the nature of property rights. Friedman regards property rights as a “complex social creation” that is defined by government. As such property rights are created by us to serve instrumental purposes, although for Freidman those purposes are very fundamental.

Nozick, on the other hand, decided that he would try and establish property rights as fundamental in and of themselves. Nozick, who started off with strong socialist political views, became inspired by Friedman and Hayek and later came to write Anarchy, State, and Utopia, which is arguably the most influential libertar-ian text of the twentieth century.

Nozick opens Anarchy, State and Utopia by saying: “Individuals have rights, and there are things no person or group may do to them (without violating their rights). So strong and far-reaching are these rights that they raise the question of what, if anything, the state and its officials may do. . . . Two noteworthy implica-tions are that the state may not use its coercive apparatus for the purpose of getting some citizens to aid others, or in order to prohibit activities to people for their own good or protection” (1974, ix, italics as per original).

For our present purposes the rights of relevance are property rights, in particular shareholder rights.15 Would Nozick agree to extend voting rights to non-shareholder stakeholders? He advocates property rights that are almost absolute and cannot be infringed upon by the state in order to benefit others. Nozick goes as far as to say that “[t]axation of earnings from labor is on par with forced labor” (1974, 169).

Nozick presents two arguments to justify property as an absolute right. The first is known as the self-ownership argument. It tries to show how individuals can legitimately acquire previously unowned things (in a hypothetical “state of nature” consisting of atomistic individuals), which then become holdings that they are entitled to. For Nozick, the argument is not that we mix our labor with un-owned objects (as was argued by John Locke), but rather that we own ourselves (in body and mind) and therefore we own everything that flows from these natural endowments. When we labor we add value to external objects through our natural endowments, and because we own our natural endowments we also come to have property rights over external objects. However, it is not sufficient that we improve external objects with our natural endowments in order to yield absolute property rights over those objects if the appropriation of unowned objects might worsen the situation of those who do not have the opportunity to appropriate. Nozick believes that this condition is usually met because even though all natural resources may

Page 18: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

200 Business and Professional Ethics Journal

already have been appropriated, those being born now need not be worse off be-cause of the economic synergetic effects that come with private property. Private property rights are said to allow the productive members of society to gain, which in turn creates labor opportunities for all, which leaves “enough and as good as” for others. Kymlicka (1990) explains that property rights enable markets, and mar-kets are efficient and give synergies, making people who cannot acquire property initially better off than if there were no property rights. For Nozick, the concept of self-ownership together with the “enough and as good as” proviso are sufficient to yield absolute property rights that may not legitimately be violated by the state.

The second argument is known as the consent argument. It essentially says that the free and consensual market exchanges among individuals will lead some individuals to earn more than others, but because the exchanges are consensual there is no basis for the state to intervene to redistribute from some individuals to others. Nozick reasons that if part of your earnings are taken in the form of taxation, then part of the time you are working is for free, and this is “on par with forced labor.” Nozick adheres to the Kantian dictum that people should always be treated as ends in themselves and never as means and suggests that high earners are used as mere means for those who earn less, as income is redistributed from the well off to the less well off. This adds to his argument for absolute property rights because if property rights are not absolute then people may be used as mere means without their consent.

Now what does this mean for extending voting rights to non-shareholder stakeholders? If we conceive of the corporation as the property of shareholders then absolute property rights imply absolute control rights over that property. In other words, those stakeholders that are not owners have no right to control the corporation unless explicitly requested to do so by the shareholders. Extending voting rights to non-shareholder stakeholders would infringe upon the control rights of shareholders. In fact, according to this view, current shareholder control rights are likely to be seen as too weak and should extend beyond merely voting for the board of directors.

Interestingly, both Nozick and Rawls adhere to the Kantian dictum of treat-ing people as ends in themselves and not merely as means. People are not to be used for the benefit of others and this puts limits on what individuals may do to one another. “The debate between liberal egalitarians like Rawls and libertarians like Nozick and Milton Friedman is a prominent feature of political argument in modern democratic societies. This debate reflects disagreement about what the correct principle of distributive justice is” (Sandel 1998, 205). This is seen in their

Page 19: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy and Business Ethics 201

different interpretations of Kant’s categorical imperative. Kymlicka (1990) points out that Rawls and Nozick differ on the question of which rights are most impor-tant in treating people as ends in themselves. Rawls prioritizes rights to a certain share of society’s resources, while Nozick prioritizes the right over oneself which for Nozick implies absolute property rights. Seeing society as a fundamentally co-operative exercise, Rawls believes that we have both negative and positive rights, whereas Nozick, who regards individuals atomistically, only views us has having natural negative rights.16

Freeman

While some might object to characterizing Freeman’s position as libertarian, Free-man and Philips’s (2002) article—“Stakeholder theory: A libertarian defense”—is unequivocal regarding stakeholder theory’s libertarian underpinnings. They state: ““[S]takeholder theory” has roots that are deeply libertarian. . . . We argue . . . that strong notions of “freedom” and “voluntary action” are the best possible underpin-nings for stakeholder theory, and in doing so, seek to return “stakeholder theory” to its managerial and libertarian roots found in Freeman (1984)” (2002, 331).17

Freeman also believes that it is a moral imperative that people never be treated merely as means and this forms the normative foundation for his stake-holder theory. Evan and Freeman (2003, 100) write: “The right to property does not yield the right to treat others as means to an end. Property rights are not license to ignore Kant’s principle of respect for persons. Any theory of the modern corpo-ration that is consistent with our considered moral judgments must recognize that property rights are not absolute.”

For Freeman, a libertarian defense of normative stakeholder theory cannot be grounded in the property rights of shareholders (Freeman and Phillips 2002). Instead “[t]he hallmark of libertarian theory is one of consent and agreement.” (Freeman and Phillips 2002, 341). In order for stakeholders not to be used merely as means they ought to have a right to participate in the decisions that affect them.18 If corporations use stakeholders as means then at a minimum stakeholders “must agree to and hence participate (or choose not to participate) in the decisions to be used as such.” (Evan and Freeman 2003, 100). In other words there needs to be consent and agreement from all the parties affected by managerial decisions in order to meet Kant’s categorical imperative.19

Compared to Friedman and Nozick, Freeman shifts focus from property rights to the right of self-determination, thus giving stakeholders a way to influence de-cisions that affect them. Self-determination is achieved by giving stakeholders

Page 20: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

202 Business and Professional Ethics Journal

participation rights in decisions rather than arguing that their property cannot be infringed upon.20 Would Freeman extend voting rights to non-shareholder stake-holders? As we noted earlier Freeman and Evan (1990) do endorse extending voting membership on the board for stakeholders, and this is one way of enabling stake-holders to participate and influence the decisions that affect them. Freeman et al. say that the “idea of stakeholder boards of overseers is actually quite interesting. It may well turn out that such a board becomes a very effective “governance mechanism” to help managers create as much value as possible for stakeholders” (2010, 19).

Exogenous vs. Endogenous Safeguards

All parties to the debate as we have framed it believe that safeguards are necessary in order to protect stakeholders and citizens more generally from the potential ex-ternalizing harms of business. However, disagreement abounds regarding whether such safeguards should be externally imposed (exogenous) or internally imposed (endogenous), as well as how extensive such safeguards should be.

Exogenous Safeguards

Irrespective of whether a Rawlsian society (on reflection of empirical consider-ations of economic efficiency) ends up endorsing the SPN or the SEN, it would endorse exogenous safeguards. According to Rawls (2001), the principles of justice are realized in a “property-owning democracy” (though they could also be realized in societies that do not have such private ownership). Such a society would ensure the widespread ownership of productive assets and human capital ex ante (rather than redistributed ex post) so that the distribution that results from the exchanges and agreements of citizens is just as a matter of pure procedural justice. Once the basic structure is set up, “individuals and associations are then left free to advance their (permissible) ends within the framework of the basic structure, secure in the knowledge that elsewhere in the social system the regulations neces-sary to preserve background justice are in force” (Rawls 2001, 54). For example, this means a set up with appropriate political institutions (Liberty Principle), a public education system (Equality of Opportunity Principle), and inheritance taxes (Difference Principle). By following the publicly recognized rules, the basic liber-ties and the fair distributive shares of citizens are realized.

In a Rawlsian society, neither the SPN nor the SEN would be unfettered because the corporation is embedded and regulated by the basic structure. Rawls (1999, 63) says that “Free market arrangements must be set within a framework of political and legal institutions which regulates the overall trends of economic

Page 21: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy and Business Ethics 203

events and preserves the social conditions necessary for fair equality of oppor-tunity.” When this is achieved, markets and the actors within them can be left to take care of themselves. However, the pursuit of shareholder interests would be constrained by regulation, such as employment law (e.g., to ensure equal opportu-nity), market regulation (e.g., to regulate product safety), competition law (e.g., to avoid excessive market power), environmental law (e.g., to regulate externalities), and tax legislation (e.g., to provide redistributive effects). When this system of background justice is in effect, corporate activity will result in social cooperation (internally) and competition (between corporations) that is just for society as a matter of pure background procedural justice.

Boatright (2002, 1849) notes that “the stockholder and stakeholder theories disagree not about whether third parties ought to be protected from unjust harm, but how best to provide this protection.” Many concerns that stakeholder theorists wish to address are taken care of by the background institutions in Rawls’s theory and primarily through laws protecting the interests of the different stakeholder groups, as suggested above. Referred to as exogenous safeguards by Freeman and Evan (1990, 346–347), they “effectively constrain the pursuit of stockholder in-terests at the expense of other claimants of the firm . . . they force management to balance the interests of stockholders and themselves on the one hand with the interests of customers, suppliers and other stakeholders on the other.”21

Exogenous constraints on corporate behavior that are part of the basic struc-ture can also stretch beyond legislation. For example, the state can grant other legal forms, such as the non-profit corporation, that act as vehicles through which citizens can organize to pursue special interests. One such special interest can be the monitoring of corporate behavior, as is currently the case with many nongov-ernmental organizations (NGOs) (Campbell 2007). Nevertheless, NGOs cannot be allowed free rein in their activities merely because they do not operate from a profit motive. They can suffer from the same legitimacy problems as corporations, not being democratically legitimate representatives of the citizens (Scherer and Palazzo 2007).

To the limited extent that Friedman/Nozick would impose safeguards on cor-porate behavior, those safeguards would be exogenous rather than endogenous. Recall that Friedman asserted that the social responsibility of business is “to use its resources and engage in activities designed to increase its profits so long as it stays within the rules of the game” (1962, 133, our emphasis). In other words, corporate managers ought to work so as to realize the interests of the owners subject to exogenous constraints. Their belief in absolute property rights inhibits

Page 22: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

204 Business and Professional Ethics Journal

endogenous constraints that allow non-shareholder stakeholders from infringing on the owners’ right to control their property. However, as libertarians they do also believe in strong negative rights of non-interference which importantly pre-cludes harming others. The limited role of the state is to put in place the legal and enforcement institutions that are needed to guarantee contracts and protect negative rights. The envisioned limited role of government implies that such a sys-tem of government would espouse limited exogenous constraints and regulation. For example, Friedman and Friedman (1979) believe there is a role for govern-ment to play in rectifying market-failures such as addressing negative corporate externalities (“neighborhood effects”) such as environmental pollution. However, Friedman and Friedman caution against too readily turning to the government as a solution. “The imperfect market, may after all, do as well or better than the imper-fect government” (1979, 218). Friedman would regard extensive regulation to be a distortion to the efficiency of the market, while Rawls would regard it as essential to frame the market so that the interactions lead to a just result.

Endogenous Safeguards

Instead of such exogenous constraints, Freeman and Evan (1990) propose a theory with endogenous safeguards that do not externalize the costs of activities among contracting parties on others. (A simple way to understand the demarcation be-tween endogenous vs. exogenous constraints is that the former involves corporate self-constraint while the latter involves externally imposed constraints.) However, for Rawls, it is essential that the safeguards are exogenous as his theory regards the basic structure as the primary subject of justice. The justificatory difference between Freeman and Rawls stems from their different libertarian and liberal starting points. Freeman and Evan (1990) object to exogenous constraints primar-ily on two fronts: (1) that endogenous constraints are more effective in protecting stakeholder interests, and (2) that exogenous constraints externalize contracting costs onto society.

First, Freeman and Evan (1990) wish to grant stakeholder voting member-ship on the board because it is seen as more effective in protecting stakeholders’ interests. In essence, they take the view that safeguards that are created endog-enously to the corporation through bilateral contracting between the corporation and stakeholders, together with the more general safeguard of board stakeholder representation, will always be more effective than exogenous stakeholder safe-guards imposed by government. This view is maintained because government cannot legislate in a manner that is tailored to the particular circumstances of

Page 23: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy and Business Ethics 205

stakeholders of individual corporations. However, it is not clear that endogenous safeguards always are more effective (or more efficient) for protecting stakeholder interests. Although Freeman and Evan are correct in their view that government cannot tailor its safeguards to every corporation, there will be many circumstances when exogenous safeguards through government regulation are both more effec-tive and more efficient. For example bilateral-agreements may not give effective protection to one party if the other party is in a significantly stronger bargain-ing position, and this is not circumvented by equal voting membership on the board because any stakeholder group in a system of voting is subject to the risk of minority oppression. Exogenous safeguards can on the other hand give protec-tion to stakeholder groups irrespective of the internal contractual dynamics of the corporation. Boatright (2002, 1842) believes that stakeholder theorists regard the shareholder-management relationship as an ideal for treating all stakeholders, but that “stakeholders usually derive little benefit from the set of rights negotiated by shareholders and generally prefer other safeguards for their interests. Instead of seeking a seat on the board of directors or the benefit of fiduciary duties, con-sumers, for example, settle for manufacturers’ warranties, consumer and product safety laws, and a tort liability system.” Furthermore, it can also be argued that exogenous stakeholder protections that are applicable to all corporations can be much more efficient for protecting the interests of stakeholders as it saves the con-tracting of each of these safeguards for every corporation for every stakeholder group (Child and Marcoux 1999).

Moreover, although formal constraints (endogenous or exogenous) are im-portant, one should not characterize stakeholders as helpless minions at the mercy of all-powerful managers. Stakeholders are capable of engaging in strategies to further their own ends (Frooman 1999). Just as managers can engage in the management of stakeholders, stakeholders can engage in the management of man-agers. However, there will be differing power relationships and therefore different strategies across stakeholders if they are to get what they want (Mitchell, Agle, and Wood 1997).

Second, Freeman and Phillips (2002, 335) think that “Rawls’s first principle of justice is a paradigm case of a libertarian principle.” The first principle accords with them because it sets out the liberties of individuals and essentially puts for-ward negative rights of non-interference. However, the second principle would seem to be unacceptable because it affords citizens of the state positive rights which require the use of social resources that would involve a redistribution of wealth. For libertarians, positive rights only arise through individual consent and,

Page 24: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

206 Business and Professional Ethics Journal

moreover, state aid may violate some negative rights (such as the right not to have one’s property infringed upon) through the need for taxation. This helps explain Freeman and Evan’s second objection to exogenous safeguards that their costs “are spread over the entire society” (1990, 347). The cost of legislating and enforc-ing government regulation is spread across citizens, usually through taxation. This is objectionable to libertarians because it imposes costs on third parties to corpo-rate contracting (without their consent). In other words those, and only those, who engage in contracting should bear the full costs that result from their agreements. However, for liberals and Rawls in particular, there is nothing objectionable per se for society to bear third party costs if this results in a fairer basic structure. Furthermore, it would be practicably unworkable and inefficient to internalize all the potential external costs of contracting as every potentially affected third party would need to engage in the contracting and be compensated bi-laterally (Child and Marcoux, 1999).

In a Rawlsian society, the corporate legal form, as part of the basic structure, would be regarded as an instrument to be used by citizens as allowed by the state. On the other hand Freeman, and libertarians more generally, regard the corpora-tion as a nexus-of-contracts where the corporation is conceptualized as a set of voluntary agreements that should be self-enforcing in order to limit the role of the state (Freeman and Phillips 2002). This helps explain the different uses of exog-enous and endogenous controls. With Rawls, the state provides a corporate legal form which is part of the basic structure where the exogenous controls provide a playing field that procedurally leads to a just outcome when individuals act within the rules, while for Freeman justice results from responsible individuals respecting the fundamental rights of others when contracting freely and through this process of contracting form corporations.

SPN vs. SEN

Both the SPN and the SEN operate on the inside of the corporation as norms of corporate governance. As such, these norms are about how corporations achieve their goals. From a liberal viewpoint that goal is efficient production within con-straints, while from the libertarian viewpoint the goal is decided by the rights holders; in the case of Nozick by the shareholders, and in the case of Freeman by the stakeholders.

For liberals like Rawls, property rights are instrumental for enabling an ef-ficient economy and likewise the choice between the SPN and the SEN also falls to efficiency. For libertarians the instrumental aspect of property is also important

Page 25: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy and Business Ethics 207

as is seen in the justification for Nozick’s “enough and as good” proviso, but primarily property is fundamental as a natural right irrespective of its beneficial consequences, which in turn leads to the advocacy of absolute property rights. “When Robert Nozick argues for the necessity, for reasons of justice, of guar-anteeing individual liberties including the rights of property ownership .  .  . he is ready to leave matters in the hands of these institutions [needed to enable a legal and economic framework] rather than calling for any revision based on an assessment of outcomes” (Sen 2009, 84). Similarly, with Freeman, although he believes that stakeholder theory on an instrumental interpretation will lead to the best outcome, normatively it is based on the rights of stakeholders to participate in the decisions that affect them irrespective of the consequences for the corporation.

Both shareholder theory and stakeholder theory are capable of sharing lib-ertarian foundations through a nexus-of-contracts view of the corporation. On a libertarian interpretation, shareholder theory results from the nexus-of-contracts when a strong focus is placed on the property and control rights of shareholders, while stakeholder theory results when emphasis is placed on the stakeholders’ rights to participate in decision-making. Furthermore, shareholder theory and stakeholder theory are also capable of having foundations within political liber-alism. Rawls’s theory might endorse the SPN or the SEN depending on which is found to be empirically most efficient. Rawls’s political liberalism advocates exogenous safeguards in order to protect citizens and as such protects them across the range of stakeholder hats they might wear. With the SPN, a Rawlsian society would constrain corporations with extensive regulation, while with the SEN, exog-enous constraints might be more moderate due to its self-regulating nature.

Mintzberg (1985) provides a useful categorization of the different perspec-tives that have been put forward regarding who should control the corporation. This categorization is in the form of a “conceptual horseshoe” that places the different perspectives on a spectrum from purely social justifications where the corpora-tion is nationalized, to purely economic justifications where the shareholders have complete corporate control. The preceding positions that we have discussed can be seen to fall into this spectrum of categories. Stakeholder theory in its Freemanite guise would fall under the category of “Democratize it,” implying that employees and other stakeholders have a right to be part of the corporate decision-making process. Rawls’s theory of justice, whether or not it endorses the SPN or the SEN, would fall under the category of “Regulate it,” showing the importance of ex-ogenous constrains. And finally, shareholder theory in its Friedmanite/Nozickian guise would fall under the category of “Restore it,” implying that full corporate

Page 26: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

208 Business and Professional Ethics Journal

control rights need to be restored to the shareholders. Mintzberg suggests that in practice none of the positions can be relied on exclusively. “I believe that we need to treat the conceptual horseshoe as a portfolio of positions from which we can draw, depending on circumstances. Exclusive reliance on any position will lead to a narrow and dogmatic society” (1985, 61).

The shareholder vs. stakeholder debate has played out over the years primar-ily as a normative debate between competing positions within moral philosophy, with utilitarian arguments often offered in favor of shareholder theory and deon-tological arguments often offered in favor of stakeholder theory. This is perhaps one of the reasons why the debate has not come much closer to a resolution. The two main normative branches of moral philosophy (utilitarian and deontological) are irreconcilable; either consequences are fundamental or principles are funda-mental.22 Much the same can be said about different positions within in political philosophy. However, political philosophy, unlike moral philosophy, is not funda-mentally about how we should treat each other, but rather about the terms upon which we should live and cooperate together and the principles that should govern the institutions that administer that cooperation. Philosophically, there is little con-sensus as to whether liberal or libertarian modes of government are preferable, but there is a consensus (or as close as we will ever get to a consensus) that the process for resolving such differences is called democracy. Democracy allows citizens to choose how they should be governed and this offers a practical solution to differ-ing normative conceptions of political justice. Through a consensus to abide by the political principles of government that result from a democratic process, an actual choice is made in favor of one political philosophy over another. In this way, by regarding the shareholder vs. stakeholder debate primarily in terms of political philosophy, we can deem acceptable whichever of the two positions that results in any (well functioning) democracy.

How the differences between political conceptions affect the CSR initiatives of corporations in different nations is brought to the fore in the paper by Mat-ten and Moon (2008) on implicit and explicit CSR. “Explicit CSR” is defined as “corporate policies that assume and articulate responsibility for some societal interests” (2008, 409). To the extent that corporations engage in explicit CSR, it is more prevalent in the US where belief in individual responsibility and small government lead managers/owners to assume moral duties towards their stake-holders. On the other hand, “implicit CSR normally consists of values, norms, and rules that result in (mandatory and customary) requirements for corporations to address stakeholder issues that define proper obligations of corporate actors in

Page 27: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy and Business Ethics 209

collective rather than individual terms” (2008, 409). Implicit CSR is more preva-lent in Europe were there is a greater acceptance of collective responsibility and large government with attendant regulation.

Neither European countries nor the US are entirely liberal or libertarian in the manner that we have presented the respective political philosophies in this paper, but there is a tendency towards large government and small government respec-tively, and this is related to liberal and libertarian justification which influence the nature and extent of exogenous and endogenous safeguards for stakeholders. In well functioning democracies, both shareholder theory and stakeholder theory, whether with endogenous or differing degrees of exogenous safeguards, must be regarded as acceptable.23

Conclusion

At the core of the basic debate in business ethics is the legitimacy of the shareholder primacy norm and thus whether managers should focus primarily on shareholder or stakeholder interests. This paper offers four key conclusions on the debate: (1) A recognition of the importance of voting rights for perpetuating the Shareholder Primacy Norm (SPN) leads to the Stakeholder Equality Norm (SEN) as an ap-propriate operationalization of stakeholder theory with the SEN as a competing norm of governance to the SPN; (2) A Liberal society (Rawls) would arbitrate between the SPN and the SEN based on which is economically most efficient; (3) A Libertarian society (Fiedman/Nozick; Freeman) would arbitrate between the SPN and the SEN based on how one interprets the right to self-determination; either it requires absolute property rights for shareholders or it requires an equal right for stakeholders to participate in decision-making; (4) The debate between shareholder theory and stakeholder theory is framed by liberal and libertarian jus-tifications that primarily hinge on whether and to what extent one should have exogenous or endogenous safeguards.

Drawing on stakeholder theory as the competing theory to shareholder theory, we formulate the Stakeholder Equality Norm as the alternative norm of corporate governance to the SPN. The SEN extends an equal right to vote to stakeholder rep-resentatives on the board which gives equal representation for each constituency and leads to the removal of shareholder primacy (as it is the sole right to vote for the board that establishes the SPN).

Contrary to what one might first assume, but in keeping with Rawls’s egalitarianism, we then argue that the choice between shareholder primacy and broader stakeholder considerations does not hinge on deliberations of fairness in a

Page 28: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

210 Business and Professional Ethics Journal

Rawlsian society but on which governance principle is best from the perspective of economic efficiency. This is because the unit of analysis for Rawls is the citi-zens of society and not corporate stakeholders. Hence, when the basic structure fully realizes the two principles of justice, the primary arbiter among economic systems is efficiency to the benefit of the least advantaged. Economic efficiency would thus also arbitrate between the SPN and the SEN. However, neither the SPN nor the SEN would be unfettered in a Rawlsian society. In Justice as Fairness the basic structure would impose exogenous constraints on management mainly through legislation that aims to regulate corporate behavior in line with Rawls’s two principles of justice.

On the other hand, libertarian political philosophy is also capable of en-dorsing both the SPN and the SEN depending on how one interprets the right to self-determination. Friedman/Nozick regard absolute property rights as funda-mental to self-determination, otherwise property owners are used merely as means when others have control rights over the property that they have labored for. On this interpretation, the SPN is endorsed to guarantee the corporate control rights of shareholders. Freeman, on the other hand, regards a right to participate in the decision-making process over issues that affect stakeholders as central to not treat-ing stakeholders merely as means. On this interpretation, the SEN is endorsed to extend corporate control rights to a wider group of stakeholders than merely shareholders.

It is interesting that all parties to the debate (Rawls, Nozick, and Freeman) claim to have Kantian foundations that adhere to the categorical imperative. For Rawls it requires both negative and positive rights on a societal level that protect citizens from harms as well as extending a right to share in society’s resources so that liberties may be exercised; for Nozick it implies absolute rights to property to avoid “forced labor” of property owners; and for Freeman it implies decision-making rights to enable consensual stakeholder relations.

Finally, our analysis shows that the issue of how corporate behavior should be constrained cuts to the heart of the basic debate between shareholder theory and stakeholder theory. Shareholder theory promotes exogenous safeguards while stakeholder theory tends to promote endogenous safeguards, and the justifications for these differences essentially reduce to a debate between political liberalism versus libertarianism. Liberalism tends towards strong exogenous safeguards (Rawls, SPN or SEN), while libertarianism tends towards either weak exogenous safeguards (Friedman/Nozick, SPN) or endogenous safeguards (Freeman, SEN).

Page 29: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy and Business Ethics 211

The basic debate between shareholder theory and stakeholder theory thus becomes a matter of liberal and libertarian interpretations applied to corporate constituencies. Therefore political philosophy is significant to both business ethics and corporate governance because of the potential constraints placed on the corpo-ration by the state. By regarding the debate as one founded on political philosophy this provides a practical resolution to the conflict through an acceptance of the outcome of the democratic political process.

Endnotes

1. Freeman does not regard stakeholder theory as opposed to the satisfaction of shareholder interests; rather, he regards shareholder theory as encompassed by stake-holder theory (see Freeman et. al. 2010). Freeman et al. (2007, 76) note that “even if you want to maximize value for shareholders, you still have to create value for stake-holders.”

2. Dodge v. Ford is the most cited case to articulate the shareholder primacy norm. However, Lynn Stout (2012) suggests that the case is widely misunderstood be-cause it was primarily about the minority oppression of shareholders in a closely held corporation (rather than a public corporation). The court found that majority share-holder Ford had no right to disregard the financial interests of minority shareholders the Dodge brothers. Furthermore, and perhaps most importantly, Justice Ostrander’s remark was “mere dicta,” i.e., a remark that was not necessary to reach the court’s decision.

3. With the introduction of the business judgment rule the SPN became un-enforceable, but it was only with the introduction of non-shareholder constituency statutes that it ceased to be prohibited for managers to consider non-shareholder inter-ests.

4. Anderson (2000, 170) defines a social norm as “a standard of behavior shared by a social group, commonly understood by its members as authoritative or obligatory for them.”

5. A recent study by Witt and Redding (2009) that investigates senior executive perceptions of why firms exist, found that US executives cited shareholders as the pri-mary reason for the firm’s existence whereas German and Japanese executives placed less importance on shareholders. This corroborates the view that US executives hold the SPN as a social norm. It also supports our argument regarding the significance of the structure of corporate law in perpetuating the SPN as a social norm because both Germany and Japan have corporate governance systems that are less shareholder-centric than the US model.

Page 30: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

212 Business and Professional Ethics Journal

6. Rawls introduces a further five core ideas in order to justify his principles of justice: the idea of a well-ordered society; the idea of the basic structure as the primary subject of justice; the idea of an original position; the idea of free and equal citizens; and, the idea of public justification.

7. Does the assignment of voting rights have to be part of the corporate legal form? Strictly speaking, the corporate legal form can be agnostic with regard to the distribution of voting rights to stakeholders. However, in an economic system with private ownership in the means of production, the SPN will obtain as a norm of gover-nance by default. The concept of ownership involves a significant element of control over the property owned. The very point of an economic system with private owner-ship in the means of production is that citizens, as opposed to the state, control the means of production. Corporations are created by investors coming together and in-corporating. They then elect a board that employs managers that in turn contracts with different stakeholders. They may even, if they so wish, extend voting rights to other stakeholders. The point is that this is done at the discretion of the shareholders. Sim-ply by being the first stakeholders they become the primary stakeholders. In a private property system, control over assets is exercised by the owners, and you cannot have a shareholderless for-profit corporation (though clearly there are models where the owners might be employees too). The shareholders arrive first. Therefore, unless it is written into the corporate legal form that all stakeholders must have an equal right to vote, then arguably the default becomes shareholder primacy.

8. The lexical priority of the liberty principle and the equal opportunity prin-ciple over the difference principle also implies that the primary goods covered by the former cannot be exchanged for primary goods covered by the latter. For example, Justice as Fairness would not endorse a move to a system with constrained liberties of free speech but that benefitted from greater income and wealth.

9. Note that Rawls assumes that a system of social cooperation would allow for redistribution of income and wealth. Therefore if initially only one person benefits from a change to the system, both can benefit in the end.

10. German corporate law provides employees with board representation for cor-porations above a certain size (number of employees). This is made possible because employees are easily identifiable individuals while other stakeholder groups with more transactional relationships with the corporations do not lend themselves to such easy and relevant identification.

11. The SEN could also be formulated by removing shareholder voting rights thus making all stakeholders equal with respect to lacking voting rights. In this manner the primacy of shareholders would be removed. In order to establish equal stakeholder consideration (in the absence of voting rights) one could envisage that managers are (through statutory law) charged with duties of equal consideration for all stakeholders.

Page 31: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy and Business Ethics 213

By formulating the SEN in this manner one overcomes the problems of identifying relevant stakeholders to give equal voting rights to. However, the problem of who the “relevant stakeholders” are that management owes equal consideration to is still left opaque as well as creating the difficulty of who should appoint the board of directors if there are no voters that decide. Nothing in this paper crucially hinges on the “no voting rights” or “equal voting rights” interpretation of the SEN as long as no constituency can impose themselves as primary. We will focus on the “equal voting rights” inter-pretation of the SEN despite its practical difficulties because it is truer to the spirit of stakeholder theory as it seeks to empower stakeholders equally with voting rights.

12. Since Freeman (1984) introduced stakeholder theory it has come to mean many things to many people, making it difficult to speak of generically. However, as Freeman is undoubtedly the “father” of stakeholder theory, we use his writings to represent the core of the theory (with greater attention to the normative aspects of the theory). Freeman’s views have changed over the years; in particular, the position that management should balance stakeholder interests (1984) has evolved into a form of multiple stakeholder value creation (Freeman et al. 2007; Freeman et. al. 2010). How-ever, neither position speaks directly to stakeholder equality. Indeed, most treatments of stakeholder theory do not discuss stakeholder equality, yet this is an unavoidable consequence of removing the primacy of one stakeholder group (that has sole voting rights). The SEN is the logical counter norm to the SPN once one realizes how voting rights dictate primary consideration by management.

13. But unlike shareholder theory, maximizing profits is not the main point of stakeholder theory. Donaldson and Preston (1995, 79–81) maintain that success for stakeholder theory lies “in satisfying multiple stakeholder interests—rather than in meeting conventional economic and financial criteria. . . . No theorist, including Rawls, has ever maintained that bargains reached on the basis of the “veil of ignorance” would maximize efficiency.” Similarly, Collins (1997) maintains that irrespective of the effi-ciency of “participatory management” in corporations, the primary reason for adopting such a system of governance rests on its supposed ethical superiority.

14. Justice as Fairness is not a moral theory that asks people (or managers) to be impartial in their treatment of other people (or stakeholders); rather it is a political theory that asks the basic institutions of society to follow the two impartial principles of justice in their treatment of all citizens (irrespective of what stakeholder group they belong to). Citizens do not fall into discrete stakeholder groups; each individual citi-zen can belong to any number of stakeholder groups depending on their numerous relationships with corporations throughout society. As a political theory, Justice as Fairness covers the concerns of all stakeholders by virtue of their status as citizens. The basic structure seen as a coherent whole is egalitarian in its treatment of citizens

Page 32: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

214 Business and Professional Ethics Journal

(but that does not necessarily translate into egalitarian principles of how managers treat different stakeholders).

15. Technically the law separates the corporation and its assets from the share-holders. The corporation owns itself, while shareholders own shares as a separate form of property (Pickering 1968). However, the fiduciary duties imposed on managers in common law are due to early judicial depictions of their relationship with sharehold-ers as one of trust (e.g., Berle 1931; 1932). Managers were considered trustees for the shareholders who were the owners of the corporation. Despite the mid-nineteenth-century separation of the corporation from its shareholders in terms of ownership, important features of the structure of corporate law that came with the earlier depiction remained, both in terms of fiduciary duties and more importantly in terms of voting rights of shareholders (Tricker 2009). Although shareholders do not technically own the assets of the corporation, the spirit of the law still treats them as owners and gives them the power to direct the corporation through their voting rights.

16. Rawls and other liberals hold that positive rights, which may interfere with some negative rights, are necessary to make the negative rights meaningful. For ex-ample, the liberty to pursue one’s own destiny is vacuous unless one has some means (income and wealth) with which to pursue it (Nagel 1975).

17. To be clear, note that Freeman’s own view of libertarianism is consistent with Wolff’s (2000) broad characterization of libertarianism which we use. Freeman and Phillips (2002) say: “We claim that an argument is a libertarian argument if it (1) relies on freedom, liberty, the equal liberty principle, or some kindred notion; (2) relies on basic negative rights, like those defined in Rawls’s first principle, and including indi-vidual rights to property; (3) allows for the creation of positive obligations through various voluntary actions (e.g., contracting and promising); (4) countenances at most a minimal state, as defined by Nozick and others; and, (5) assumes that human beings are largely responsible for their actions on others.

18. Paas (1996) points out that stakeholder participation rights in decision-making do not follow from Kant’s categorical imperative to never treat people “merely as a means to an end.” This second formulation of the categorical imperative allows people to treat others as means, but not merely as means. This is made clear by the fact that any transaction of a good or service involves using the other party in a transaction as a means to attain the object of the transaction. A carpenter agrees to be a means through which a home owner gets a new porch, and the homeowner agrees to be a source of income for the carpenter. Therefore it does not necessarily follow that stakeholders have a right to participate in decisions that affect them, because as is often the case, there is an explicit or implicit agreement that one party will do as requested by the other; i.e., that the carpenter will build the porch and the homeowner will pay. What the categorical

Page 33: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy and Business Ethics 215

imperative forbids is that either party does not fulfill their part of the agreement; that would be to use someone merely as a means.

19. Although Freeman explicitly argues for a libertarian defense (Freeman and Philips 2002) as well as a Kantian defense (Evan and Freeman 2003) of normative stakeholder theory, the connection between the two has not been explicitly made before. This connection does seem palpable given Freemans rejection of absolute property rights, his concern with consent and agreement making, as well as his ad-herence to not treating people merely as means. This connection is made stronger by noting how other libertarians like Nozick also ground their theories in an adherence to Kant’s categorical imperative.

20. Friedman and Nozick do not disregard the importance of self-determina-tion, but they see absolute property rights as necessary for the self-determination of property owners whereas Freeman sees absolute property rights as inhibiting the self-determination of those who are not the property owners.

21. Note that voting rights for the board of directors in a Rawlsian society qualify as an exogenous safeguard because they are part of the corporate legal form that is part of the basic structure. However, voting rights have the property of operating internally by making directors and managers responsive to the interests of the voting right hold-ers. As such, one would imagine that the SEN would entail a diminished need for other exogenous safeguards for stakeholders as it is designed to respond to stakeholder concerns internally.

22. Certainly attempts have been made to reconcile the two, such as rule utilitari-anism, but the fundamental conflict regarding the mode of argumentation in terms of either consequences or principles still remains.

23. Varying degrees of exogenous and endogenous safeguards on corporate be-haviour are today influenced at the political level by liberal and libertarian sentiments regarding the role of government. However, if the democratic political process is to truly provide a resolution to the shareholder vs. stakeholder debate, then the debate itself (rather than just the extent of safeguards) needs to be politically and directly debated.

References

Agle, B. R., and R. K. Mitchell. 2008. “Introduction: Recent Research and New Ques-tions.” Introductory section of “Dialogue: Toward Superior Stakeholder Theory.” Business Ethics Quarterly 18(2): 153–159.doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/beq200818214

Page 34: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

216 Business and Professional Ethics Journal

Anderson, E. 2000. “Beyond Homo Economics: New Developments in Theories of Social Norms.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 29(2): 170–200.doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1088-4963.2000.00170.x

Arnold, D. G. 2003. “Libertarian Theories of the Corporation and Global Capitalism.” Journal of Business Ethics 48: 155–173.doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1023/B:BUSI.0000004595.77613.ec

Benz, M., and B. S. Frey. 2007. “Corporate Governance: What Can We Learn from Public Governance?” Academy of Management Review 32: 92–104.doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.5465/AMR.2007.23463860

Berle, A. A. 1931. “Corporate Powers as Powers of Trust.” Harvard Law Review 44: 1049–1074. doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/1331341

———. 1932. “For Whom are Corporate Mangers Trustees: A Note.” Harvard Law Review 45(7): 1365–1372. doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/1331920

Boatright, J. R. 1994. “Fiduciary Duties and the Shareholder-management Relation: Or, What’s So Special about Shareholders?” Business Ethics Quarterly 4(4): 393–407.

———. 2002. “Contractors as Stakeholders: Reconciling Stakeholder Theory with the Nexus-of-Contracts Firm.” Journal of Banking and Finance 26: 1837–1852. doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/S0378-4266(02)00194-2

Bonnafous-Boucher, M. 2005. “Some Philosophical Issues in Corporate Governance: The Role of Property in Stakeholder Theory.” Corporate Governance 5(2): 34–47. doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1108/14720700510569229

Buchholz, R. A., and S. B. Rosenthal. 2002. “Social Responsibility and Business Ethics.” In A Companion to Business Ethics, ed. R. E. Frederick, 303–322. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishers.

Campbell, J. L. 2007. “Why Would Corporations Behave in Socially Responsible Ways? An Institutional Theory of Corporate Social Responsibility.” Academy of Management Review 32(3): 946–967.doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.5465/AMR.2007.25275684

Child, J. W., and A. M. Marcoux. 1999. “Freeman and Evan: Stakeholder Theory in the Original Position.” Business Ethics Quarterly 9(2): 2007–223.doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/3857472

Chilosi, A., and M. Damiani. 2007. “Stakeholders vs. Shareholders in Corporate Governance.” Journal of Corporate Governance 6(4): 7–45.

Collins, D. 1997. “The Ethical Superiority and Inevitability of Participatory Manage-ment as an Organizational System.” Organization Science 8(5): 489–507.doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1287/orsc.8.5.489

Page 35: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy and Business Ethics 217

Dodd, M. E. 1932. “For Whom are Corporate Managers Trustees?” Harvard Law Review 45: 1145–1163. doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/1331697

Donaldson, T., and L. E. Preston. 1995. “The Stakeholder Theory of the Corporation: Concepts, Evidence, and Implications.” Academy of Management Review 20(1): 65–91.

Easterbrook, F., and D. Fischel. 1985. “Limited Liability and the Corporation.” Uni-versity of Chicago Law Review 52: 89–117.doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/1599572

Evan, W. M., and R. E. Freeman. 2003. “A Stakeholder Theory of the Modern Corpora-tion: Kantian Capitalism.” In Ethical Theory and Business, ed. T. L. Beauchamp and N. E. Bowie. London: Prentice Hall.

Fisch, J. E. 2006. “Measuring Efficiency in Corporate Law: The Role of Shareholder Primacy.” The Journal of Corporation Law 31: 637–674.

Freeman, R. E. 1984. Strategic Management: A Stakeholder Approach. Boston: Pit-man Publishing Inc.

———. 1994. “The Politics of Stakeholder Theory: Some Future Directions.” Busi-ness Ethics Quarterly 4(4): 409–421.doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/3857340

———. 2008. “Ending the So-called ‘Friedman-Freeman’ Debate.” Section II of “Dialogue: Towards Superior Stakeholder Theory.” Business Ethics Quarterly 18(2): 153–190. doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/beq200818214

Freeman, R. E, and W. M. Evan. 1990. “Corporate Governance: A Stakeholder Ap-proach.” Journal of Behavioral Economics 19(4): 337–359.doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/0090-5720(90)90022-Y

Freeman, R. E., J. Harrison, and A. Wicks. 2007. Managing for Stakeholders: Survival, Reputation, and Success. New Haven and London: Yale University Press.

Freeman, R. E., J. Harrison, A. Wicks, B. Parmar, and S. de Colle. 2010. Stakeholder Theory: State of the Art. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511815768

Freeman, R. E., and R. A. Phillips. 2002. “Stakeholder Theory: A Libertarian De-fense.” Business Ethics Quarterly 12(3): 331–349.doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/3858020

Freeman, S. 2008. Rawls. New York: Routledge.Friedman, M. 1962. Capitalism and Freedom. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.———. 1970. “The Social Responsibility of Business is to Increase its Profits.” The

New York Times Magazine, September 13.Friedman, M., and R. D. Friedman. 1979. Free to Choose: A Personal Statement. New

York: Harcourt, Inc.

Page 36: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

218 Business and Professional Ethics Journal

Friedman, R. D. and M. Friedman. 1998. Two Lucky People: Memoirs. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Frooman, J. 1999. “Stakeholder Influence Strategies.” Academy of Management Re-view 24: 191–205.

Galai, D., and Z. Wiener. 2008. “Stakeholders and the Composition of the Voting Rights of the Board of Directors.” Journal of Corporate Finance 14(2):107–117.doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.jcorpfin.2008.02.005

Hartman, E. M. 1994. “The Commons and the Moral Organization.” Business Ethics Quarterly 4(3): 253–269. doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/3857446

Hinkley, R. 2002. “How Corporate Law Inhibits Social Responsibility.” The Humanist 62(2): 26–28

Jensen, M. C. 2002. “Value Maximization, Stakeholder Theory, and the Corporate Objective Function.” Business Ethics Quarterly 12(2): 235–256.doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/3857812

Kraakman, R. R., P. Davies, H. Hansmann, G. Hertig, K. J. Hopt, H. Kanda, and E. B. Rock. 2004. The Anatomy of Corporate Law: A Comparative and Functional Approach. New York: Oxford University Press.

Krouse, R. and M. McPherson. 1988. “Capitalism, ‘Property-Owning Democracy,’ and the Welfare State.” In Democracy and the Welfare State, ed. A. Gutmann, 79–105. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Kymlicka, W. 1990. Contemporary Political Philosophy: An Introduction. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Matten, D., and J. Moon. 2008. “‘Implicit’ and ‘Explicit’ CSR: A Conceptual Frame-work for a Comparative Understanding of Corporate Social Responsibility.” Academy of Management Review 33(2): 404–424.doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.5465/AMR.2008.31193458

McDonnell, B. H. 2004. “Corporate Constituency Statutes and Employee Gover-nance.” William Mitchell Law Review 30(4): 1227–1259.

McWilliams, A., and D. Siegel. 2001. “Corporate Social Responsibility: A Theory of the Firm Perspective.” Academy of Management Review 26(1): 117–127.

Melé, D. 2008. “Corporate Social Responsibility Theories. In The Oxford Handbook of Corporate Social Responsibility, edited by A. Crane, A. McWilliams, D. Mat-ten, J. Moon, and D. S. Siegel, 47–82. Oxford: Oxford University Press.doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199211593.003.0003

Mintzberg, H. 1985. “Who Should Control the Corporation?” The McKinsey Quarterly (Autumn): 47–64.

Page 37: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy and Business Ethics 219

Mitchell, R. K., B. R. Agle, and D. J. Wood. 1997. “Toward a Theory of Stakeholder Identification and Salience: Defining the Principle of Who and What Really Counts.” Academy of Management Review 22(4): 853–886.

Moriarty, J. 2005. “On the Relevance of Political Philosophy to Business Ethics.” Business Ethics Quarterly 15(3): 455–473.doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/beq200515330

Nagel, T. 1975. “Libertarianism without Foundations.” Yale Law Journal 85: 136–149.doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/795521

Nozick, R. 1974. Anarchy, State, and Utopia. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers Ltd.Nunan, R. 1988. “The Libertarian Conception of Corporate Property: A Critique of

Milton Friedman’s Views on the Social Responsibility of Business.” Journal of Business Ethics 7: 891–906.

Paas, D. 1996. “Stakeholders and Participation in Corporate Governance: A Critique of Some of the Arguments.” Business and Professional Ethics Journal 15(4): 3–17. doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/bpej199615410

Phillips, R. 2003. Stakeholder Theory and Organizational Ethics. San Francisco: Berrett-Koehler Publishers. doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/beq200313434

Phillips, R., E. R. Freeman, and A. C. Wicks. 2003. “What Stakeholder Theory is Not.” Business Ethics Quarterly 13(4): 479–502.

Phillips, R. A. 1997. “Stakeholder Theory and a Principle of Fairness.” Business Ethics Quarterly 7(1): 51–66. doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/3857232

Phillips, R. A., and J. D. Margolis. 1999. “Towards an Ethics of Organizations.” Busi-ness Ethics Quarterly 9(4): 619–638. doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/3857939

Pickering, M. A. 1968. “Company as a Separate Legal Entity.” Modern Law Review 31: 481–511. doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-2230.1968.tb01206.x

Rawls, J. 1996. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.———. 1999. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard Uni-

versity Press.———. 2001. Justice as Fairness: A Restatement. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of

Harvard University Press.Sandel, M. J. 1998. Liberalism and the Limits of Justice. NY: Cambridge University

Press. doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511810152Scherer, A. G., and G. Palazzo. 2007. “Towards a Political Conception of Corporate

Social Responsibility: Business and Society Seen from a Habermasian Perspec-tive.” Academy of Management Review 32(4): 1096–1120.doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.5465/AMR.2007.26585837

Sen, A. 2009. The Idea of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

Page 38: Shareholders vs. Stakeholders: How Liberal and Libertarian Political Philosophy Frames the Basic Debate in Business Ethics

220 Business and Professional Ethics Journal

Smith, D. G. 1998. “The Shareholder Primacy Norm.” The Journal of Corporation Law 23: 277–323.

Stout, L. 2012. The Shareholder Value Myth: How Putting Shareholders First Harms Investors, Corporations and the Public. San Francisco: Berrett-Koehler Publishers, Inc.

Suchman, M. C. 1995. “Managing Legitimacy: Strategic and Institutional Approaches.” Academy of Management Review 20: 571–610.

Sundaram, A. K., and A. C. Inkpen. 2004a. “The Corporate Objective Revisited.” Organization Science 15(3): 350–363. doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1287/orsc.1040.0068

———. 2004b. “Stakeholder theory and ‘The corporate objective revisited’: A reply.” Organization Science 15(3): 370–371.doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1287/orsc.1040.0067

Testy, K. 2002. “Linking Progressive Corporate Law with Progressive Social Move-ments.” Tulane Law Review 76: 1227–1252.

Tricker, B. 2009. Corporate Governance: Principles, Policies, and Practices. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Waldron, J. 2000. “Liberalism.” Concise Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. London: Routledge, 486.

Wempe, B. 2005. “In Defense of a Self-disciplined, Domain-specific Social Contract Theory of Business Ethics.” Business Ethics Quarterly 15(1): 113–135.doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/beq20051516

Williamson, O. 1984. “Corporate Governance.” Yale Law Journal 93: 1197–1230.doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/796256

Witt, M. A., and G. Redding. 2009. The Spirits of Capitalism: German, Japanese, and US Senior Executive Perceptions of Why Firms Exist. Working Paper, 2009/61/EPS/EFE, INSEAD, Fontainebleau, France.

Wolff, J. 2000. “Libertarianism.” Concise Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. London: Routledge, 487–488.