Top Banner

of 11

Said an Ethics of Language - Said on Foucault

Jun 01, 2018

Download

Documents

Jack Sidnell
Welcome message from author
This document is posted to help you gain knowledge. Please leave a comment to let me know what you think about it! Share it to your friends and learn new things together.
Transcript
  • 8/9/2019 Said an Ethics of Language - Said on Foucault

    1/11

    An Ethics of Language

    The Archeology of Knowledge and The Discourse on Language by Michel FoucaultReview by: Edward SaidDiacritics, Vol. 4, No. 2 (Summer, 1974), pp. 28-37Published by: The Johns Hopkins University PressStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/464989 .

    Accessed: 24/01/2015 17:13

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

     .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of 

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

     .

    The Johns Hopkins University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to

     Diacritics.

    http://www.jstor.org

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=jhuphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/464989?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/464989?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=jhup

  • 8/9/2019 Said an Ethics of Language - Said on Foucault

    2/11

    Michel

    Foucault. The

    Archeology

    of

    Knowledge

    and

    The

    Discourse on Lan-

    guage.

    New York:

    Pantheon

    Books,

    1972.

    Since

    the

    publication

    of

    Les

    Mots et les

    choses

    (the

    title of its

    1971

    English

    translation

    is

    The Or-

    der

    of

    Things)

    in

    1966,

    Foucault's work has

    been

    revisionist

    in

    character

    and concern.

    For not

    only

    have his

    three

    essays

    on

    Nietzsche

    and

    Deleuze,

    his

    two

    later books

    L'Archdologie

    du

    savoir,

    and

    L'Ordre

    du

    discours,'

    all

    been

    about thinkers

    and

    thought,

    revising,

    reordering,

    reinterpreting

    what had

    been

    written,

    ordered

    and

    interpreted

    differently

    from

    them;

    but also

    Foucault

    now

    turned

    his

    thought

    back towards

    his own

    previous

    work. Thus

    it

    appeared

    in 1969

    that The Order

    of

    Things

    and

    Madness

    and

    Civilization

    had

    tried

    "to

    measure

    the

    mutations

    that

    operate

    in

    general

    in

    the field

    of his-

    tory;

    an

    enterprise

    in

    which

    the

    methods,

    limits,

    and

    themes

    proper

    to

    the

    history

    of ideas are

    questioned;

    an enterprise by which one tries to throw off the last

    anthropological

    constraints

    [.

    .

    .].

    These

    tasks

    were

    outlined

    [in

    those two

    earlier

    books]

    in a rather

    dis-

    ordered

    way,

    and

    their

    general

    articulation

    was

    never

    clearly

    defined"

    (p.

    15).

    Also

    part

    of

    this

    revisionist

    phase

    has been Foucault's disenchantment

    with the

    idea of an

    author,

    a

    concept

    he

    has

    found

    grossly

    incapable

    of

    dealing

    with

    the

    trans-personal

    authority

    of texts

    and

    documents.

    To

    revise

    has

    not

    meant

    to

    change

    opinions

    about which

    authors are more

    sig-

    nificant than

    others,

    although

    one can assume

    that

    that

    too

    has

    happened

    to Foucault.

    To revise

    for

    him has

    meant

    primarily

    to understand

    more

    closely

    the

    pro-

    cess of

    knowledge,

    its

    formation,

    dispersion,

    trans-

    mission and

    permanence,

    in

    terms

    of

    "anonymous

    rules" that are extremely precise and specialized.

    Moreover

    he

    has

    been

    at

    pains

    to show that

    during

    the

    course

    of this

    understanding

    he

    has been released

    not

    only

    from

    obligations

    to

    the

    history

    of

    ideas,

    but

    also

    from the

    conventional

    biography

    of

    great

    men

    and

    the

    narration of

    important

    events.

    All

    told

    then

    a

    good

    deal

    of

    Foucault's

    revision

    has been

    negative,

    and his

    description

    of

    those

    anonymous

    rules

    is fre-

    quently

    an itemized

    list

    of what

    they

    are

    not. Usu-

    ally,

    however,

    the

    negatives

    are

    pronounced

    against

    what

    he

    refers

    to as

    anthropology,

    which

    is the

    very

    thing

    that

    Nietzsche had called

    anthropomorphism:

    the

    habit

    of

    making

    all

    knowledge

    in

    the

    image

    of

    man

    or, worse,

    making every

    item

    of

    knowledge

    re-

    ducible

    to

    an

    original

    human act

    without

    which

    the

    item would otherwise have no cognitive status.

    Foucault's self-revision

    is

    theoretically

    consis-

    tent with one of the

    principal

    themes

    of his histor-

    ical

    research,

    the

    disappearance

    in

    contemporary

    knowledge

    of man's

    role as central

    subject,

    author

    and

    actor.

    But

    why

    not also

    practically

    consistent?

    Because Foucault

    is,

    as I have elsewhere

    said,

    far

    too

    clearly

    the

    unusually impressive

    author

    of his

    work. This is an

    unhesitating compliment

    to him

    as

    a

    stylist

    of

    thought,

    yet

    I

    intend it also as a

    way

    of

    Edward

    Said,

    Professor of

    English

    and

    Comparative

    Lit-

    erature at

    Columbia,

    is

    teaching

    at Harvard this

    year.

    Edward Said

    J i r T It

    O

    I L G Q J ( J

    making

    very

    doubtful his

    theoretical

    ambition

    to

    find

    himself,

    as

    he

    would

    like,

    "on the other

    side

    of

    discourse."

    An

    anonymous

    writer he

    clearly

    is

    not.

    Nevertheless

    the

    ambition

    to write

    as

    if

    from the

    standpoint

    of

    anonymous

    rules

    has been worth main-

    taining

    since,

    according

    to

    Foucault,

    he

    now knows

    that

    discourse

    "is

    made

    up

    of

    a

    limited number

    of

    statements for which a group of conditions of exis-

    tence can

    be

    defined."

    Among

    these conditions an

    author is

    not

    necessarily

    one

    of

    the most

    important.

    To

    understand this

    we

    need

    only

    recall that Freud's

    account of

    the

    Unconscious

    and its

    behavior

    is

    not

    completely

    dependent

    for its

    intelligibility upon

    the

    neurotic

    patient.

    The author of neurotic

    thoughts

    does not

    authorize,

    except

    in

    a

    limited

    way,

    the

    en-

    tire

    system

    of

    coherence

    by

    which

    his

    thoughts

    can

    be understood.

    Similarly,

    Marx's

    description

    of ide-

    ology envisages

    no

    particular

    individual;

    as

    a

    philo-

    sophic

    idea

    it has

    a

    force

    (in

    Marxist

    discourse)

    that

    need not

    always

    be referred back to

    Marx's

    biogra-

    phy.

    "Discourses are

    composed

    of

    signs;

    but

    what

    they

    do

    is

    more than

    use

    these

    signs

    to

    designate

    things. It is this more that renders them irreducible

    to

    the

    language

    and to

    speech.

    It is this 'more'

    that

    we must reveal and

    describe"

    (p.

    49).

    The

    questions

    Foucault has

    been

    asking

    himself therefore are

    as

    i

    These last two works

    now

    appear

    together

    in

    English

    as The

    Archeology

    of

    Knowledge

    &

    The Discourse

    on

    Language.

    The

    first,

    whose

    French

    original

    appeared

    in

    1969,

    is translated

    by

    M.

    Sheridan

    Smith,

    and

    the sec-

    ond,

    which

    originally

    appeared

    in

    1971,

    is

    translated--

    less

    carefully-by Rupert Swyer.

    Unless

    otherwise

    noted,

    page

    references

    appended parenthetically

    to

    quotations

    from

    Foucault are

    taken

    from

    this one

    volume

    of

    two

    translations.

    This content downloaded from 142.150.248.14 on Sat, 24 Jan 2015 17:13:19 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Said an Ethics of Language - Said on Foucault

    3/11

    follows: can

    one describe intellectual

    production

    without

    stopping

    the

    description

    at

    terminals

    like

    author,

    Zeitgeist,

    period,

    texts,

    ideas or

    language?

    What

    gives

    written

    language

    a

    recognizable imprimt

    6ver

    and

    above

    the

    signature

    of its author? What in

    short is

    the

    regularity

    of

    language

    in

    use

    in

    relation

    to

    which

    an author is a

    kind of

    eruptive

    irregularity?

    In

    raising

    these

    questions

    Foucault,

    I

    suspect,

    would

    prefer

    to

    be

    called

    a teacher

    rather than

    an

    author,

    because

    a teacher

    exposes knowledge directly

    before his students, he frees "a coherent domain of

    description"

    for and

    with

    his

    students.

    The

    more

    Foucault's

    work

    increases

    in

    volume

    and

    authority

    the

    more

    he

    has

    agitated

    to

    diminish

    the

    author's

    prerogatives,

    the more also he has

    become

    a teacher

    who

    stands

    in

    "the field

    of

    coordination and sub-

    ordination

    of

    statements in which

    concepts appear,

    and

    are

    defined,

    applied

    and transformed"

    (pp.

    182-

    83).

    Nowhere does Foucault

    himself make the ex-

    plicit

    distinction

    between author

    and

    teacher,

    but

    it

    is

    a

    very

    useful one nonetheless.

    Primarily

    a teacher

    makes

    explicit

    what an author

    hides inside the

    flow-

    ing

    lines of his

    language: namely

    that

    knowledge

    is

    dispersion,

    strategy,

    formation,

    discontinuity.

    More-

    over

    the

    teacher's

    place

    of

    business

    is

    the

    class,

    a

    site of exteriority, whereas the author's locale, a

    page,

    is

    far

    less visible

    as

    activity

    (which

    it

    is),

    and

    much

    more

    his

    private property.

    All this

    is

    a

    political

    motif

    running

    through

    Foucault's

    Archeology

    as

    he

    turns

    the

    teacher's

    openness upon

    the author's

    ac-

    cumulated reserves

    of

    power.

    Class

    struggle

    within

    knowledge

    pits

    man-the-author as historian

    (whose

    security

    is

    "the

    destiny

    of

    rationality

    and

    the

    teleo -

    ogy

    of

    the

    sciences,

    the

    long,

    continuous

    labor

    of

    thought

    from

    period

    to

    period,

    the

    awakening

    and

    the

    progress

    of

    consciousness,

    its

    perpetual

    resump-

    tion of

    itself,

    the

    uncompleted,

    but

    uninterrupted

    movement

    of

    totalizations,

    the

    return

    to an

    ever-

    open

    source,

    and

    finally

    the historico-transcendental

    thematic,"

    p.

    39)

    against

    a

    revolutionary

    teacher

    whose

    vocabulary

    replaces history

    of ideas

    with

    "archeology,"

    documents

    with

    "monuments,"

    texts

    with

    "discourses,"

    language

    with

    "statements"

    (enonces).

    The teacher's aim

    is

    an

    attempt

    to

    reveal discursive

    practices

    in their com-

    plexity

    and

    density;

    to show

    that

    to

    speak

    is to do some-

    thing-something

    other

    than

    to

    express

    what

    one

    thinks;

    to

    translate what one

    knows,

    and

    something

    other

    than

    to

    play

    with

    the

    structures

    of

    a

    language

    (langue);

    to

    show

    that to add a statement to

    a

    pre-existing

    series

    of

    statements

    is

    to

    perform

    a

    complicated

    and

    costly ges-

    ture,

    which

    involves

    conditions

    (and

    not

    only

    a situa-

    tion,

    a

    context,

    and

    motives),

    and

    rules

    (not

    the

    logical

    and

    linguistic

    rules

    of

    construction);

    to show

    that a

    change in the order of discourse does not presuppose

    'new ideas,' a little invention and

    creativity, a different

    mentality,

    but transformations n a

    practice,

    perhaps

    also

    in

    neighboring practices,

    and in

    their common articula-

    tion.

    (p. 209)

    Thus

    the

    teacher

    deprives

    the

    sovereign subject

    (or

    cogito)

    "of

    the exclusive and instantaneous

    right"

    to

    change

    discourse.

    What

    has

    become more clear than

    ever

    in

    Foucault's

    revisionist assault

    upon

    scholarship

    is the

    particular

    will to

    knowledge pushing

    his work for-

    ward. On

    the one

    hand,

    in his most

    recent series of

    lectures

    at the

    College

    de

    France he has been

    study-

    ing

    the

    regular

    transformations which a

    "polymor-

    phous"

    appetite

    for

    knowledge

    can

    undergo;

    on

    the

    other

    hand,

    the

    trajectory

    of his own

    intellectual

    project

    has

    re-formed itself

    to

    accommodate

    certain

    actualities in research

    elucidated

    by

    his

    practice.

    I

    think

    it is

    imperative

    to

    understand

    that his

    vocabu-

    lary

    of

    working

    terms-monument,

    archeology,

    statement,

    discourse,

    etc.-is not

    a

    fussy

    way

    of

    de-

    claring

    his

    originality,

    but

    is rather a

    design

    to

    meet

    the actualities and the desires of will to knowledge

    in

    general,

    and his

    own search for

    knowledge

    in

    par-

    ticular. If

    his most recent work

    appears

    to

    be

    more

    explicitly political

    and

    revolutionary

    than the

    work

    that

    brought

    him

    great

    fame,

    then that

    is

    because,

    I

    think,

    he has

    only

    lately

    apprehended

    the latent

    pub-

    lic

    quality

    of his historical

    investigation

    in

    Madness

    and

    Civilization

    and The

    Order

    of

    Things.

    Probably

    the

    May

    1968

    events

    in

    Paris

    played

    a

    major

    role

    in

    bringing

    him out

    from behind

    his

    work: two

    espe-

    cially

    important

    and

    extended

    interviews,

    in

    which

    Foucault

    began

    to draw forth

    the

    political meaning

    of

    "archeology,"

    date from that

    period.

    One

    is

    "R6ponse

    'a

    une

    question," Esprit,

    No. 5

    (May

    1968),

    pp.

    850-74;

    the other is

    "R6ponse

    au

    Cercle

    d'6pis-

    t6mologie,"

    Cahiers

    pour l'analyse,

    9

    (Summer

    1968),

    pp.

    9-40.

    From

    then

    on,

    I

    believe that Foucault's

    inter-

    ests are dominated

    by

    a

    symptomatic

    group

    of

    pres-

    sures on him

    (one

    can

    just

    as

    well call

    them desires

    or condititons

    or

    obsessions).

    Taken

    all

    together

    these

    pressures

    have

    kept

    him

    responsible

    for

    the

    goals

    and

    the

    results

    of

    his

    research,

    and

    responsive

    to the

    encroachments on him

    of

    the

    academy,

    the

    community

    of

    radicals,

    the

    injustices

    of

    contempo-

    rary

    society,

    and his

    own

    popularity.

    The

    first

    of

    these

    pressures

    is the

    simplest

    to state and

    the

    hardest

    to deal with. It

    is the historian's need

    to see

    history

    as a mass of historical

    documents

    intended,

    necessi-

    tated, by certain condititons, not as chance produc-

    tions

    willed into

    existence

    by

    the flukes

    of

    genius

    or time.

    An

    intellectual

    rejection

    of

    the

    watery

    ra-

    tionale

    usually

    employed

    in

    determining

    the

    setting

    of a text in time and

    place,

    this

    pressure

    enables

    Foucault to

    search for

    rigor

    in

    explanation

    where

    none had

    been

    possible previously.

    Yet in

    order

    to

    resort

    neither

    to

    mechanically

    determinist

    explana-

    tions nor to

    simple

    causal

    arguments,

    Foucault

    re-

    draws

    the terrain in

    which,

    as

    a

    historian,

    he

    can

    function

    systematically.

    To

    asnwer

    the

    question

    why

    did X

    (not A)

    say

    Y

    (not

    B)

    on

    occasion

    Z

    (not W),

    X,

    Y, Z,

    A,

    B

    and W

    must

    be

    re-defined

    as

    belonging

    wholly

    to an

    historically

    and

    particularly

    apprehensible

    or-

    der. This order Foucault calls discourse. Hence:

    "The

    question

    posed by

    language analysis

    of

    some

    discursive fact

    or other is

    always:

    according

    to what

    rules has

    a

    particular

    statement been

    made,

    and con-

    sequently

    according

    to what

    rules could other

    sim-

    ilar

    statements

    be made? The

    description

    of the

    events of discourse

    poses

    a

    quite

    different

    question:

    how is it

    that

    one

    particular

    statement

    appeared

    rather than

    another?"

    (p.

    27).

    Obviously

    statement

    is

    the

    key

    word

    here,

    and

    consequently,

    as we shall

    see,

    Foucault

    must make the

    nature

    of

    the statement

    coherent both

    from the

    standpoint

    of

    its

    retrospec-

    diacritics/Summer

    974

    This content downloaded from 142.150.248.14 on Sat, 24 Jan 2015 17:13:19 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Said an Ethics of Language - Said on Foucault

    4/11

    tive historical

    analysis

    and of its

    rationally

    intel-

    ligible

    method of

    production.

    However

    the

    place

    of

    discourse,

    its

    setting,

    in which

    statements

    occur,

    is

    specified by

    Foucault as the

    archive. The retrieval

    of

    the archive from

    its own time and

    place

    in the

    past

    and

    its

    description

    is

    what,

    with

    only

    the most

    unavoidable

    geological analogy

    intended,

    he

    calls

    archeology.

    The next pressure has already been implied in

    my

    initial definition of discourse

    and archive.

    Par-

    adoxically history

    no

    longer

    can

    be

    conceived

    of

    as

    a

    domain which

    is

    entirely,

    or

    even

    mainly, temporal

    (if

    by

    time one

    means,

    generally,

    the

    linear

    succes-

    sion of dates and

    events).

    Foucault

    begins

    The

    Archeology

    of

    Knowledge

    with a

    stocktaking

    of the

    extent

    to

    which recent

    historical research

    is about

    "the

    great

    silent,

    motionless bases

    that

    traditional

    history

    has covered

    with a

    thick

    layer

    of

    events"

    (p.

    3).

    To

    uncover

    those bases

    is

    to

    admit

    that

    an

    "epistemological

    mutation" has

    overtaken

    the

    study.

    of

    history.

    Its essential

    point

    is

    what Foucault

    and

    others have

    called

    decentering,

    which

    is fundamen-

    tally opposed

    to

    anthropological

    and

    humanistic

    at-

    tempts

    to

    write

    total

    history

    radiating

    out

    from man.

    For

    the new

    kind of

    history

    there

    is no

    quasi-divine

    archi,

    or

    telos,

    no

    Weltanschauung,

    no

    smug

    con-

    tinuity,

    no

    immobile

    structures

    necessarily

    to

    be

    found

    in

    it. The effects

    of

    ethnology,

    linguistics,

    psy-

    choanalysis,

    and

    generally

    of

    Nietzschean

    interpre-

    tation have been

    to

    dissolve

    the

    priority

    of

    these

    given

    calendars

    which

    supposedly

    typify

    time.

    Rather

    the historian

    must now write

    general

    history:

    "a total

    description

    draws

    all

    phenomena

    around

    a

    single

    centre-a

    principle,

    a

    meaning,

    a

    spirit,

    a

    world-

    view,

    an overall

    shape;

    a

    general

    history,

    on the

    con-

    trary,

    would

    deploy

    the

    space

    of a

    dispersion"

    (p.

    10).

    How else

    is

    one

    to

    deal

    with

    such

    questions

    as

    the "apparently unmoving histories" of "sea routes

    [...]

    of

    corn or

    of

    gold-mining

    [...]

    of

    drought

    and

    of

    irrigation

    [...] crop

    rotation

    [...]

    of the

    balance

    achieved

    by

    the

    human

    species

    between

    hunger

    and

    abundance"

    (p.

    3)?

    No

    longer

    is the

    historian

    simply

    to link

    events

    in a

    causal

    series;

    he

    must

    now

    ask

    about

    different

    sorts of

    series,

    new

    criteria

    of

    period-

    ization,

    differently

    articulated

    systems

    of

    relation

    between

    series.

    Dates,

    by

    which

    a

    sequential

    calendar

    miming

    the

    line

    of a

    man's life

    was

    formerly

    con-

    structed and

    given priority,

    acquire

    diminished

    and

    qualified

    significance.

    Recurrent

    distributions

    and

    architectonic

    unities,

    displacements

    and

    transforma-

    tions-these

    are

    the

    spatial

    indicators

    of historical

    activity

    today,

    and

    it

    is

    Foucault's

    goal

    to formulate

    a method sensitive to these indicators.

    But the

    linear

    image

    of

    time,

    based on the se-

    quential

    calendar

    of a man's

    life,

    is itself abetted

    by

    "two models

    that have

    for so

    long

    imposed

    their

    image:

    the

    linear model

    of

    speech

    (and

    partly

    at

    least of

    writing)

    in which all events succeed one

    an-

    other,

    without

    any

    effect

    of coincidence and

    super-

    position;

    and

    the model

    of the stream of conscious-

    ness

    whose

    presence

    always

    eludes itself in its

    open-

    ness

    to

    the future

    and

    its retention

    of the

    past" (p.

    169).

    It

    is to break

    the

    hold of these models

    that

    Foucault

    describes

    discourse and

    archive,

    with

    their

    own

    forms

    of

    sequence

    and succession. Here we

    come

    to the

    third

    and the most

    complex

    pressure up-

    on the new

    method. For

    just

    as

    history

    is not

    tem-

    poral

    sequence,

    because

    the

    birth-to-death

    span

    of

    man's

    life

    is

    an

    adequate

    measure neither

    of

    large

    units

    like

    demographic expansion,

    of

    phenomena

    of

    rupture,

    discontinuity,

    coincidence,

    and

    complemen-

    tarity,

    so too

    the

    spatial dispersion

    enacted

    by

    his-

    tory

    cannot be filled with

    objects

    that are

    analogies

    (disguised

    or

    not)

    or

    direct unmediated

    representa-

    tions of human life. Textual evidence, in other

    words,

    is

    based

    on historical

    documents,

    but these

    documents are

    formed and

    persist

    monumentally,

    according

    to

    their own

    laws,

    and

    not

    according

    to a

    human

    image.

    A

    text

    does

    not

    simply

    record-is

    not

    the

    pure

    graphological

    consequence

    of-an

    im-

    mediate desire

    to

    write. Rather it distributes

    various

    textual

    impulses, regularly

    and on

    several

    axes;

    what

    gives

    these

    impulses

    unity

    is

    what Foucault

    calls

    a

    discursive

    formation,

    bound

    neither

    by

    an

    individual

    author,

    a

    "period,"

    a

    "work,"

    nor an idea.

    A

    text,

    to

    those who

    persist

    in

    making

    of a

    contingent

    print-

    ing

    device an

    ontological

    unit

    having

    final

    value,

    is a

    fundamentally

    inconstant

    epistemological

    judgment.

    The

    background

    for this

    more

    than

    simply

    relativist

    thought

    was

    first sketched

    in

    detail

    by

    Fou-

    cault in

    the

    final

    pages

    of

    The

    Order

    of

    Things.

    He

    remarked there how mimetic

    representation

    after

    such

    writers as

    Sade,

    Mallarm6

    and

    Nietzsche

    could

    convey

    neither

    their desires

    nor

    their

    psychological

    discoveries.

    Concurrently

    the

    logic

    of

    syntax

    as well

    as

    the linear

    sequence

    of

    printed language

    in

    their

    work is

    assaulted

    (and

    found

    wanting)

    by

    a

    wish to

    express

    non-syntactic, non-sequential

    thought.

    To-

    gether

    with

    these

    writers, Marx,

    Saussure

    and Freud

    put

    forward

    systems

    of

    thought

    for

    which no

    image

    was

    adequate.

    Thus

    writing

    could not have a

    predic-

    tive form

    based

    either

    upon biological growth

    or

    up-

    on

    a

    representative governing image.

    Instead

    writing

    sought to constitute its own realm, inhabited entirely

    by

    words and

    the

    spaces

    between

    them. In turn

    the

    relations between

    this

    realm

    and

    empirical reality

    were made

    possible

    according

    to

    particular strategies

    and

    enunciative functions. What

    ideas one

    has about

    a text therefore

    change

    definitively

    as one examines

    a novel

    by Virginia

    Woolf,

    or

    a textbook

    of

    organic

    chemistry,

    or a

    political pamphlet,

    all

    dating

    from

    roughly

    the same

    period.

    The

    Archeology

    of

    Knowledge

    takes the

    pro-

    cess

    of

    defining

    the realms of

    language

    and

    "reality"

    commonly

    known

    by

    all

    three

    such

    "texts"

    a

    step

    closer to formalization. The

    vocabulary

    and

    the

    problematics

    of that

    kind

    of

    knowledge

    are articu-

    lated

    by

    Foucault with the

    principle negative

    aim of

    avoiding descriptions equivalent to, or understand-

    able in terms

    of,

    sense

    impressions.

    Since

    no

    image

    is

    capable

    of

    containing knowledge-formal

    knowl-

    edge

    cannot be

    immediately

    seen,

    heard, smelled,

    felt,

    or tasted-it

    can

    neither

    be

    produced

    nor

    sought

    after

    (desired)

    in the

    simple experiential

    terms

    of

    daily

    life. The

    will to

    knowledge expresses

    itself

    in

    what Foucault

    calls an

    element

    of

    rarity

    very special

    to it. Hence the

    pertinence

    of Foucault's

    choice

    of

    savoir over

    connaissance

    (English regrettably

    trans-

    lates both

    as

    knowledge)

    for the

    object

    of his

    study:

    the former is unthinkable without reference to condi-

    tions and

    appropriations

    that make it

    knowledge,

    the

    latter-as

    Foucault

    says

    in a

    summary

    of his

    1970-

    This content downloaded from 142.150.248.14 on Sat, 24 Jan 2015 17:13:19 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Said an Ethics of Language - Said on Foucault

    5/11

    71 course of

    lectures at

    the

    Collkge-is

    best

    studied

    as

    something

    fundamentally

    subjective

    and

    selfish

    (interessde),

    produced

    as an event

    of desire

    (produite

    comme

    evenement du

    vouloir),

    and

    determining

    truth

    by

    falsification

    (determinant

    par falsification

    l'eflet

    de

    vdritd).

    Therefore

    knowledge

    (savoir)

    is that of which

    one

    can

    speak

    in

    a

    discursive

    practice,

    and

    which is

    specified

    by

    that fact: the domain

    consti-

    tuted

    by

    the

    different

    objects

    that

    will

    or will not

    acquire

    a scientific status

    (the knowledge

    of

    psychiatry

    in

    the

    nineteenth century is not the sum of what was thought

    to be

    true,

    but

    the

    whole

    set

    of

    practices, singularities,

    and

    deviations

    of

    which

    one

    could

    speak

    in

    psychiatric

    discourse);

    knowledge

    is also

    the

    space

    in

    which the

    subject may

    take

    up

    a

    position

    and

    speak

    of the

    objects

    with

    which he

    deals

    in

    his

    discourse

    (in

    this

    sense,

    the

    knowledge

    of clinical

    medicine

    is

    the whole

    group

    of

    functions

    of

    observations,

    interrogation, decipherment,

    recording

    and

    decision that

    may

    be exercised

    by

    the

    sub-

    ject

    of

    medical

    discourse); knowledge

    is

    also the field

    of coordination and subordinationof statements n

    which

    concepts appear,

    and are

    defined,

    applied

    and

    trans-

    formed

    (at

    this

    level,

    the

    knowledge

    of Natural

    History,

    in the

    eighteenth

    century,

    is

    not the

    sum of

    what was

    said,

    but

    the

    whole set of

    modes

    and

    sites

    in

    accordance

    with

    which

    one

    can

    integrate

    new

    statement

    with the

    already said); lastly, knowledge is defined by the possi-

    bilities of use and

    appropriation

    offered

    by

    discourse

    (thus,

    the

    knowledge

    of

    political

    economy,

    in

    the Clas-

    sical

    period,

    is

    not

    the

    thesis

    of the different

    theses sus-

    tained,

    but the

    totality

    of its

    point

    of

    articulation

    on

    other discourses or

    on

    other

    practices

    that are not dis-

    cursive).

    There are bodies

    of

    knowledge

    that are inde-

    pendent

    of the

    sciences

    (which

    are

    neither their

    histor-

    ical

    prototypes,

    nor their

    practical by-products),

    but

    there is no

    knowledge

    without

    a

    particular

    discursive

    practice;

    and

    any

    discursive

    practice may

    be defined

    by

    the

    knowledge

    that

    it

    forms.

    (pp.

    182-83)

    Knowledge

    is

    specified

    by

    discourse,

    and

    vice

    versa.

    The

    tautology

    does not

    matter,

    if

    only

    be-

    cause

    what it

    thereby

    banished

    is

    a

    conception

    of

    knowledge as the free-floating, spontaneous emana-

    tion of

    genius

    and/or individual

    hard

    work. Fou-

    cault is not

    the first

    modern to

    attack

    this romantic-

    ally

    humanist vision

    of

    knowledge, although

    I think

    he

    does more to

    regularize

    the

    irregularities

    of

    knowledge,

    to

    specify

    knowledge

    that

    is,

    than most

    others.

    The

    importance

    of

    the attack has

    gone

    far

    too

    long

    unnoticed,

    however,

    especially

    in

    the

    United

    States. In

    the first

    place

    romantic

    knowledge

    (con-

    naissance),

    signifies

    property quite

    narrowly,

    the

    property

    of the

    big

    brain

    whose

    inspiration

    knowl-

    edge

    therefore seems.

    Secondly

    it

    is

    antidemocratic,

    not in

    any

    vague

    counter-culture

    sense,

    but rather

    in

    the sense

    that

    permits

    its votaries to wave

    the

    ban-

    ner of

    science and

    knowledge

    and,

    at the

    same time

    to conceal the privilege-but not the rigor or real

    science,

    which

    are absent-that

    entitles them

    to

    act

    as

    thought-producers.

    In March

    1972 Foucault be-

    gan

    explicitly

    to

    speak

    of

    an

    interplay

    of

    desire,

    power

    and interest

    as

    being

    the

    radical intellectual

    target

    in

    the

    struggle

    to uncover

    the hidden

    strategies

    of

    social

    power

    (L'Arc,

    number

    49,

    p.

    9).

    The con-

    tinuity

    between such a

    statement and

    Foucault's

    at-

    tack

    upon

    anti-democratic

    epistemology

    in

    The

    Archeology

    is

    plain.

    Thirdly,

    and this

    realization I

    believe

    is

    necessitated

    by

    the first

    two,

    romantic

    knowledge

    is

    anti-intellectual and

    anti-rational. Yet

    nowhere

    does

    Foucault

    say

    as a result

    that

    knowl-

    edge

    (savoir)

    is

    immediately

    accessible to

    introspec-

    tion,

    to

    direct

    questioning,

    or

    even

    to

    consciousness.

    What

    he does

    say

    is

    that

    knowledge

    is

    produced,

    dis-

    seminated and

    reformed

    in

    ways

    that can be

    intelligi-

    bly

    specified

    and

    characterized,

    albeit with

    difficulty.

    In one or two

    places

    Foucault

    carefully

    distinguishes

    between his

    archeological

    method and

    Chomsky's

    methods

    (never

    mentioned

    by

    name)

    of

    linguistic

    analysis

    based

    upon

    the

    generative

    model.

    While

    both theories appear to have a strong libertarian

    thrust,

    archeology,

    by

    seizing,

    out of the mass

    of

    things

    said,

    upon

    the

    statement defined as

    a

    function

    of realization of

    the

    verbal

    performance, distinguishes

    itself from a

    search

    whose

    privileged

    field is

    linguistic competence:

    while

    such

    a

    description

    constitutes a

    generative

    model,

    in order

    to

    define the

    acceptability

    of

    statements,

    archeology

    tries

    to

    establish rules of

    formation,

    in order to

    define

    the

    con-

    dition of their realization.

    (p.

    207)

    The

    opacity

    of

    this

    disclaimer

    thins

    out

    a

    bit

    if

    it

    is

    read with the

    following,

    earlier,

    passage

    in

    mind:

    "it is

    vain to

    seek,

    beyond

    structural,

    formal,

    or in-

    terpretative

    analyses

    of

    language,

    a domain

    that is

    at

    last

    freed from all

    positivity,

    in which the

    freedom

    of

    the

    subject,

    the labour of

    the human

    being,

    or

    the

    opening up

    of

    a transcendental

    destiny

    could

    be ful-

    filled"

    (p.

    112).

    Positivity

    and

    specification:

    these

    make

    up

    the

    tough,

    almost

    material,

    rind of

    knowledge.

    Yet like

    an

    archive

    (as

    understood

    conventionally) they

    are

    not

    wholly corporeal

    either,

    for

    they

    inhabit a

    spe-

    cial

    medium

    of

    rarity. Mainly,

    positive

    and

    specifi-

    able

    knowledge

    is

    regular,

    it absorbs

    discontinuity

    and

    individual

    effort,

    it

    conceals its

    structure,

    it is

    eminently capable

    of

    being

    there,

    even

    if

    it

    is not

    visible,

    and it

    is

    repeatable.

    This is

    not as

    unimag-

    inable a

    constellation

    of features as its

    seems.

    Fou-

    cault has assembled

    together

    various

    characteriza-

    tions made by other writers, some of whom he names

    and

    acknowledges,

    others

    he

    probably

    did

    not

    have

    in

    mind. It is

    a useful

    exercise to

    describe a few

    of

    these correlative

    discoveries made

    by

    others.

    They

    have the

    virtue

    of

    placing

    Foucault

    against

    a

    rela-

    tively

    familiar

    background

    where,

    if

    my

    irony

    is not

    mis-interpreted,

    the almost

    oppressively

    novel

    vocab-

    ulary

    of his

    methodology

    itself

    seems

    more

    regular.

    Nevertheless

    one

    must

    note

    that Foucault's own

    thought

    about

    originality

    is

    highly

    ambivalent.

    I

    shall

    return to that

    critical

    problem

    a

    little later.

    One

    brings

    Foucault

    together

    with

    Thomas S.

    Kuhn,

    Georges

    Canguilhem

    and Michael

    Polanyi

    only

    with

    trepidation.

    Nevertheless I have

    ventured

    to do so

    and find

    the

    attempt

    instructive. All of

    these writers on the structure of scientific knowledge

    stress

    the

    regularity

    of

    that

    knowledge,

    that

    is,

    the

    shared

    paradigms

    discussed

    by

    Kuhn that

    comprise

    a

    "research

    consensus." This

    consensus enables further

    research,

    accommodates or is

    radically

    altered

    by

    anomaly,

    and

    always,

    according

    to

    Kuhn,

    performs

    the function of

    providing

    in

    ongoing

    time

    "a

    new

    and

    more

    rigid

    definition of

    the

    field"

    of scientific

    research. "Men

    whose

    research

    is

    based on

    shared

    paradigms

    are

    committed to

    the same rules and

    standards

    for scientific

    practice.

    That

    commitment

    and the

    apparent

    consensus it

    produces

    are

    prereq-

    diacritics

    Summer

    974

    This content downloaded from 142.150.248.14 on Sat, 24 Jan 2015 17:13:19 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Said an Ethics of Language - Said on Foucault

    6/11

    uisites for

    normal

    science,

    i.e.

    for

    the

    genesis

    and

    continuation of a

    particular

    research tradition"

    (The

    Structure

    of

    Scientific

    Revolutions.

    Chicago:

    Univ.

    of

    Chicago

    Press,

    rev. ed.

    1970;

    p.

    11).

    If new

    problems

    emerge

    as anomalies

    it

    is

    because

    they

    are

    in

    disharmony

    with "the

    background provided

    by

    the

    paradigm"

    (p.

    65).

    Within the

    paradigm,

    as

    Canguilhem

    showed

    in a

    very

    early study

    that

    pre-

    dates Kuhn's Scientific Revolutions by nineteen

    years,

    criteria are formed

    in

    medicine,

    for

    instance,

    that

    determine

    "the

    normal"

    and

    "the

    pathological."

    He

    concludes

    that

    "every empirical concept

    of illness

    retains a

    disciplined

    relation

    with

    an

    axiological

    con-

    cept

    of

    illness.

    Consequently

    it

    is

    not an

    objective

    method that characterizes

    a

    biological phenomenon

    as

    pathological.

    It

    is

    always

    the relation between ob-

    server

    and

    individual

    patient,

    mediated

    by

    the

    clinic,

    which

    justifies

    the label

    pathological"

    (Le

    Normal

    et

    le

    pathologique.

    Paris:

    P.

    U.

    F.,

    rev.

    ed.

    1962;

    p.

    156).

    Canguilhem dispels

    the

    subjectivist

    fallacy

    by

    saying

    that there

    is

    such

    a

    thing

    as

    objective path-

    ology

    so

    long

    as

    it

    is

    understood

    first

    that

    that

    objec-

    tivity

    is

    absolutely

    tied to a

    specific

    biological

    history

    (with

    its own time, events,

    sequence,

    sociology,

    or-

    der)

    and

    second,

    that

    the

    object

    of

    objective path-

    ological practice

    "is

    not

    so much a fact as

    a

    value"

    (p.

    157).

    In 1966

    Canguilhem

    refined

    this view

    by

    say-

    ing

    that within a

    science

    like

    pathology

    there

    are

    norms

    that

    regulate

    even

    the

    concept

    of

    error. Thus

    "health

    is

    a

    genetic

    and

    enzymatic

    correction

    of

    an

    error

    [in

    the

    substitution

    of

    one

    molecular

    arrange-

    ment

    for another:

    the

    conceptual

    structure of

    bio-

    chemistry

    here

    is

    borrowed

    from information-

    theory].

    To be

    sick

    is

    to

    have been

    wrong,

    wrong

    not

    in the sense

    of

    a

    counterfeit

    note

    in the sense

    of

    a

    false

    brother,

    but

    in the sense

    of a mistaken fold

    of

    the page, or of a wrong line of verse" (Canguil-

    hem,

    p.

    208).

    In

    Personal

    Knowledge (Chicago:

    Univ.

    of

    Chicago

    Press, 1958)-to

    which Kuhn

    re-

    fers-and

    in

    his

    Lindsay

    Memorial

    Lectures,

    The

    Study

    of

    Man

    (Chicago:

    Univ.

    of

    Chicago

    Press,

    1959),

    Polanyi

    demonstrates

    that

    what he calls

    tacit

    knowledge

    can be

    incorporated,

    and

    is indeed

    an

    important

    part

    of what

    passes

    for

    "objective"

    scien-

    tific

    research.

    Tacit

    knowledge

    need

    not be

    immedi-

    ately

    formulable

    in a set

    of

    rules;

    nonetheless it

    is

    consentual

    and works

    as

    a

    basis

    upon

    which

    scien-

    tific

    research

    conducts

    itself. The

    point

    is that

    even

    the

    apparently

    contradictory

    status of

    explicit

    and

    implicit

    knowledge,

    as well

    as the

    discontinuity

    be-

    tween

    them,

    does

    not inhibit

    the

    regularity

    of

    the

    whole body of scientific knowledge at any given

    time.

    Kuhn's brilliant

    analysis

    of the

    role

    played

    by

    textbooks in

    contributing

    to the scientific

    par-

    adigm

    stands

    in a

    fairly

    close

    relation to

    Foucault's

    account of

    discursive

    practice

    "as a

    body

    of

    anon-

    ymous,

    historical

    rules,

    always

    determined

    in the

    time

    and

    space

    that have

    defined a

    given

    period,

    and

    for a

    given

    social,

    economic,

    geographical,

    or

    lin-

    guistic

    area,

    the

    conditions

    of

    operation

    of the enun-

    ciative

    function"

    (p.

    117).

    Foucault's

    archeology

    of

    knowledge

    scants

    the

    difference

    between

    science,

    social science and

    hu-

    manities.

    All of these divisions are

    subject

    to

    the

    laws of discursive

    practice,

    and the relations

    between

    them

    are

    equally

    a

    function

    of

    these

    laws.

    If

    from

    the

    "archeological"

    historian's

    viewpoint,

    a

    society

    can be

    studied as

    a

    quasi-transcendental

    form of dis-

    course

    (I

    adapt

    this

    notion

    from

    Angus

    Fletcher's

    theory

    of a

    transcendental

    art-form in his The

    Tran-

    scendental

    Masque:

    An

    Essay

    on Milton's

    "Comus."

    Ithaca:

    Cornell

    Univ.

    Press,

    1972),

    then

    the intra-

    social

    exclusions

    and

    incorporations

    that

    comprise

    the penal system, the organization of university cur-

    ricula,

    the

    structure of

    the

    political

    bureaucracy,

    in-

    sofar

    as

    these

    are

    coherent

    positivities,

    are discursive

    practices,

    too.

    Thus a

    positvity

    is

    that

    acted-upon

    knowledge

    which

    can

    be

    rationally

    ascertained

    and

    articulated,

    no

    matter

    how

    implicit

    or

    hidden it

    may

    first

    appear

    to be.

    The

    more one

    reads

    in

    Foucault

    the

    more one

    notices

    the

    extent

    to

    which

    he

    is sus-

    picious

    of,

    and

    attracted

    to,

    knowledge

    whose

    prac-

    tice

    conceals the

    fact

    of

    its

    fabrication.

    He

    has this

    in

    common

    obviously

    with

    a

    number of

    modern

    thinkers,

    of

    whom

    Barthes

    the

    structuralist,

    Lukics

    and

    Adorno,

    the

    neo-Marxists,

    furnish

    the

    most

    directly

    relevant

    analogies.

    Barthes'

    anatomy

    of

    myth

    (in

    Mythologies)

    construes

    the

    bourgeois

    habit

    of appeals to immutable

    "reality"

    as a form of illu-

    sionment,

    by

    which

    what is

    present

    is

    falsely

    given

    as

    not-made and

    always-there.

    Lukics'

    definition

    of

    proletarian

    class-consciousness also

    demonstrates

    how

    the

    bourgeois

    status-quo

    masks a

    discourse

    or

    a

    theory

    that

    denies

    its

    own

    self-preserving

    activity.

    And

    Adorno,

    whose

    philosophical

    investigations

    of

    contemporary reality

    play

    an

    important

    role

    in Fred-

    eric

    Jameson's

    excellent

    Marxism and

    Form

    (Prince-

    ton:

    Princeton Univ.

    Press,

    1972),

    equates

    the

    so-

    called

    autonomy

    of a

    work

    of art

    in

    class

    society

    with

    the

    class-derived

    concealment of

    work:

    Works

    of art owe their

    existence to

    the social

    division

    of

    labor,

    to

    the

    separation

    of

    mental and

    physical

    work.

    In such a situation, however, they appear under the

    guise

    of

    independent

    existence;

    for

    their medium

    is not

    that of

    pure

    and autonomous

    spirit,

    but

    rather

    that of

    a

    spirit

    which

    having

    become

    object

    now

    claims

    to have

    surmounted the

    opposition

    between

    the two. Such

    con-

    tradiction

    obliges

    the

    work

    of

    art

    to

    conceal

    the

    fact

    that

    it is

    itself a human

    construction.

    (p. 408)

    Jameson

    continues Adorno's

    argument

    as

    follows:

    "There

    is thus

    given

    within

    the

    very concept

    of work

    -either in

    the form

    of

    the

    division of labor in

    gen-

    eral

    or in

    the more

    specialized

    types

    of

    production

    characteristic of

    capitalism-the

    principle

    of a cen-

    sorship

    of

    the

    work

    process

    itself,

    of a

    repression

    of

    the

    traces

    of

    labor on the

    product."

    Yet if

    the work

    process

    is

    not to remain

    occult,

    a certain order must be assumed for it. How, if one

    does not

    wish to

    employ

    crude sensationalist meta-

    phors,

    can

    one

    depict

    rational

    work as

    a

    process

    hav-

    ing significant

    material

    consequences?

    How does one

    deal with

    the

    problem

    of

    showing

    discourse

    in its

    persistence

    to be

    what Foucault

    has called a

    material-

    istic

    incorporeal?

    Val6ry's

    Leonardo

    comes

    to

    mind

    here.

    What

    interests

    Val6ry

    in Leonardo

    is not

    his

    biography

    but

    his

    constructive

    power

    as

    a

    mind.

    Construction

    itself has its own

    logic

    whose

    basis

    is

    an

    "intervention

    in natural

    things."

    The initial

    step

    in

    a construction

    is

    a decision to move

    away

    from

    nature and into

    the

    constructive element.

    (There

    is

    an

    interesting study

    of Leonardo's use of

    sketches

    This content downloaded from 142.150.248.14 on Sat, 24 Jan 2015 17:13:19 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Said an Ethics of Language - Said on Foucault

    7/11

    that

    develops

    this

    theme

    further

    than

    Valry:

    E.

    H.

    Gombrich's

    "Leonardo's

    Method of

    Working

    out

    Compositions"

    in his

    Norm and

    Form:

    Studies

    in

    the

    Art

    of

    the

    Renaissance

    (London:

    Phaidon,

    1966).

    Thereafter

    Val6ry

    meditates

    upon

    Leonardo's

    architectural

    projections

    for

    monuments

    which,

    al-

    though

    they

    have no

    empirical equivalent,

    neverthe-

    less

    have

    a

    special

    empirical validity.

    Leonardo saw

    "the air

    [as

    being]

    full of

    infinite

    lines,

    straight

    and

    radiating,

    intercrossing,

    and

    interweaving

    without

    ever coinciding one with another." In this element of

    rarity

    Leonardo

    puts

    his

    monuments:

    The

    monument

    (which

    composes

    the

    City,

    which

    in turn is

    almost

    the whole

    of

    civilization)

    is

    such

    a

    com-

    plex

    entity

    that our

    understanding

    of

    it

    passes through

    several

    successive

    phases.

    First

    we

    grasp

    a

    changeable

    background

    that

    merges

    with

    the

    sky,

    then

    a

    rich

    tex-

    ture of motifs

    in

    height,

    breadth,

    and

    depth,

    infinitely

    varied

    by perspective,

    then

    something

    solid,

    bold,

    resis-

    tant,

    with

    certain

    animal

    characteristics-organs,

    mem-

    bers-then

    finally

    a

    machine

    having gravity

    for

    its

    mo-

    tive

    force,

    one that

    carries

    us

    in

    thought

    from

    geometry

    to

    dynamics

    and

    thence to the most

    tenuous

    speculations

    of

    molecular

    physics.

    (Valkry.

    Collected Works.

    Prince-

    ton:

    Princeton Univ.

    Press,

    1972;

    vol.

    III,

    pp.

    49-50)

    "In our time,"

    says

    Foucault,

    "history

    is that which

    transforms

    documents

    into

    monuments"

    (p.

    7).

    Val-

    6ry's

    account

    of the

    constructed monument corre-

    sponds

    to

    Foucault's

    concept

    of

    the duration

    in

    his-

    tory

    of

    texts as

    monument: the historian's

    discipline

    is

    archeology

    ("the

    intrinsic

    description

    of the

    monu-

    ment")

    which

    also

    passes

    through

    several

    successive

    phases.

    A

    document's

    monumentality

    can

    only

    emerge

    when

    discourse

    is not elided

    with

    reality.

    The

    time

    of its

    construction,

    the time

    of

    monumen-

    tal

    duration,

    the

    time

    of its

    analysis:

    these

    three are

    correlates

    that

    tend

    differently

    to

    repeat

    each

    other

    without

    being

    copies

    of

    nature

    or of

    an

    ideal.

    Monu-

    mentality

    is

    the

    general

    mode of

    presence

    of dis-

    course, although

    in

    the

    special

    sense of the word

    in-

    tended

    by

    Foucault

    (like

    Valery

    before

    him)

    monu-

    mental

    presence

    does not

    exclusively

    mean

    empirical

    visibility.

    A

    library,

    for

    instance,

    is

    one

    particular

    mode of

    presence

    for

    discourse

    as

    monument:

    as vis-

    ible

    objects

    the books in

    the

    stacks

    are less

    important

    than

    the

    infinitely

    interwined

    lines

    that

    connect

    the

    books

    to

    each

    other

    and

    keep

    the word on the

    pages.

    Moreover in

    the

    conception

    of

    books and

    language

    as a

    universe that

    Borges

    has

    made

    cur-

    rent,

    each

    discourse

    becomes

    a sort of

    cross-refer-

    ence to

    every

    other discourse. In such

    a universe

    there

    is

    no

    determinable

    origin

    and no final

    goal,

    since

    repetition

    underlies

    cross-reference. Foucault's

    philosophical

    affinity

    with Gilles

    Deleuze derives

    from this interest in repetition, although recently the

    affinity

    has

    become

    political

    as

    well.

    Deleuze's

    Dif-

    ference

    et

    repetition (Paris:

    P.

    U.

    F., 1968)

    goes

    a

    very long

    way

    towards

    laying

    forth a

    philosophy

    of

    repetition

    with which

    Foucault,

    whose

    recognition

    that

    there

    is

    no

    Origin

    is

    pre-supposed

    by

    his

    interest

    in

    repetition

    and

    discourse,

    has

    publicly agreed.

    What

    makes such

    comparative

    abstractions like dif-

    ference and

    repetition

    clear in

    Deleuze's otherwise

    very complex

    argument

    is his

    way

    of

    describing

    those

    things

    as

    forms of action.

    "Repetition

    [in

    time]

    is a condition of action

    before it becomes a

    concept

    of reflection"

    (Deleuze,

    p.

    21).

    Using examples

    from

    Marx,

    H61derlin,

    Vico,

    and

    Nietzsche,

    Deleuze

    con-

    structs before

    his

    reader the drama

    of

    repetition

    that

    is

    capable

    of

    producing

    the

    absolutely

    different.

    Aside from

    being

    an

    appealingly

    surprising

    volte-face,

    this

    argument

    reveals

    the

    extent

    to which

    repetition,

    as a device

    or a mode

    or a

    philosophic

    habit,

    is

    not

    the

    opposite

    of

    originality

    in the romantic

    sense

    of

    that

    word. If as

    a

    concept

    or a

    description, original-

    ity

    concealed an

    appeal

    to

    some

    extra-positive "priv-

    ilege" (the Muse, inspiration, a "raptus") it also

    contained

    an

    anxiety

    about the value of what

    one

    was

    saying.

    As

    Vico was

    one of the first to

    argue,

    all utterance

    is

    a

    form

    of

    re-inscription:

    hence

    orig-

    inality

    is

    a far more unstable

    quality.

    Instead,

    it

    and

    creativity

    belong

    inherently

    to what

    Harold

    Bloom

    calls

    misprision,

    one

    of whose

    signs

    is

    parody,

    the

    form of

    writing

    relied

    upon

    to a

    great

    extent

    by

    many

    of the modern

    masters like

    Eliot,

    Mann

    and

    Joyce.

    This

    deliberate

    mis-taking

    characterizes

    in-

    ventiveness.

    Far from

    being

    the

    -realization

    of

    an

    "interiority"

    like

    inspiration,

    discourse

    for

    Foucault

    is

    only misprision

    and

    exteriority:

    "it is

    a

    practical

    domain

    that

    is

    autonomous"

    (p.

    121).

    Therefore,

    "the time

    of discourse

    is not the

    translation,

    in

    a

    visible chronology, of the obscure time of thought"

    (p.

    121).

    Here we

    can

    begin

    to

    understand how

    repetition

    produces

    difference.

    Discursive

    language

    is

    like

    a

    repertory

    theatre

    that

    stages

    numerous

    spectacles.

    This

    figure

    connects

    Foucault

    with

    Kenneth

    Burke's dramatistic

    analysis

    of

    literature,

    although

    Foucault

    holds that

    discursive

    practice

    is neither

    benign

    nor

    necessarily

    artistic:

    effectiveness

    is its main criterion of

    success. Effec-

    tiveness can

    be

    judged

    in

    several

    ways

    but

    Foucault

    is

    right,

    I

    think,

    not

    to

    make

    effectiveness

    dependent

    upon

    so

    fickle

    a

    perception

    as

    the

    retrospective

    crit-

    ic's.

    Yet

    neither is

    effectiveness

    passive conformity

    to

    a

    sort

    of

    general

    will.

    Discursive

    practice

    is

    modified

    constantly by

    each

    statement made within

    it, just

    as

    in Kuhn's

    discussion

    of

    the research

    paradigm

    every

    research

    worker

    re-articulates a

    special aspect

    of the

    paradigm

    and

    extends

    and refines it further.

    We

    must

    still

    ask,

    however,

    where discursive

    practice

    actually

    takes

    place,

    how is its

    effectiveness measured

    or

    realized,

    and

    what sort of

    activity

    it is

    really.

    In

    answering

    these

    questions

    in The

    Archeology

    of

    Knowledge

    Foucault

    admits that

    what

    he

    supplies

    is

    not

    yet

    a

    theory

    but

    only

    a

    possibility

    (pp.

    114-15).

    One

    ought

    to be

    willing

    to

    accept

    this

    qualification

    if,

    in

    exchange,

    the

    possibility provides

    enough

    of an

    indication

    that a

    possibility

    now is not

    just

    an

    excuse

    for

    the absence of

    theory.

    In

    other

    words,

    is

    a

    possi-

    bility

    described at

    length

    forceful

    enough

    to

    prepare

    the ground for a theory? I think it is, in this case.

    For Foucault is

    proposing

    a method for

    under-

    standing

    social

    behaviour

    as what

    it

    is

    that

    people

    must do in

    order to

    speak

    and

    write as

    contributors

    to an

    ongoing system

    of

    the

    values,

    discoveries,

    er-

    rors,

    and institutions that

    we call

    knowledge

    (savoir).

    Since

    knowledge

    is neither

    a

    mysterious jumble

    of

    ideas nor a fact

    of

    nature,

    and since it is

    not some-

    thing

    that

    one

    has

    but

    something

    that one

    does,

    it

    is

    best

    conceived

    of

    initially

    as

    occupying

    a

    group

    of

    hypothetical

    spaces.

    One of

    them

    might

    be where

    one stands in order

    to

    speak,

    another

    might

    be from

    dkccri

    IS/Summer

    1974

    This content downloaded from 142.150.248.14 on Sat, 24 Jan 2015 17:13:19 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Said an Ethics of Language - Said on Foucault

    8/11

    where he draws forth the elements

    he

    combines

    to

    make

    a

    statement,

    another

    might

    be where he

    puts

    his

    statement,

    and a fourth

    might

    be where

    his

    state-

    ment

    is

    either

    preserved,

    modified,

    accumulated,

    or

    passed

    on.

    Surrounding

    all

    these

    places

    is a set

    of

    general

    boundaries,

    or

    limits,

    that holds all the

    other

    spaces

    in.

    This

    constraint

    is

    the

    dpistm&e,

    which,

    when

    it is

    specified

    as

    an

    actively

    populated

    expanse

    of knowledge-acts at a given moment in history, is

    not an

    open space

    but rather

    a

    system

    of

    distances.

    Thus in

    the

    eighteenth

    century,

    for

    example,

    the

    dis-

    tance between

    religion

    and

    psychology

    as

    discipline

    is

    closer

    than

    it is a hundred

    years

    later. The

    whole

    map

    of

    such relations

    is what

    Foucault

    means

    by

    dpistime.

    This

    is

    very

    different

    from

    describing

    a

    Zeitgeist,

    or

    an

    ideology,

    or

    a

    Weltanschauung.

    What

    distinguishes

    dpisteme

    from

    them

    is not

    that

    all

    are

    unconscious

    or

    communal,

    but

    that

    only

    the

    episteme

    is not

    an

    implicit

    belief-system

    sometimes

    projected

    by

    individuals

    or

    institutions. Rather

    the

    dpistmrne

    "is

    a

    constantly moving

    set

    of

    articulations,

    shifts,

    and

    coincidences

    that are established

    only

    to

    give

    rise

    to

    others"

    (p.

    192).

    The rules

    collectively

    governing

    these move-

    ments of the

    dpistem'-governing

    their

    appearance

    as

    events,

    for the

    dpistime

    is

    usually

    described

    by

    Foucault

    as

    a set

    of

    moving

    constraints

    that

    estab-

    lish an

    outer

    limit of

    knowledge-make

    discourse

    possible.

    The

    historical

    economy

    of discourse is

    the

    archive:

    The archive is

    first

    the

    law

    of

    what

    can be

    said,

    the

    system

    that

    governs

    the

    appearance

    of statements

    as

    unique

    events.

    But

    the archive

    is also

    that

    which

    deter-

    mines

    that

    all these

    things

    said

    do not accumulate

    end-

    lessly

    in

    an

    amorphous

    mass,

    nor are

    they

    inscribed

    in

    an

    unbroken

    linearity,

    nor do

    they disappear

    at

    the

    mercy

    of

    chance external

    accidents;

    but

    they

    are

    grouped

    together in distinct figures, composed together in accor-

    dance

    with

    multiple

    relations,

    maintained or blurred

    in

    accordance

    with

    specific

    regularities.

    ...

    The archive

    is

    not

    that

    which, despite

    its

    immediate

    escape,

    safeguards

    the event

    of the

    statement,

    and

    preserves,

    for

    future

    memories,

    its

    status

    as

    an

    escape;

    it is that which

    em-

    bodies

    it,

    defines at

    the

    outset

    the

    system

    of

    its

    enunci-

    ability.

    Nor

    is the

    archive

    that

    which

    collects the

    dust

    of statements

    that

    have

    become inert once

    more,

    and

    which

    may

    make

    possible

    the

    miracle of their

    resurrec-

    tion;

    it is

    that

    which

    defines

    the mode of occurrence

    of

    the

    statement-thing;

    t is

    the

    system

    of

    its

    functioning.

    Far

    from

    being

    that

    which

    unifies

    everything

    that

    has

    been

    said in

    the

    great

    confused

    murmur of

    a

    discourse,

    far

    from

    being

    only

    that

    which

    insures

    that

    we exist

    in

    the midst

    of

    preserved

    discourse,

    it is

    that

    which

    differ-

    entiates

    discourses

    in

    their

    multiple

    existence

    and

    speci-

    fies them in their own duration. (p. 129)

    Discourses

    exist

    within

    the archive.

    They

    are

    special-

    ized modes

    of utterance

    (clinical

    discourse,

    for

    in-

    stance,

    or

    sociological

    discourse)

    that

    must

    not

    be

    confused

    with

    simple

    jargon.

    A discourse

    is

    syste-

    matic,

    and

    it has

    epistemological,

    social,

    political,

    economic

    and historical

    relations

    with other

    dis-

    courses in

    the archive.

    Most

    important,

    the

    discourse

    is

    not

    dialectical-"without

    flaw,

    without

    contradic-

    tion,

    without

    internal

    arbitrariness"

    (p.

    114)-and

    is made

    up

    of

    statements,

    which

    "bear an

    enuncia-

    tive function"

    (p.

    115).

    We are

    back

    to

    effectiveness,

    and it

    now be-

    comes

    possible

    to

    see

    that Foucault

    is

    most

    interested

    in

    defining

    the statement:

    the

    dpisteme',

    the

    archive,

    even

    discourse,

    all

    these

    are

    analytic

    instruments

    more or

    less

    invented

    by

    the

    archeologist

    in

    order

    to

    approach

    the

    statement,

    in

    order

    to

    provide

    a

    suitable

    terminology

    for

    apprehending

    the

    statement,

    which

    is

    after

    all

    the

    very

    mode

    and

    presence

    of

    effectiveness.

    For Foucault the

    statement

    is

    not

    a

    sentence necessarily, nor any unit describable by

    grammar

    or

    logic.

    Moreover

    since

    it

    is in and of

    discourse

    it

    cannot be

    something

    latent

    that

    is real-

    ized

    by

    discourse. The

    more

    Foucault

    enumerates

    what a

    statement

    is

    not,

    the

    more it

    is

    evident

    that

    a

    statement

    is difficult

    both to

    make

    and to describe:

    it is

    rare.

    The statement is not

    just

    another

    unity-above

    or be-

    low-sentences

    and

    propositions;

    it

    is

    always

    invested

    in unities of this

    kind,

    or even in

    sequences

    of

    signs

    that do not

    obey

    their laws

    (and

    which

    may

    be

    lists,

    chance

    series,

    tables);

    it characterizes not

    what

    is

    given

    in

    them,

    but

    the

    very

    fact that

    they

    are

    given,

    and

    the

    way

    in which

    they

    are

    given.

    It

    has

    the

    quasi-invisibility

    of the

    "there

    is,"

    which is effaced

    in

    the

    very

    thing

    of

    which one can say: "there s this or that thing." (p. 111)

    Perhaps

    a

    prefiguration

    of

    what Foucault means

    by

    a

    statement

    is

    to be

    found

    in

    the smile

    of

    the

    Chesh-

    ire

    cat

    or,

    as he himself

    says

    in the

    opening pages

    of

    The Order

    of

    Things,

    in

    the list

    of

    animals

    given

    in

    a

    Chinese

    encyclopedia

    referred

    to

    in "The

    Analyt-

    ical

    Language

    of

    John

    Wilkins"

    by

    Borges.

    "Al-

    though

    the

    statement

    cannot

    be

    hidden

    it

    is

    not

    vis-

    ible

    either

    [...]

    it is

    like

    the

    over-familiar

    that con-

    stantly

    eludes one"

    (pp.

    110-11).

    Another

    important

    aspect

    of

    the statement

    is that it

    is

    correlative

    with

    a lack:

    "There

    may

    in fact be-and

    always

    are-in

    the conditions

    of

    emergence

    of

    statements,

    exclu-

    sions,

    limits,

    or

    gaps

    that

    divide

    up

    their

    referential,

    validate only one series of modalities, enclose groups

    of

    coexistence,

    and

    prevent

    certain

    forms

    of use"

    (p.

    110).

    Thus a

    statement

    emerging

    prevents

    an-

    other utterance from

    emerging; conversely,

    with

    re-

    gard

    to a

    whole series of

    possibilities,

    a

    statement

    emerges

    to

    be

    something

    else,

    namely,

    a

    statement,

    but not

    an

    idea,

    or a

    sentence,

    or a

    passing

    remark.

    At

    all

    events,

    one

    thing

    at

    least

    must be

    empha-

    sized

    here: that the

    analysis

    of discourse

    [and

    of state-

    ments in

    and

    by

    discourse]

    thus

    understood,

    does

    not re-

    veal

    the

    universality

    of a

    meaning,

    but

    brings

    to

    light

    the

    action

    of

    imposed

    rarity,

    with

    a

    fundamental

    power

    of affirmation.

    Rarity

    and

    affirmation:

    rarity,

    in

    the last

    resort of affirmation

    [Swyer's

    translation here

    is

    impos-

    sibly garbled:

    Foucault

    says,

    "the

    rarity

    of

    affirmation"]

    -certainly

    not any continuous out-pouringof meaning,

    and

    certainly

    not

    any monarchy

    of the

    signifier.

    (p.

    234)

    The

    peculiar,

    and I think the

    crucial,

    problem

    of The

    Archeology

    of

    Knowledge

    is its

    attempt

    to

    define effectiveness

    without

    theory,

    that

    is,

    to

    regard

    practice

    not

    as a cause

    of

    effectiveness

    but as

    the

    main

    part

    of it. To affirm with force even

    as

    one

    ex-

    cludes

    much

    else-this is

    effectiveness.

    Effectiveness

    is also

    to

    modify

    other effective

    statements,

    and

    it is

    also to

    last,

    to be

    re-activated

    (as

    when a later

    age

    returns to

    Marx or to

    Freud),

    to

    be

    consciously

    ex-

    cluded

    (as

    when The Wasteland

    excludes Christian-

    ity),

    to be

    re-appropriated

    (as

    in

    his

    essay

    "Kafka

    This content downloaded from 142.150.248.14 on Sat, 24 Jan 2015 17:13:19 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Said an Ethics of Language - Said on Foucault

    9/11

    and his

    Precursors"

    Borges gives

    Kafka

    his

    forgotten

    patrimony).

    Lest it

    be assumed that statements

    in discourse

    during

    a

    given

    epistime

    make

    up

    a

    unity

    resembling

    either

    the

    Great

    Chain of

    Being

    or a

    Hegelian

    total-

    ity

    Foucault

    goes

    out of his

    way

    to

    show that this

    is

    not

    what

    he has in

    mind.

    Two of his most com-

    plex

    chapters

    in The

    Archeology-"Contradictions"

    and

    "The

    Comparative

    Facts"-insist

    yet

    more

    strongly

    on

    the discontinuous

    nature

    of statements

    in the archive. To the archeologist discourse is a

    space

    of

    dissension.

    Eighteenth-century

    Natural

    His-

    tory,

    for

    instance,

    is

    essentially

    a

    set

    of "intrinsic

    oppositions [...

    .

    distributed over

    different

    levels of

    the

    discursive

    formation"

    (p.

    154).

    These

    opposi-

    tions

    articulate

    divergence,

    incompatibility,

    and

    ex-

    clusion. "In

    the

    case

    of

    the

    systematic analysis

    of

    plants

    [in

    eighteenth-century

    Natural

    History],

    one

    applies

    a

    rigorous

    perceptual

    and

    linguistic

    code,

    and

    in

    accordance with a

    constant

    scale;

    for

    method-

    ical

    description

    [during

    the same

    period],

    the

    codes

    are

    relatively

    free,

    and

    the scales of

    mapping may

    oscillate"

    (p.

    154).

    When;

    however,

    there are

    no

    contradictions-that

    is,

    if

    one wishes

    to

    show,

    as

    Foucault

    did in

    The Order

    of

    Things,

    that

    eighteenth

    century

    General Grammar and Natural

    History

    are

    related

    after

    all-there

    is "a

    region

    of

    interpositiv-

    ity,"

    which is

    tangled

    but

    is

    also a set of

    fairly

    well-

    articulated

    correlations.

    Everything

    I

    have

    so far said of Foucault in-

    terprets,

    rather than

    summarizes,

    his

    archeology

    as

    simultaneously

    the

    expression

    of radical dissatisfac-

    tion

    and radical

    affirmation.

    Let

    us

    take

    dissatisfac-

    tion and

    doubt first. I think

    he

    is

    correct to

    judge

    Western historical

    understanding

    as

    being

    based

    very

    generally upon

    two forms of

    explanation,

    one

    ver-

    tical,

    and

    one horizontal.

    Both

    generally

    work to-

    gether

    since both mix

    the

    temporal

    and

    the

    spatial

    modes.

    Written historical

    evidence

    is

    judged

    to

    be

    a trace, which when it is explained vertically is con-

    ceived of

    as the

    exterior residual

    expression

    of

    an

    interior,

    or

    underlying,

    force, rationale,

    meaning,

    image,

    or

    idea.

    When it

    is

    explained

    horizontally

    it

    is

    conveived of

    as

    having

    been

    preceded

    by

    some-

    thing

    that

    gives

    it

    meaning:

    other

    events,

    a succes-

    sive line of

    development,

    an

    Origin.

    To Foucault

    any

    form of

    understanding

    that sends

    one

    away

    to

    given

    or assumed

    ontologically prior

    forms such

    as

    an

    author,

    a

    period,

    an

    idea,

    a

    source,

    a

    world-view

    -in

    short,

    a

    genealogy

    of order-discounts

    the

    pres-

    ence of

    the

    evidence,

    its

    sheer

    persistence

    as event

    or as

    evidence,

    in

    favor

    of deterministic

    hyposta-

    tizations. Moreover

    these determinisms assume

    a

    priv-

    ilege

    in

    the

    understanding

    without account

    being

    taken of their very circumstantial nature. When

    Nietzsche said that discussions of

    poets

    like

    Homer

    (about

    whom

    as

    authors

    nothing

    was

    known)

    were

    judgments

    made

    by

    later

    generations

    and not at

    all

    accurate

    descriptions

    of

    reality,

    he was

    saying

    some-

    thing

    that

    Foucault

    would

    agree

    with

    readily.

    To

    say

    that

    Shelley

    wrote "Adonais" is not

    sufficiently

    to

    describe the

    fact

    that

    "Adonais" was written. In or-

    der to do that one would

    have to

    grasp

    first

    of all

    why

    to the critic in 1973

    it matters that the

    poem

    was

    written

    (and

    this involves an

    archeological

    de-

    scription

    of

    literary

    discourse

    today),

    then to

    grasp

    how as

    writing

    the

    poem

    was

    received,

    modified

    and

    preserved

    in

    poetico-elegiac

    discourse

    in the

    early

    nineteenth

    century.

    While one

    may

    never to able

    to

    complete

    such an

    archeological

    description-and

    Foucault

    is under no illusion

    that it is

    anything

    but

    interminable-its

    stated

    requirements

    are at