Top Banner
Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar's Janos-Faced Dualist Interpretation of Hegel by Ryan Haecker Thank you for providing this detailed response on how you interpret Hegel's Absolute. Before I address the points which you raise, I wish to briefly preface this discussion with a summary of the questions surrounding my hypothesis at the present. The hypothesis that I had presented was that the homology between the anti-foundationalism of Hegel's Absolute and the lack of a foundation in mathematics suggested the possibility of a Hegelian analysis of the problem of the foundation of mathematics, in which mathematics could be categorized as a formal domain of thought that is abstracted from, opposed to, and united with Hegel's system of philosophy as it united within the difference of the Absolute. I wrote (colored blue): "I argue that, because mathematics is not founded upon itself, it must be founded upon something other-than-itself; and that the most plausible candidate is the self-subsistent Hegelian Absolute..." To establish this thesis requires, from the standpoint of the Absolute, a deduction of the abstract domain of mathematics from Hegel's Logic; and from the standpoint of mathematics, a demonstration of the impossibility of a foundation to mathematics; which I proposed might be the consequence of Bertrand Russell's Paradox as it was re-employed in Kurt Gödel's Incompleteness Theorem. Assuming an agreement on the nature of the Absolute and the anti-foundationalism of mathematics, this hypothesis requires a definite description within and through the speculative dialectic, of the mediating relation between the Absolute and all mathematics. I observe definite structure to the present dispute, concerning my hypothesis and the objections: (A) my hypothesis proposes to describe the (M) mediating relation between (S) the Absolute and (P) all mathematics to account for the absence of a foundation within mathematics, e.g. S-M-P (which can be understood as the self-mediation and self-identity of mathematics; e.g. Mathematics - Mediation - Mathematics; mathematics predicated of itself, or S = S ), which can alternatively be understood, from the standpoint of mathematics, as an explanation of the foundation of mathematics in the Absolute, e.g. Mathematics - Mediation - Absolute, P-M-S. The objection of Alan concerns, not the (A) mediation relation, but only the nature of the subject term of the Absolute within this syllogistic relation. (B) Bill and Alan objected to my characterization of Hegel's Absolute in the admittedly Fichtean terms as the Absolute Ego. Alan elaborated to say that the Absolute was neither (a) self-identical, (b) self- subsistent or (c) subjective and intentional. As the hypothesis of the (A) mediation relation of the Absolute to Mathematics (e.g. S-M-P) is a composite of the constituent conceptual terms of the Absolute and mathematics, the (B) objection to a definite nature of the subject term of the Absolute jeopardizes the consistency of my hypothesis. The three objections can be further distinguished as (a) logical, (b) ontological, and (c)
74

Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

Nov 08, 2014

Download

Documents

sivaramanlb

Ryan Hacker's debate with Alan Ponikvar on Hegel and religion. Ryan Hacker, who claims to be a Right Hegelian, debates Hegel's views on religion with atheist Hegel scholar and a specialist on speculative thinking in Hegel.
Welcome message from author
This document is posted to help you gain knowledge. Please leave a comment to let me know what you think about it! Share it to your friends and learn new things together.
Transcript
Page 1: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar's Janos-Faced Dualist Interpretation of Hegel

by Ryan Haecker

Thank you for providing this detailed response on how you interpret Hegel's Absolute.

Before I address the points which you raise, I wish to briefly preface this discussion with

a summary of the questions surrounding my hypothesis at the present. The hypothesis

that I had presented was that the homology between the anti-foundationalism of Hegel's

Absolute and the lack of a foundation in mathematics suggested the possibility of a

Hegelian analysis of the problem of the foundation of mathematics, in which

mathematics could be categorized as a formal domain of thought that is abstracted from,

opposed to, and united with Hegel's system of philosophy as it united within the

difference of the Absolute. I wrote (colored blue): "I argue that, because mathematics is

not founded upon itself, it must be founded upon something other-than-itself; and that

the most plausible candidate is the self-subsistent Hegelian Absolute..." To establish

this thesis requires, from the standpoint of the Absolute, a deduction of the abstract

domain of mathematics from Hegel's Logic; and from the standpoint of mathematics, a

demonstration of the impossibility of a foundation to mathematics; which I proposed

might be the consequence of Bertrand Russell's Paradox as it was re-employed in Kurt

Gödel's Incompleteness Theorem. Assuming an agreement on the nature of the

Absolute and the anti-foundationalism of mathematics, this hypothesis requires a

definite description within and through the speculative dialectic, of the mediating

relation between the Absolute and all mathematics.

I observe definite structure to the present dispute, concerning my hypothesis and the

objections: (A) my hypothesis proposes to describe the (M) mediating relation between

(S) the Absolute and (P) all mathematics to account for the absence of a foundation

within mathematics, e.g. S-M-P (which can be understood as the self-mediation and

self-identity of mathematics; e.g. Mathematics - Mediation - Mathematics; mathematics

predicated of itself, or S = S ), which can alternatively be understood, from the

standpoint of mathematics, as an explanation of the foundation of mathematics in the

Absolute, e.g. Mathematics - Mediation - Absolute, P-M-S. The objection of Alan

concerns, not the (A) mediation relation, but only the nature of the subject term of the

Absolute within this syllogistic relation. (B) Bill and Alan objected to my

characterization of Hegel's Absolute in the admittedly Fichtean terms as the Absolute

Ego. Alan elaborated to say that the Absolute was neither (a) self-identical, (b) self-

subsistent or (c) subjective and intentional. As the hypothesis of the (A) mediation

relation of the Absolute to Mathematics (e.g. S-M-P) is a composite of the constituent

conceptual terms of the Absolute and mathematics, the (B) objection to a definite nature

of the subject term of the Absolute jeopardizes the consistency of my hypothesis. The

three objections can be further distinguished as (a) logical, (b) ontological, and (c)

Page 2: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

epistemological. Observe further that in the order of being (ordo esse), from the

standpoint of the Absolute, the latter is derived from the former; something is only (c)

thinking if it is (b) self-subsistent; and something is only (b) self-subsistent if it is (a)

self-identical. Hence, the question of whether or not the Absolute is (c) subjective and

intentional will depend on its (b) self-subsistence, which further depends on (a) its self-

identity. This means also that the self-identity and self-subsistence of the Absolute do

not (abstractly for the understanding) depend on (c) the subjectivity and intentionality

of the Absolute. For this reason, I proposed that my hypothesis of the (1) mediating

relation of the Absolute to Mathematics might be consistent even without disputing the

theological question of the (c) subjectivity and intentionality of the Absolute, which is

simply the personhood and self-consciousness of God. Although I admit that these

distinctions and relations of dependency (1 & 2, and 'a → b → c') reduces the speculative

Absolute to the categories of finite understanding, I expect that this mode of thinking

and writing may nonetheless be helpful to frame and adjudicate the present dispute.

In response to Alan's objection to characterizing the Absolute as subject, self-conscious

and intentional, I replied with an argument from grammar that contended that Alan

was inconsistent in characterizing the Absolute as an "Absolute form" of "self-reflective

subjectivity" for there can be no self-reflection without a self and no subjectivity without

a subject: both terms 'self-reflective' and 'subjectivity' refer to either an adjective or a

verb form of a composite term of self and subject. To deny that the Absolute is self or is

subject is, simply grammatically, to deny that it can be composed further to have self-

reflection and or subjectivity:

"The biggest objection that I have to this interpretation is that I do not understand how

thought can be self-reflective and subjective in any way without a self, an Ego, and a

subject of thought. It seems a flat contradiction to say that the Absolute is "self-reflective

subjectivity" and yet the Absolute has no self. This problem, I expect, requires Hegelian

interpreters to either affirm that the Absolute is, simply by its essence, or in virtue of

some other particular thing, a self-reflective Ego."

"intentionality is the determinative intellective activity of a subject, a self, and an Ego; if

the Absolute is subject, self and Ego then it has intentional relations towards objects of

its consciousness."

The argument from grammar would ordinarily defeat the contention, that a self-

reflective Absolute has no self, simply because the former predicate cannot be applied

while the latter is denied, without equivocation. However, because we are disputing

Hegel's Absolute, Alan can possibly wiggle out of what amounts to the equivocal fallacy

by appealing in some imaginative way to the infinite dialectical movement of speculative

reason. Thus, Alan (colored red) responds with two counter-claims:

Page 3: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

"I would like to make two claims that seem inconsistent. (1) First, as you note,

the true may be both taken as substance as well as subject but it is not a

self-subsistent substance nor an actual subject. And (2) second, the absolute

only emerges within the orb of finite subjectivity."

1) "With the first point I wish to indicate that we can employ the absolute without

buying into the notion that the absolute is some ultimate substance or some actual

infinite spirit that has intentions."

Alan appears to agrees with my previous claim that, because we can perhaps "employ

the absolute without... (c) intentions" then the (A) mediating relation between the

Absolute and mathematics can be true without attributing (c) self-consciousness,

subjectivity and intentionality to the Absolute. I wish to note that, according to my

argument above for the independence of (a) self-identity and (b) self-subsistence from

(c) subjectivity and intentionality, this means that Alan agrees that my hypothesis could

be sound even in spite of his criticisms.

2) "With the second point I provide the reason for the first point. There is nothing grand

about the absolute – either with respect to substance or subject – because the absolute

first comes on the scene as the form that finite thought takes when this thought is

brought to a dialectical impasse."

Here Alan first defines how the (2) second point provides the justification for the (1)

first (e.g. 1 iff 2, or 2 <=> 1). Thus, both points are defeasible if the (2) second point is

defeated. Alan describes that "comes on the scene" which ambiguously implies that the

Absolute existed prior to coming on the scene; for nothing 'comes' anywhere without

having first been existing somewhere else. This is important because it will contradict

the non-metaphysical emergentist account of the Absolute that Alan afterwards

presents; in which the Absolute is a form of the thought of an inter-subjective human

community which emerges as the "form that finite thought takes" is "brought to a

dialectical impasses", namely the contradictory impasses of the Kantian antinomies.

Alan explains:

"Only if there is frustrated finite thought is there a dialectic. And only if

there is a dialectic is there absolute form. All truths for Hegel manifest

this absolute form that is the identity in difference of dynamic, idealized

moments. As infinite or unconditioned the absolute form comes on the scene

by means of an insight by the speculative philosopher who attends to what

happens to finite thinking at this moment of frustration."

Page 4: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

According to Alan's description there is little possibility of discerning the central

question of our dispute, namely the essence of the Absolute as subjective and

intentional, because Alan carefully conceals any commitment a realist definition of the

Absolute that pre-exists human thought, or an anti-realist idealist definition of the

Absolute that emerges only with human thought. When Alan describes the Absolute as

"infinite or unconditioned" that may "come on the scene" "by means of an insight" by

the speculative philosopher he appears to imply that the philosopher generates the

Absolute where there was none before. Is this what Alan means? If not, then how does

the Absolute exist before insight of the speculative philosopher? One answer that Alan

might give is to affirm that the Absolute exists intellectually by knowing itself in-and-

through its own intentional subjectivity. Another answer is that the Absolute exists in an

inchoate and unrealized nascent form among the inter-subjective thinking of historical

human communities. The former is the so-called transcendentist, metaphysical, and

theological interpretation of the Absolute as the subjective self-conscious and

intentional God of Christianity, while the latter is the so-called immanentist, non-

metaphysical, and humanist interpretation of the Absolute as the self-understanding of

historical human communities. Alan affirms the latter and deny the former, even as he

sometimes employs ambiguous language that seems to suggest the former. Previously,

Alan and I had apparently disagreed upon the ontological status of the Absolute. I

wrote:

" I believe that our disagreement pertains rather to the ontic status of this becoming,

specifically the question of whether it may essentially possess the power to be self-

subsistent and provide the foundation of mathematics that mathematics does not

provide for itself: I want to affirm greater ontology and power of self-subsistence while

you wish to deny these to Hegel's Absolute."

At the end of Alan's reply, he apparently agrees with me that the Absolute can be

interpreted ontologically, as either self-subsisting or implicitly ontologically divided

within itself:

"what this shows is that Hegel's absolute has ontological import."

Yet Alan still wants to disagree on the nature of this "ontological import." Alan writes:

Hegel's absolute is not theological but prosaic in the extreme. It comes into being and

inverts due to the way it reflects thought's ability to shift perspective... Thought and

being are one, but not as a simple identity."

Page 5: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

When Alan describes Hegel's Absolute as "prosaic in the extreme" he means to

ontologically reduce the ontological divisions intrinsic within the Absolute even after he

has affirmed that the Absolute is in some sense ontological; for 'prosaic' means the

absence of any definite features, in the manner of free-prose, and is thus opposed to real

ontological divisions (such as any equivocal division between subject and object, creator

and creatures) within the unity of the Absolute. In my previous reply I objected to the

ostensible contradiction of Alan affirming that the Absolute is self-reflective while

denying to the Absolute a self; unless perhaps if the self could, in some way, be a

historical human community of inter-subjective thinking:

"I interpret you, on the other hand, to understand the 'self' Hegel's self-reflective

Absolute to be like Pinkard's absolutization of the inter-subjective self-reflective thought

of historical human communities. The initial objection re-emerges with this answer:

where in a historical community of inter-subjective thinking is there any 'self' to which

the Absolute subjectively may reflect upon?"

Of course, this careful concealment of ontological commitment is just the trick that

Hegel relies upon to work through the different stages in the dialectic. Alan is similarly

presenting a dialectic of stages of dialectical thought in his speculative reply to my

objections. The difference between how I interpret Alan and how I interpret Hegel is

that I understand Alan to be presenting a two-stage dialectic that culminates in the

negative moment which effaces all logical-identity and obliterates all ontological

subsistence (both (a) and (b) of which are crucial to any hypothesized founding of

mathematics upon the Absolute), while I understand Hegel to reconcile the negative and

positive moments in a synthesis which preserves both positivity and negativity is a self-

moving concept. In short, I envisage Alan's dialectic to never advance beyond tarrying

with the negative in a bad infinite of negating the positive moment. I invite Alan to

correct me if he observes that I am misrepresenting his position. As evidence, observe

how Alan writes:

The dialectic itself arises at that point when thought attempts to complete

itself as a self-concern. Hegel's Logic is about this self-thinking thought... The problem

is that thought does not complete itself by providing this final comprehensive insight

that totalizes its self-thinking. Instead, at this culminating point thought breaks down. It

ceases to make sense. It exhibits an inconsistent thought or antinomy in keeping with

the attempt to think frame as simultaneously also item framed... this is where Hegel

thinks the paradoxical thought: the inability to think the final ultimate thought IS the

final ultimate thought. The dialectic that exhibits the impasse of finite thinking also

exhibits the coherent absolute form of this impasse.

Page 6: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

Any Hegel interpreter that rises to the self-criticism of modern philosophy, especially

the skeptical phenomenalism of Hume and transcendental criticism of Kant, must admit

that classical realism, represented by the positive moment in Hegel's dialectic, to be

untenable from the standpoint of human knowing (ordo episteme). This is not

disputed. What will be disputed is whether there is real self-subsistence in the Absolute,

in the order of being (order esse), from the standpoint of the Absolute. The question

that I wish to raise for Alan is whether or not there is a negative moment, in which

thought "breaks down" and "ceases to make sense" by exhibiting an "inconsistent

thought or antinomy" is the final moment in Hegel's dialectic. As I read Hegel, his

dialectic does not ultimately conclude in the thinking of the "paradoxical thought" and

the "inability to think the final ultimate thought" as a "coherent absolute form", but

rather both the positive moment of realism and this negative moment which opposes

realism are joined together in a mutually enriching third synthetic moment: the

negation of the paradox does not simply nullify positive reality through its opposition,

but rather the positive reality and the opposition of the negative criticism are altogether

taken upon into a self-moving conceptual synthesis that unites and preserves the

alternation of positing and negating in their mutual opposition. This is how I described

our dispute in the previous reply:

"I understand Hegel to interpret the synthetic moment as the truth and concrete reality

of the prior conceptual moments. If Becoming emerges from the dialectic of Being and

Non-Being, then it must possess some being of the former moments, of Being and Non-

Being; simply because for nothing emerges from nothing and without possessing some

being. This is why I interpret Hegel's dialectic as both logical and ontological. An

emergence of something is an addition of being viz. the emergence. Hence I interpret

the concrete synthetic moment of Hegel's dialectic as both an increase in truth and

reality over the previous abstract moments. "

Further, I described how this interpretation conceptually subsumed the ultimate-ness of

the negative moment of paradox in what I interpret to be Alan's negative dialectic:

" I would contend that the negative moment of the dialectic, that negates the being of

what is posited, is not itself ultimate but is rather combined with the posited being in

such a way that ontologically enriches the synthesis of the previous moments: e.g. being-

for-self is contradicted by being-for-others and becomes being-for-self-and-others, or

being-in-and-for-itself. Thus, I interpret the ontologically robust conception of Hegel's

Absolute to be the result rather than the refuse of critical speculation."

To explain away the equivocal fallacy and to dialectically narrate his definition of the

Absolute as not a subject, self or self-consciousness with any intentionality, Alan

presents his long-awaited negative inversion of the realism of the Absolute, in a manner

Page 7: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

consistent with (P) his Pinkardian non-metaphysical interpretation and with his (Z)

Zizekian emphasis on paradox:

"Finite thinking seeks to comprehend what is self-identical or a self-standing content,

meant in this way to be an absolute content. The dialectic subverts this intention. [i.e.

subverts the intention to be self-standing] The infinite then appears as what is not

intended: the form of this failure to grasp content. Thus the absolute comes on the scene

by way of cunning behind the back of the thought of an intentionally directed finite

subject. But this absolute is not itself a subject. It simply is thought that as self-reflexive

exhibits subjective form."

Alan describes how the cunning of reason moves "behind the back of thought of an

intentionally directed finite subject" to the dialectic of thought that "is not itself a

subject" but simply exhibits "thought that as self-reflexive exhibits subjective form."

Who or what is the thinker that thinks the reason that moves "behind the back" of the

thought of the "intentionally directed finite subject"? If it is not the subjective,

intentional self-consciousness of the Absolute and is also not the finite thinking of the

speculative philosopher, then there is only one other option; which is the mediation

between (PhG, C.CC) religious consciousness and (PhG, B) finite individual

understanding; the (PhG, C.AA & C.BB) Spirit of the inter-subjective historical human

community. Thus, the rejection of the theological interpretation of the Absolute as an

intentional subject, even as thought is described to act independently of the finite

speculative philosopher, means, as a consequence of the limited sets of thinking

thinkers, that Alan must adopt the (P) Pinkardian interpretation of the Absolute as the

inter-subjectivity of a human community; for some thinking could only subvert some

thinking if these thinking activities were distinct; and were the distinction not between a

man and the Absolute then it must be between the mankind and a man, between the

collective and the individual.

Alan supports his Pinkardian reading of Hegel's dialectic by describing how any attempt

to conceive of or apprehend the Absolute results in a reduction of the dynamic self-

moving Spirit of the Absolute to a static image that may be analyzed according to the

finite categories of the Understanding, or 'common reason' to use Alan's term. Alan

writes:

The absolute immediately inverts when thought. It becomes a static or abstract version

of the exhibited dynamic... Finite thinking caught in the endless cycle of the transiting of

being/nothing gives way by means of a perspective shift. What motivates the shift marks

a divide between common and speculative thinking... there are no realities that persist

thus there is nothing for us to think. Speculative reason in contrast embraces the evident

paradox: there are no realities to think, only ideal moments that vanish into one

Page 8: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

another, this then is what we will think. In this way, thought is a self-concern.

Alan contends that because thought "immediately inverts" the dynamism of the

Absolute, to become a static abstraction of common reason and understanding, finite

thinking (i.e. common reason) is caught in a bad infinite "cycle of transiting" from the

positive moment of being to the negative moment of non-being. This is the (Z) Zizekian

paradox that Alan interprets Hegel to have dialectically generated from the "impasse" of

the Kantian antinomies for common reason. For Alan, the bad infinite of the "cycle of

transiting" resulting from the Kantian antinomies produces a "perspective shift" in

which "there are no realities that persist" and "there is nothing for us to think" unless

we, as speculative reasoners, follow Alan in embracing the interpretation of the

conclusion of the negative moment as a paradox, in which "ideal moments vanish into

one another" as a totally immanent "self-concern" of historical human communities.

Hence according to Alan the non-metaphysical (P) Pinkardian interpretation depends

upon the (Z) Zizekian dialectic of paradox.

I have two objections to Alan's narration of Hegel's dialectic as in this negative fashion

of a dialectic of paradox. Following Alan's example, (Z.i) the first is dependent upon

(Z.ii) the second. (Z.i) First, rather than addressing the interpretation that I had

proposed, in which Hegel's dialectic should be interpreted as three logical moments in

the familiar triadic arrangement, Alan presents what appears to be a dialectic of only

two logical moments that concludes by affirming the ultimate-ness of the negative

moment, and rejoicing in its paradox. For example, Alan describes how the negativity of

the negative moment entirely obliterates all intrinsic reason and substance of the

positive moment when he describes how afterwards "there are no realities that persist

thus there is nothing for us to think." If I am correct in interpreting Alan as thusly

ejecting the reason and substance of the positive moment, then Alan commits himself to

the sort of "bad skepticism" that Hegel describes (colored green) in the Introduction to

the Phenomenology of Spirit:

"To make this comprehensible we may remark, by way of preliminary, that the

exposition of untrue consciousness in its untruth is not a merely negative process.

Such a one-sided view of it is what the natural consciousness generally adopts; and a

knowledge, which makes this one-sidedness its essence, is one of those shapes assumed

by incomplete consciousness which falls into the course of the inquiry itself and will

come before us there. For this view is scepticism, which always sees in the

result only pure nothingness, and abstracts from the fact that this nothing

is determinate, is the nothing of that out of which it comes as a result.

Nothing, however, is only, in fact, the true result, when taken as the nothing of what it

comes from; it is thus itself a determinate nothing, and has a content. The

scepticism which ends with the abstraction “nothing” or “emptiness” can advance

Page 9: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

from this not a step farther, but must wait and see whether there is possibly

anything new offered, and what that is — in order to cast it into the same

abysmal void. When once, on the other hand, the result is apprehended, as it truly is,

as determinate negation, a new form has thereby immediately arisen; and in

the negation the transition is made by which the progress through the complete

succession of forms comes about of itself." (PhG, §79, Miller Trans.)

I contend that Alan's negative dialectic of paradox, which emphasizes the ultimate-ness

of the negative moment as paradox, is simply the sort view of skepticism that Hegel

critiques in this section from the Phenomenology of Spirit. For both Alan and the shape

of incomplete consciousness of Skepticism, the result of the dialectic is to only see "pure

nothingness" in which there is no reason, or substance, and "nothing is determinate"

and from this nothing Skepticism brings forth its result, the result of paradox.

(Z.ii) Second, I object that, in just the same way as Skepticism can bring forth no

determinate content of thought as a result, Alan is mistaken to hold that he can bring

forth any determinate content of thought from the annihilating negativity of a paradox

in which "there are no realities that persist thus there is nothing for us to think." To say,

to the contrary, that determinate thought come from nothing, Alan must violate

Parmenides prohibition and contend the impossible: that some determinate thing can

come from the indeterminateness of nothing! Blessed Plato writes:

"You see, then, that in our disobedience to Parmenides we have trespassed far beyond

the limits of his prohibition... He says you remember, ‘Never shall this be proved that

things that are not, are, but keep back thy thought from this way of inquiry.’”

- Plato, the Sophist, 258c-d

Alan mentions his indebtedness to Zizek, but where did Zizek discover this doctrine?

Zizek found it buried in the Jena writings of none other than F.J. Schelling! For Zizek,

Alan and Schelling, there is no determinate way of resolving the contradictions of

thought in the Kantian antinomies. The resolution is, thus, for Zizek to think through

the paradox (which I confess that I don't understand) just as it was for Schelling to have

an aesthetic intuition of the identity between ideality and reality, the system of things

thought and of things of extension. In either case we have a empty nothingness in which

nothing can emerge according to any reasoning at all; for nothing less than a miracle can

bring forth something from nothing and miracles are totally inscrutable. Again Hegel

criticizes this doctrine of Schelling, in which determinate thought arises from nothing,

in a famous passage from the Phenomenology of Spirit:

"This monotonousness and abstract universality are maintained to be the

Absolute. This formalism insists that to be dissatisfied therewith argues an incapacity

Page 10: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

to grasp the standpoint of the Absolute, and keep a firm hold on it... we find here all the

value ascribed to the general idea in this bare form without concrete realisation;

and we see here, too, the style and method of speculative contemplation identified with

dissipating and, resolving what is determinate and distinct, or rather with hurling it

down, without more ado and without any justification, into the abyss of vacuity.

(PhG. §16, Baillie Trans.)

For Alan the "abstract universality" "maintained to be the Absolute" is the cunning of

reason that persists in the inter-subjective human community "behind the back of the

thought of an intentionally directed finite subject." The paradox of the Kantian

antinomies may totally negate and obliterate all reason and substance in the positive

moment only because some reason and substance of thought persists, behind the back

of the finite subject, in the activity of self-reflective thinking of the inter-subjective

human community.

If my interpretation is correct, Alan like Schelling holds that the dialectic of self-

reflective reasoning may persists, even in spite of hurling down the determinate and

distinct content of speculative contemplation into the paradoxical "abyss of vacuity",

because thought subsists, not in "an intentionally directed finite subject", but "in the

abstract identity A = A" of the spiritual substance of the inter-subjective human

community; which is not thought but remains a "bare form without concrete

realization." The totally un-thought abstract identity of the historical human

community, which Zizek perhaps identifies with historical materialism, is an empty

notion with no rational content; it consists in the positing that would "pit this single

assertion, that “in the Absolute all is one”, against the organized whole of determinate

and complete knowledge"; it is to "give out its Absolute as the night in which, as we say,

all cows are black – that is the very naïveté of emptiness of knowledge." (PhG. §16,

Baillie Trans.) The (Z.i) first objection that Alan performs the incomplete stage of

conscious thought of "bad skepticism" follows from (Z.ii) the second objection of the

emptiness and impossibility of the negative dialectic of paradox in which nothing comes

from the "abyss of vacuity."

To conclude, I distinguished the disputes into two questions: (A) the mediating relation

between the Absolute and mathematics (e.g. S-M-P), and (B) the nature of the Absolute

as the self-conscious and intentional being which we call God. I distinguished three

characteristics that had been attributed to the Absolute; (a) self-identity, (b) self-

subsistency, and (c) self-conscious subjectivity and intentionality; and argued that (A)

the mediating relationship of my hypothesis minimally required (a) self-identity and (b)

self-subsistency but did not require (c) self-conscious subjectivity and intentionality. I

observed that Alan agreed with my claim that the (A) mediating relation between the

Absolute could operate even without (c) the self-conscious subjectivity and

Page 11: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

intentionality, but only with the (a) self-identity and (b) self-subsistency of the Absolute.

Because Alan only contests whether the Absolute is (c) self-conscious, subject and

intentional, and we both agree that this property (c) is not required for the truth of (A)

the mediating relation between the Absolute and Mathematics, I judge that Alan admits

the possibility (A) that mathematics could be categorized as a formal domain of thought

that is abstracted from, opposed to, and united with Hegel's system of philosophy as it

united within the difference of the Absolute.

If, on the contrary, Alan intended to reverse this opinion and contend that (c) self-

conscious subjectivity and intentionality were essential to any conception of (A) the

Absolute that mediates and founds mathematics, then I have further critiqued the basis

of Alan's critique of the (c) self-conscious subjectivity and intentionality of the Absolute.

Alan's critique of (c) was presented in two theses, in which (1) the first thesis, that the

Absolute "is not a self-subsistent substance nor an actual subject" entirely depends upon

(2) the second thesis, that "the absolute only emerges within the orb of finite

subjectivity." My arguments are directed against the second thesis to, as a consequence

of their dependency, kill two birds with one stone. I argued from grammar that Alan

was inconsistent in characterizing the Absolute as an "Absolute form" of "self-reflective

subjectivity" while also denying that that the Absolute possessed a self, subject and Ego.

Alan suggests with the language of "emerge" and "come on the scene" that the Absolute

possesses subsists prior to the finite thought of the intentional subject, but he neglects

to immediately disclose in what substance the Absolute subsists in. I propose three

domains of thinking in which the self-reflective thought of the Absolute may subsist: (i)

in the intentional subjectivity of the Absolute which is what we call God; (ii) in the inter-

subjective human community which Hegel calls Spirit; or (iii) in the finite thinking of

the speculative philosopher, posited by what Fichte calls the Ego. I argued that if Alan

denied that the Absolute subsisted (i) in subjective intentionality then it can only subsist

in (ii) Pinkard's historical human communities and in (iii) Fichte's posting. I had

previously argued that Alan was attempting to reduce the Ontological differentia of the

Absolute to an immanentist non-metaphysical interpretation by denying being, but now

Alan affirms that the Absolute possesses being, which he describes as "ontological

import." I argued that Alan's two-stage dialectic that culminates in the negative moment

was intended to obliterate all (a) logical self-identity and (b) ontological self-

subsistence. I described how the real difference in Alan and I's interpretation was that,

while he identified the transcendentist interpretation of the Absolute (possessing

properties a, b, and c) with the positive moment of naive realism, I contended that all of

the properties (a, b, and c) could be attributed to the Absolute through a critical dialectic

of speculative reason in a synthetic moment which preserves both positivity and

negativity is a self-moving concept. I challenged Alan to defend the ultimate-ness of the

negative moment of the paradox.

Page 12: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

Finally, I showed how the (P) Pinkardian interpretation which reduces the (i) self-

reflective subjectivity of the Absolute to the (ii) inter-subjectivity of the historical human

community crucially depends, for the force of this negative reduction, upon the (Z)

Zizekian dialectic of paradox. Just as thesis (1) could be defeated by defeating thesis (2),

so could the (P) Pinkhardian sociological reduction be defeated by defeating the (Z)

Zizekian dialectic of paradox (e.g. 1 iff 2, P iff Z). I described how the (Z) Zizekian

dialectic of paradox was Hegel's triadic Trinitarian dialectic but an incomplete skeptical

negative dialectic which totally ejected the reason and substance of the positive moment.

Alan committed himself to "bad skepticism" when he wrote: "there are no realities that

persist thus there is nothing for us to think." Just as it is impossible for anything emerge

from nothing, so is it impossible for determinate thought to emerge from the

annihilating negativity of the paradox. Alan hurls all reason and substance into the

empty notion of the abysmal vacuity and seeks to pull them back out again. This may

only be possible if reason and substance subsist in (P) Pinkard's inter-subjective

historical human community. However, because the (P) Pinkardian interpretation of the

Absolute as the inter-subjectivity of the historical human community depends upon the

(Z) Zizekian dialectic of paradox, Alan cannot appeal to (P) Pinkard to justify (Z) Zizek.

Alan's Zizekian dialectic of paradox is no better as a rebuttal to the self-conscious

subjectivity and intentionality of the Absolute, than Schelling's conceptually vacuous

aesthetic intuition of the Absolute - the night in which all cows are black.

***

First Counter-Thesis against the Dualist Interpretation of Hegel

Thank you once again for your thorough response to my criticism of your criticism of

my mathematical hypothesis. I agree that, insofar as we are "each presenting aspects of

our contrasting conceptions of Hegel's absolute," there will unavoidable

misunderstandings and contentions. I hope that I may bring the points of conflict into

sharper relief in the following response. It has become exceedingly apparent that you

and I disagree on no merely superficial and accidental element of our respective

interpretations of the philosophy of Hegel. Rather, we each of us interpret the most

essential element, Hegel's dialectic, in different ways. In each case, the different

interpretation of the essence of thought, finitely and absolutely, conditions an altogether

different interpretation of the accidents in the whole. Saint Thomas Aquinas wrote at

the beginning of De Ente et Essentia (Essence and Existence), that a "small mistake in

the beginning is a big one in the end." Hence, beginning with a small disagreement in

Hegel's Logic we come to an absolute disagreement in our interpretation of Hegel's

Absolute. For this reason, it had been a mistake to begin by analyzing the properties of

the Absolute, as though these hung ready at hand from the branches of a the Tree of

Page 13: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

Knowledge, without having first analyzed the essential origin of these properties in the

essence of Hegel's Absolute, the Logic of Hegel's Dialectic.

Before I begin my reply, I wish to briefly sketch what I take to be the interpretive

traditions in which we each implicitly stand. The Right or Old Hegelians who

personally studied under Hegel and posthumously edited and compiled Hegel's

collected writings in the Hegel Yearbook are generally said to have followed Hegel in

his conclusions of the fittingness of Lutheran Christianity and constitutional monarchy.

Later these original Hegelians were opposed by a younger-generation of student

radicals, Left or Young Hegelians, who intended to employ the dialectical form of

Hegelian philosophy against the received content of Hegelian philosophy. Thus the

interpretive tradition of the philosophy of Hegel has been divided along political lines,

that homologously represents the division of political liberalism into right-

conservatives and left-progressives. Although Hegel was adamantly opposed to sects

and dualities, the bare inert factuality of his philosophical corpus offers little possibility

of resolving the dilemma, as each interpretative pole will claim for themselves

legitimacy according to either the content or the form of the philosophy of Hegel: Right

Hegelians will claim to follow the conclusions, while Left Hegelians will claim to follow

the method of the master.

Admitting this conundrum, I believe it more expedient that our labor of philosophical

exegesis should focus less upon the extrinsic correspondence between an interpretation

and the text, and more on the intrinsic coherence of the interpretation itself. Hence,

while I understand that you have argued about the correspondence of your

interpretation with better informed Hegel scholars than myself, I intend only to argue

for the superior coherence of what I will call my Trinitarian interpretation of Hegel in

relation to what I will call your Dualist interpretation of Hegel (if you would prefer

another designation for your interpretation, I would gladly adopt an alternative

nomenclature). Finally, I must mention that I was puzzled by your off-handed

comment that the "natural misreadings" in which commentators fail to free themselves

from "natural assumptions" "block comprehension" and "characterize most

commentaries" as this statement seems to dismiss most Hegelian commentators: which

interpretative tradition and which commentators do you find common agreement with?

On my behalf, I can identify as standing within the Right Hegelian tradition, which

includes Johann Adam Möhler, Franz von Baader, James Sterling, Emil Fakenheim,

Benedetto Croce, Jean Hyppolite, J.N. Findlay, Cyril O'Reagan, Dale Schlitt, Robert

Pippin and our own beloved Stephen Theron. Without intending any censure, may I

ask which commentators, besides your oft-mentioned references to Slavoj Žižek, you do

find yourself in agreement with? If your interpretation is only consonant with Mr.

Žižek, have you familiarized yourself with the critiques of Žižek, both as a Hegel

Page 14: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

interpreter and as a Hegelian philosophy? [See: Horwtiz, Noah. "Contra the

Slovenians: Returning to Lacan and away from Hegel" (Philosophy Today, Spring 2005,

pp. 24–32] I raise this question of interpretation because I intend to criticize your

reading of Hegel as a systematic misreading of the philosophy of Hegel as it has been

misinterpreted according to the psychoanalytic theories of Mr. Žižek.

The thesis of my criticism is three-fold: (A) first, I follow Horwitz in alleging that you

are interpolating the Zizekian-Lacanian notion of the unconscious in place of Hegel's

unconscious; (B) second, you absolutize this notion of the unconscious as negativity;

and (C) third, the consequence of this interpolation and absolutization of the negation

of consciousness is the absolutization of the unknown object which is known only as

what is unknown, which Fichte calls the non-Ego. The inference follows from the first

thesis to the last thesis: (A) as the Zizekian-Lacanian notion of the unconscious is

interpolated in place of the Hegelian unconsciousness it may assume the role of the

negative in Hegel's dialectic; (B) this negativity is absolutized at the beginning of the

Logic and subsequently in all dialectical sequences; (C) the result of the absolutization

of the negative is a duality between positive and negative thought; which you identify

with the duality between common intellect and speculative reasoning of the paradox; in

which the latter subsumes the negativity of the opposition of the prior moments, the

Kantian antinomies, and yet remains unrealized as a result of the prior interpolation.

This interpretation can be in some sense self-consistent simply because the system of

Hegelian philosophy is presuppositionless, which means also that it entirely

presupposes itself. Hence (A) presupposes (B) just as (B) presupposes (A). The task of

criticism is neither to show that this Dualist interpretation extrinsically contradicts the

Trinitarian interpretation, nor even that this Dualist interpretation intrinsically

contradicts itself (both of these are no doubt true but equally trivial as you applaud

these very contradictions as signs of "thinking the paradox"), but more decisively that

this interpretation fails on its own account to realize the very purpose which it sets for

itself, seeks to achieve, and leaves forever unrealized.

(A)

Please allow me to preface my reply by defining some key terms. First, the word

'intention' means to think rather than to will some object of thought. The Stanford

Encyclopedia of Philosophy explains it thusly:

"Intentionality is the power of minds to be about, to represent, or to stand for, things,

properties and states of affairs... The word itself, which is of medieval Scholastic origin,

was rehabilitated by the philosopher Franz Brentano towards the end of the nineteenth

century. ‘Intentionality’ is a philosopher's word. It derives from the Latin word intentio,

which in turn derives from the verb intendere, which means being directed towards

Page 15: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

some goal or thing... As the Latin etymology of ‘intentionality’ indicates, the relevant

idea of directedness or tension (an English word which derives from the Latin

verb tendere) arises from pointing towards or attending to some target."

Franz Brentano gave a modern formulation to the term in his book "Psychology from an

Empirical Standpoint"(1874):

"Every mental phenomenon is characterized by what the Scholastics of the Middle

Ages called the intentional (or mental) inexistence of an object, and what we might call,

though not wholly unambiguously, reference to a content, direction toward an object

(which is not to be understood here as meaning a thing), or immanent objectivity. Every

mental phenomenon includes something as object within itself, although they do not

do so in the same way. In presentation, something is presented, in judgment something

is affirmed or denied, in love loved, in hate hated, in desire desired and so on. This

intentional inexistence is characteristic exclusively of mental phenomena. No physical

phenomenon exhibits anything like it. We can, therefore, define mental phenomena by

saying that they are those phenomena which contain an object intentionally within

themselves."

'Intention' primarily denotes the mental representation of an object, as the mediating

relation between subject and object of conscious thought. 'Intentionality' differs from

'intention' as an act differs from an activity as the repetition of the intentional relation in

successive moments. Intention and intentionality are thus basic features of

consciousness, which Hegel refers to as the "pure This" of a consciousness relation to an

object, and not a self-reflective volition of some extra-mental object or state-of-affairs.

What is meant by 'intention'; as for instance when I say that it is my intention to write a

response to Alan Ponikvar; is not the same as what is meant by 'intention' for

philosophers. This definition of intentionality as the basic relation between subject and

object of consciousness, prior to any self-conscious volition, will be important later

when intention becomes operational in the Hegelian Dialectic.

Second, the term 'consciousness' has an idiosyncratic meaning in Hegel's philosophical

system, which is speculatively constructed in the section A. Consciousness in the first

three chapters of the Phenomenology of Spirit. Although Hegel appropriates many

philosophical terms, he does so primarily, not to simply import their meaning from

convention, but as vehicles to creatively re-conceptualize their meaning according to the

various relations they assume within the overall architectonic of concepts that is the

system of philosophy. Consciousness is the first major division of the Phenomenology

of Spirit - the introduction to the entire system of philosophy - and accordingly assumes

an altogether different meaning, as it is speculatively constructed in first standpoint of

consciousness, than it may have in either conventional vernacular, or even in

Page 16: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

specialized psychoanalytic theory, psychological research and psychiatric practice. The

meaning of consciousness only comes to be known through the whole sequence of the

dialectical movement through the standpoint of consciousness. Hegel summarizes this

at the beginning of B.IV Self-Consciousness:

"In the kinds of certainty hitherto considered, the truth for consciousness is something

other than consciousness itself. The conception, however, of this truth vanishes in the

course of our experience of it. What the object immediately was in itself — whether mere

being in sense-certainty, a concrete thing in perception, or force in the case of

understanding — it turns out, in truth, not to be this really; but instead, this inherent

nature (Ansich) proves to be a way in which it is for an other. The abstract conception of

the object gives way before the actual concrete object, or the first immediate idea is

cancelled in the course of experience. Mere certainty vanished in favour of the truth.

There has now arisen, however, what was not established in the case of these previous

relationships, viz. a certainty which is on a par with its truth, for the certainty is to itself

its own object, and consciousness is to itself the truth." (PhG §166)

In support of the idiosyncrasy of the definition of 'consciousness' in the philosophy

Hegel, I appeal to two authoritative sources: the first-hand account that Hegel gives in

A.I - A.III of the Phenomenology of Spirit, and the second-hand account of

commentators on the idiosyncratic meaning that Hegel gives to the term. In the first

two paragraphs Hegel defines Consciousness (as much as Hegel defines anything in

fixed non-speculative propositions) as the bare being and immediate object and of

intention:

"The knowledge, which is at the start or immediately our object, can be nothing else

than just that which is immediate knowledge, knowledge of the immediate, of what is...

This bare fact of certainty, however, is really and admittedly the abstractest and the

poorest kind of truth. It merely says regarding what it knows: it is; and its truth contains

solely the being of the fact it knows... Rather, the thing, the fact, is; and it is merely

because it is. It is – that is the essential point for sense-knowledge, and that bare fact

of being, that simple immediacy, constitutes its truth." (PhG §90 and §91)

Hegel again defines Consciousness in the Encyclopedia of Philosophical Sciences:

"Consciousness constitutes the reflected or correlational grade of mind: the grade of

mind as appearance. Ego is infinite self-relation of mind, but as subjective or as self-

certainty. The immediate identity of the natural soul has been raised to this pure

'ideal' self-identity; and what the former contained is for this self-subsistent reflection

set forth as an object." (Enc. §413)

Michael Innwood defines Consciousness thusly in the Hegel Dictionary:

Page 17: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

"Bewusst, a technical term in philosophy and psychology since the eighteenth century,

means 'conscious'. It is used to distinguish conscious mental states and events from

unconscious ones, but in philosophy it primarily indicates intentional consciousness

or consciousness of an object (Gegenstand)... Kant and Hegel use das Bewusstsein

('consciousness', literally 'being conscious') to denote not only a subject's consciousness,

but the conscious subject himself, in contrast to the object of which he is conscious."

Consciousness is thus the simple immediate phenomenological intuition of a uniform

manifold of totally indeterminate being. It is the abstract apprehension of a totally

indeterminate, self-identical and univocal ideal space of mental intuition. The

definitions of intention and consciousness are related to one another as form and

content that mediates between the subject and the object: intention is the form of the

relation of the subject to its object, while consciousness is the content of this relation in

which both subject and object are placed; or, alternatively, it might be said that

intention is the abstract concept of the mediation between subject and object, while

consciousness is the concrete phenomenological apprehension of being.

'Unconsciousness' is (qua 'un' and 'consciousness') then nothing more than the simple

negation of consciousness; i.e. what consciousness is not; what is not simply and

immediately phenomenologically intuited as uniform and indeterminate being. There

is, further, an important difference between negation as opposition and simple negation

(negatio simpliciter): negation of polar opposites is the opposition of things which are

each the contrary of the other, such that to increase the degree of one is to decrease the

degree of the other; while simple negation is the disjunction of things that are unrelated

as opposites. This difference in senses of negation has been expounded by, among

others, Benedetto Croce in the first chapter of What is Living and What is Dead in the

Philosophy of Hegel, and by Thomas Cajetan as a simple contrary as, for example,

between red and black. Thus, unconsciousness is not an alternate mode of

consciousness that is the contrary opposite of consciousness, but rather simply what

consciousness is not, what is altogether other-than consciousness, the bare Fichtean

non-Ego.

I have labored so diligently over the definition of these terms; intention, consciousness

and unconsciousness; because I allege that you have interpolated an alien

psychoanalytic meaning of these terms into your reading of the philosophy of Hegel

(whether this was done willfully or not is irrelevant). The meaning of the

'unconsciousness' that you interpolate is the Lacanian psychoanalytic meaning of

'unconsciousness' that is an opposed mode of consciousness that is submerged below

ordinary conscious thought, like the body of an iceberg below the water-line, which

emerges unpredictably in the course of self-conscious reflection. Where

unconsciousness is for Hegel the simple negation of what is other-than consciousness;

Page 18: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

i.e. the non-Ego; unconsciousness is for you the opposite of consciousness that results in

an original duality of consciousness and unconsciousness: consciousness and

unconscious operate in tandem with to one another; yet only the conscious mind is

immediately known; hence the unconsciousness is the unknown aspect of mind, just as

the non-Ego is the unknown aspect of the Ego; in which the negativity of the

unconscious non-Ego is submerged within the positivity of the conscious Ego. You

intimate this duality when you write:

"As I read the Phenomenology it is a complex exposition of the identity in difference or mutual implication of the reader and his self-alienated other, natural consciousness. The education to the standpoint of science that Hegel speaks about involves challenging the reader to comprehend this most comprehensive identity in difference of two way of thinking, one common and the other speculative. In the end, we are educated when we comprehend that when we are one with the absolute thought involves two views and not just one. We have to learn how to think twice, once as does the common intellect with thought directed to a self-standing thought in view and then again to the thinking of what is in view when what is in view devolves and manifests a dialectic."

Here you appear to identify the "self-alienated other" as the "common intellect" of

"natural consciousness", and the "standpoint of science" as the comprehension of the

"identity in difference of two ways of thinking, one common and the other speculative."

Speculative reasoning subsumes both "ways of thinking" within itself as the identity of

their difference. The "common intellect" of "natural consciousness" is alienated from the

self, from the Ego, from consciousness: it is the opposite of consciousness, the

unconsciousness.

"To comprehend speculatively the reader is shown how thought functions as dual. There is the intentional thought of the common intellect and then there is the cunning of the absolute that appears inadvertently behind the back – behind what is intended but frustrated in act."

Here you explicitly juxtapose the duality of thought as intentional and non-intentional;

conscious and unconscious; as "common intellect" and as the "cunning of the absolute."

One might ask how the Absolute "appears inadvertently behind the back" of "what is

intended" in intentional conscious if there is no consciousness of this cunning. Hegel's

consciousness is all being that is known. Hence there can be no conscious knowledge of

what transpires "behind the back" of consciousness. Whatever else the unconsciousness

is, it is a totally unknown non-Ego. For your psychoanalytic interpolation of

'unconciousness', what transpires "behind the back" of consciousness is always

immanently subsumed under consciousness as merely another aspect of the mind.

Page 19: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

"We are to take to heart this truth: the absolute as it will develop and unfold is not to be found anywhere other than where there is a beating human heart. In fact, we can say two things right off about Hegel's absolute. First, it lies dormant as the contradiction inherent in all that is. And second, it is articulated at the very point when the finite subject comes to a dialectical impasse and ceases to function as an intentional subject."

Prior its recognition in speculative reasoning, the Absolute remains "dormant of the

contradiction [i.e. negativity] inherent in all that is." It is in man but not known to man:

in the "beating heart" but not in the mind's conscious awareness. Intentionality is just

the abstract relation between subject and object of conscious thought. The cessation of

the functioning of the "intentional subject" is then just as much the cessation and

negation of consciousness; consciousness turned around to face its opposite; the

unconsciousness.

***

Second Counter-Thesis against the Dualist Interpretation of Hegel

Thank you for elaborating upon your interpretive distinction between the "dual view"

of consciousness. This helps me to understand how you are reading Hegel. Before I

begin elaborating upon (B) my second counter-thesis, I wish to briefly comment upon

your previous description. I acknowledge this distinction that Hegel frequently invokes

in the Phenomenology of Spirit between consciousness for-itself and for-us.

"Hegel writes so as to keep intentional consciousness and consciousness of the cunning of reason separate. In the Phenomenology this is done by distinguishing what is for consciousness and what is for us. As I have mentioned the education to the standpoint of science involves folding both views into one finite consciousness which is then prepared to enter the system and read what is written speculatively or to read employing a dual view."

I interpret consciousness for-itself as the description of how the consciousness, that is

the phenomenological protagonist, understands the journey of consciousness through

the stages of the dialectic; and I interpret consciousness for-us as a description of how

we, as the phenomenological readers, observe what transpires to, but not for, the

consciousness of the phenomenological protagonist. I call consciousness for-itself a

protagonist because I believe the Phenomenology of Spirit can be read as a Romans-

Bildung, an romantic novel of the coming-of-age of the Spirit, in which consciousness is

the heroic protagonist. I have found it amusing to imagine the narrative as a sort of

modern-day Divine Comedy in which Hegel is both Dante and Virgil: Hegel is both the

naive consciousness for-itself, from the first-person standpoint, and the guide for this

Page 20: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

consciousness, from the third-person standpoint, just as we phenomenological readers

watch on as the audience consciousness for-us.

"Why there are two views rather than one is that there are two ways of focusing our attention. First, we focus on the content as it slips away and then returns only to slip away again. We thus focus on the movement. Second, we can shift focus and attend to the coherent form of the slipping away... What is distinctive to Hegel is that first this ability is divided in the Phenomenology between the reader and natural consciousness. It is not the commonplace ability indicated by simple self-awareness."

Where we may still disagree is on the persisting significance of this "dual view" of

consciousness: to the question of whether this "dual view" is merely a heuristic literary

device meant to provide readers with a ladder to climb up the stages of consciousness

and toss away, or is ultimately constitutive of Hegel's epistemology, I answer the

former while I suspect that you would answer the latter. This interpretive difference,

between duality of views as constitutive hypostatized substance and regulative abstract

heuristic will be the basis of my criticism of your interpretation of Hegel's resolution of

the Kantian antinomies in the second counter-thesis that follows.

(B)

The second counter-thesis is that, in hypostatizing the "dual view" of the opposition

between consciousness for-us and consciousness for-itself, you also hypostatize the

negative opposite of consciousness, which is the unconsciousness; the negative of

consciousness as such. This original opposition between consciousness and what is

other-than consciousness, or between the Ego and the non-Ego, is then retained as the

negative other, the non-Ego, and the negativity of the Paradox, rather than subsumed in

the concept as difference within unity. This duality, of the Ego and the non-Ego, is

abstractly represented in the differing interpretations of the sequence of moments with

which we each describe Hegel's dialectic: where my Trinitarian interpretation present

three moments in the conventional triadic movement (e.g. thesis-antithesis-synthesis),

your own Dualist interpretation presents only two moments, or maximally three

moments that are reducible to two. This difference in our interpretation of the dialectic

will, when absolutized, account for the different interpretations of the Absolute: the

Trinitarian interpretation unites the opposed first and second moments in a third

synthetic moment as equivocal predication is united in analogical predication, while the

Dualist interpretation retains the opposition of the duality of the first and second

moments in an empty identity, which I presume you would exalt as thinking the

negative opposition of the paradox.

Page 21: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

Before turning to your examine your response, please examine Hegel's description of

these speculative moments at the conclusion of the Introduction to the Phenomenology

of Spirit. In §81 Hegel mentions that "it may be useful to say something about the

method of carrying out the inquiry." Starting in §82, Hegel describes the origination of

the contradiction between the "abstract determinations" of the (α) positive moment of

the object in-itself and (β) the negative moment of our knowledge of the object for-us

which together constitute knowledge:

"... Consciousness, we find, distinguishes from itself [α] something, to which at the same

time it [β] relates itself; or, to use the current expression, there is something [β] for

consciousness; and the determinate form of this process of relating [α & β], or of

there being something for a consciousness, is knowledge. But from this [γ] being for

another we distinguish [α] being in itself or per se; what is [β] related to knowledge is

likewise distinguished from [α] it, and posited as also existing outside this relation; the

aspect of [α] being per se or in itself is called Truth..."

In the second quoted sentence of §82, Hegel describes how knowledge is distinguished

within itself into (α) the positive reality of "being in itself or per se" and (β) the negative

ideality of "what is related to knowledge" and "distinguished from it." In §83, Hegel

distinguishes the question of knowledge of (α) the object in-itself, as the naive

correspondence between ideal thought and reality, and the (β) critical knowledge of the

knowledge, as the object that is known for-us:

"If now our inquiry deals with the truth of knowledge, it appears that we are inquiring

what [α] knowledge is in itself. But in this inquiry [β] knowledge is our object, it is for

us; and the essential nature of knowledge, were this to come to light, would be rather its

being for us..."

At the conclusion of §83, Hegel gives a warning against making the essence of

knowledge, the relation of object of knowledge to the subject, an object in-itself, as a

fixed form of knowing, or as a logic of method. This fixed form of knowing, or

methodologism, is (β) the second negative moment of knowing for-us that has been

made into an object, just as (α) the object in-itself makes the first positive moment into

the object of "what is called truth" of the thing-in-itself. In each case, the (α) first

positive and (β) the second negative moment are reified as self-subsistent finite objects.

This reification of each moments as finite objects will later be exposed to be self-

Page 22: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

contradictory, in (γ) the third synthetic moment that exposes the unreality of both in the

process of their mutually related opposition.

In §84, Hegel explains how "consciousness provides its own criterion from within itself"

to overcome the fixidity of any such form of methodologism, by once again

distinguishing (β) the negative ideal relation of knowing for-us from (α) the object itself:

"Consciousness furnishes its own criterion in itself, and the inquiry will thereby be a

comparison of itself with its own self ; for the distinction, just made [α & β], falls

inside itself. In consciousness there is [β] one element for an other, or, in general,

consciousness implicates the specific character of the moment of knowledge At the

same time this “other” is to consciousness not merely [β] for it, but also [α] outside

this relation, or has a being in itself, i.e. there is the moment of truth. Thus in what

consciousness inside itself declares to be the essence or truth we have the standard

which itself sets up, and by which we are to measure its knowledge.

In the final sentences of §84, Hegel appears to confirm what you describe as the

"perspective shift" in which both the first positive moment and the second negative are

united in a bare and simple identity of opposites. However, after affirming that 'both of

these processes are the same' Hegel goes on to describe how the (α) first positive and (β)

the second negative moment both "fall within that knowledge which we are

examining", the totality of knowledge that was first mentioned in §82:

"It is clear, of course, that both of these processes are the same. The essential fact,

however, to be borne in mind throughout the whole inquiry is that both these

moments, notion and object, [β] “being for another” and [α] “being in itself”,

themselves fall within that knowledge which we are examining [§82]. Consequently

we do not require to bring standards with us, nor to apply our fancies and thoughts in

the inquire; and just by our leaving these aside we are enabled to treat and discuss the

subject [γ] as it actually is in itself and for itself, as it is in its complete reality."

The appearance Hegel affirms the equivalency between the two moments in a bare

identity is altogether premature because, in §84, Hegel is describing how "consciousness

furnishes its own criterion in itself" in which the distinctive moment of the (α) first and

(β) second moments "falls inside itself." The criterion that emerges from within

consciousness, and not from brought as fancies of "standards with us", is the

'knowledge' that Hegel has been examining all along; the endogenous (γ) third

Page 23: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

synthetic moment of the dialectic that unites the opposition of the former two within

itself; in the actuality that is "in itself and for itself"; and the "complete reality."

In §85, Hegel juxtaposes the notion and the object, the fixed "criterion" and the object of

"what is to be tested", to describe how the form and the content of knowledge are each

dependent upon the other; for "as knowledge changes so too does the object for it

essentially belonged to this knowledge." To conclude, in §86 Hegel makes explicit,

what had only hitherto been implicit: how (α) the first positive and (β) the second

negative moments together combine in "the new and true object" of (γ) the third

synthetic moment, which is the process that contains the opposition of the former two

as difference within its unity:

"This dialectic process which consciousness executes on itself — on its knowledge as

well as on its object — in the sense that out of it the new and true object arises, is

precisely, what is termed Experience. In this connection, there is [γ] a moment in the

process just mentioned [in §85] which should be brought into more decided

prominence, and by which a new light is cast on the scientific aspect of the following

exposition. Consciousness knows something; this something is [α] the essence or is per

se. This object, however, is also [β] the per se, the inherent reality, for

consciousness. Hence comes ambiguity of this truth [i.e. α & β]. Consciousness, as we

see, has now two objects: one is [α] the first per se, the second is [β] the existence for

consciousness of this per se. The last object [β] appears at first sight to be merely the

reflection of consciousness into itself, i.e. an idea not of an object, but solely of its

knowledge of [α] that first object. But, as was already indicated [in §85], by that very

process the first object is altered; it ceases to be what is per se, and becomes

consciously something which is per se only for consciousness. Consequently, then,

what this real per se is for consciousness is truth: which, however, means that this is

the essential reality, or the object which consciousness has. This [β] new object

contains the nothingness of the first; the new object is the experience concerning that

first object."

Hegel announces that he will make explicit "the new and true object" which is the

"moment in the process" of §85. This new moment is the processing of (γ) the third

synthetic moment that contains the opposition of (α) the first positive and (β) the

second negative moments within its own self-movement. The second moment shows

the abstract untruth of the first, and "contains the nothingness of the first", just as the

Page 24: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

third moment will show the abstract untruth of the second. In the third moment, the

former two are revealed in their abstractness, finitude, unreality and untruth. The

reification of the fixed form of knowing of (β) the second negative moment of knowing

for-us, as methodologism, is shown to be just as self-contradictory as (α) the first

positive moment of "what is called truth", of the object in-itself. Hegel describes (γ) the

third synthetic moment as one that "does not seem to agree with what is ordinarily

understood by experience", the experience that understands only finite objects:

"This moment is the transition from the first object and the knowledge of it to the

other object, in regard to which we say we have had experience, was so stated that the

knowledge of the first object, the existence for consciousness of the first ens per se, is

itself to be the second object. But it usually seems that we learn by experience the

untruth of our first notion by appealing to some other object which we may happen to

find casually and externally; so that, in general, what we have is merely the bare and

simple apprehension of what is in and for itself. On the view above given, however,

the new object is seen to have come about by a transformation or conversion of

consciousness itself."

You contend (colored red) that the "transformation or conversion of consciousness" is

the result of the "futility of finite thought" of "common reason" that opens a hole for the

insight of speculative reason viewed in its "absolute form."

"The futility of finite thought guided by common reason opens a hole which with

insight can be viewed as absolute form. The void or lack of subjectivity is where the

absolute as Hegel conceives it may be thought."

While I entirely agree that the futility of the understanding of common reason results

from its finitude, and consequent inability to grasp the infinite judgment of speculative

reason, I contend that, far from nullifying finite thought in a "hole", "void or lack of

subjectivity", the much of the admittedly finite reality and truth of the α) the first

positive and (β) the second negative moments is taken up into and preserved in the (γ)

the third synthetic moment. Hegel corroborates this when he describes how the form of

(γ) the third synthetic moment is contributed by our intentionality, through our

intentional "way of looking at the matter", in the whole "series of experiences" in a

"scientifically constituted sequence":

Page 25: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

"This way of looking at the matter is our doing, what we contribute; by its means the

series of experiences through which consciousness passes is lifted into a

scientifically constituted sequence..."

Hegel distinguishes between the two views that you have endorsed: the first-person

view of consciousness for-itself and the third-person view of consciousness for-us, the

reader:

"... but this does not exist for the consciousness [for itself] we contemplate and consider.

Hegel then directs our attention back to the exposition of skepticism in §78-79, when

Hegel had previously distinguished between the bad skepticism that ejects the positive

content of what is skeptically negated as an "empty nothing", and the good skepticism

that instead retains the positive content of "what truth of the proceeding mode of

knowledge" that had been skeptically negated":

We have here, however, the same sort of circumstance, again, of which we spoke a short

time ago when dealing with the relation of this exposition to skepticism [§78-79], viz.

that the result which at any time comes about in the case of an untrue mode of

knowledge cannot possibly collapse into an empty nothing, but must necessarily be

taken as the negation of that of which it is a result — a result which contains what

truth the preceding mode of knowledge has in it.

Previously you had contended that the (α) first positive moment contributes nothing to

(γ) the third synthetic moment:

"Common reason sees the senseless dialectic and is ready to come to a skeptical

conclusion: there are no realities that persist thus there is nothing for us to think."

I (colored blue) have previously criticized you for precisely this form of bad skepticism:

"If I am correct in interpreting Alan as thusly ejecting the reason and substance of the

positive moment, then Alan commits himself to the sort of "bad skepticism"

that Hegel describes (colored green) in the Introduction to the Phenomenology of Spirit"

Hegel confirms my criticism to be correct when he describes how (γ) the third synthetic

moment, that is the processing of the opposition of (α) the first positive and (β) the

second negative moments within its own self-movement, assumes this form only by

Page 26: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

subsuming the previous two moments through subsuming the truth and reality of each,

in the process of their mutual sublation that is good skepticism:

In the present instance the position takes this form: since what [α] at first appeared as

object is reduced, when it [β] passes into consciousness, to what knowledge takes it to

be, and the implicit nature, the real in itself, becomes what this entity per se, is for

consciousness [§85]; this latter is [γ] the new object, whereupon there appears also a

new mode or embodiment of consciousness, of which the essence is something other

than that of [β] the preceding mode. It is this circumstance which carries forward the

whole succession of the modes or attitudes of consciousness in their own necessity.

Hegel signals that this is a "new object" of a "new mode of embodiment or

consciousness" (Miller translates this as "a new pattern of consciousness... for which the

essence is something different from what it was at the preceding stage"), which signals

this to be the "new and true object" mentioned in §86, and not either of the opposed and

preceding moments that had previously been exhaustively described.

Previously I described how this dispute turned on the question of how many

conceptual moments there were in Hegel's dialectic: according to my Trinitarian

interpretation this "new and true object" is (γ) the third synthetic conceptual moment

that unites (α) the first positive and (β) the second negative moments within itself;

while according to your Dualist interpretation there are only (α) the first positive and

(β) the second negative moments united by consciousness for-us as the consequence of

a "perspective shift." The difference between these interpretation crucially depends on

this transition between a second and a third conceptual moment. You write:

"The positive moment is the second perspective on the absolute negativity of the cycling. It is the insight into the coherence of this cycling. It is the negativity recollected in its coherence. I am not sure where you intend to find the positive moment. I suspect once again it is the synthesizing third referencing a thought activity that stands apart from what is being synthesized. In other words, it is not activity as immanent but an intentional activity of a subject attending to some matter in view. It is an activity delegated to the common intellect."

You describe how the positive moment of the dialectic is the "second perspective" of

speculative reason which unites the (α) first positive and (β) the second negative

moments in an "absolute negativity of the cycling" as the "negativity recollected in its

coherence." You distinguish the activity of immanent speculative reasoning from its

Page 27: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

negative opposite, the "intentional activity of a subject" of "common intellect." This

distinction between the intentionality of common intellect and the non-intentional

activity of immanent speculative reasoning, or between the activities of consciousness

and the unconsciousness, is contradicted by Hegel's explicit description of the necessity

of our contributing to the (γ) third speculative moment as "our doing,

what we contribute. [viz. the intentionality of consciousness]" Our activity of thought is

intentional simply because in it is maintained the relation between subject and object.

You further describe how this (γ) third speculative moment is nothing other than the

"two moments synthesized" in one:

"Hegel's thought, being immanent, never moves beyond a two as one. There is no third thought; there are simply two views of what the two in one means. There are not two moments synthesized. There are two moments as one that lend themselves to being taken by the common intellect as nonsense and by the speculative intellect as generative of a newfound sense."

The first two moments are understood by "common intellect", and these same two

moments re-imagined by speculative reasoning. You, intend to escape the difficulty of

thought intentionally positing a (γ) third speculative moment by, alternatively,

affirming that there are two speculative moments and two aspects of thought: positive

and negative; and common intellect and speculative reasoning. Then you proceed to

clarify the nature of the positive moment of "the second point of view" of speculative

reason that unite the "moment cycles" of the two moments:

The second point of view on the dialectic is not a mere recognition of the negative movement. It is a recognition that because this movement cycles it is coherent. It subsists as an identity in difference. It is only the ideal moments of this cycle that do not subsist. So rather than dismissing the dialectic as nonsense as does the common intellect we who view speculatively have insight into what coheres. This is the positive moment that you will soon say is missing from my account.

The negativity of the "movement of cycles" is coherent when it is united in the "identity

in difference." How, may we ask, does the negativity of the opposed moments, become

coherent in an identity? Alternatively, we may ask; what is the nature of the identity-

relation between the two opposed moments, and how is this coherent? Recall the

contradiction is traditionally taken to be the universal sign of incoherence, just as

identity is traditionally taken to be absence of difference between two terms. What then

could it mean for the negative opposition of the "movement of the cycles" to become

coherent, i.e. non-contradictory, and identical, i.e. non-different? The crucial difference

Page 28: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

between the Trinitarian interpretation and the Dualist interpretation concerns how the

opposition of the conceptual moments is resolved; either into a third synthetic concept

or as an identity between the cycling of the two discrete moments. You write:

"But I am only able - as you note - to count to two. Three is too many and certainly a community of humans is way too many."

To summarize the differences in our respective interpretations: the Trinitarian

interpretation negates the truth and reality of each of the previous moments just as it

sublates and unites their truth and reality in a third synthetic concept; which while

consisting of neither simply the first or second moment, or both taken moments

together; nonetheless is constituted by the truth and reality of each of the previous

moments, as they have been intentionally transformed by consciousness. Contrary to

this account, the Dualist interpretation denies that any of the reality and truth of the

previous moments persists to constitute a formally distinct third, but rather affirms that

each of the previous two moments remain in their mutual untruth and unreality as they

cycle around one another and just as much ceaselessly contradict one another, in the

paradox of their mutual negativity. You write:

"Hegel's thought is about the identity in difference of being and thought. It is about what

first appears as pure negativity. I have been pounding the table to say that this is the crucial point: the skeptic and speculative thinker have before them the same dialectical movement. The skeptic says that pure negativity means that there is nothing more to think. The speculative philosopher says that this pure negativity is the

infinite movement of the concept. Same content. Two views!"

In this interpretation, neither duality is united in a common third; for the positive and

negative moments of conscious common intellect are together re-imagined in the

negative opposite of consciousness, the unconsciousness of speculative reasoning.

Thus, the duality of the positive and negative moment is altogether transferred,

although not transformed, in the full turbulence of their "negative cycling", to the

unconsciousness, in which this duality persists. You write:

"So the contradictions are not resolved. We never free ourselves from

contradiction. What we do is learn to think the reason appropriate to such

contradictions. We learn to shift from common to speculative reason."

The impossibility of resolving the contradictions means that the negativity of the

dualities is never overcome in a speculative "third thought" because there "are not two

moments synthesized" but rather only two dualities; or two pairs of two; two moments

Page 29: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

in two senses "that lend themselves to being taken by the common intellect as nonsense

and by the speculative intellect as generative of a newfound sense." Consciousness

cannot resolve the contradictoriness of the two moments in a third so the Dualist

interpretation posits yet another duality, the duality of consciousness and

unconsciousness, the unconscious activity of speculative reasoning "behind the back" of

consciousness:

The trauma comes about because the common intellect assumes that when we have the absolute as such before us we can think it. It is the thought that harmonizes our worldview. What Hegel is showing is that this harmonized thought is a fiction of metaphysical thinking. If we attempt to think this thought we find there is nothing to think other than the slipping away of this thought. Our need to disguise the disturbance at the heart of the absolute – our need to convince ourselves that we inhabit a well-ordered universe – is the divine thought that we need to give up. It is nothing but a fiction as shown at the inception of the Logic. The thinker that thinks the reason behind the back of consciousness is identified by Hegel to be the reader.

The unconsciousness of speculative reason cannot be the consciousness for-itself, and

thus must be the consciousness for-us, the reader; and this duality of consciousness is,

on the Dualist interpretation, not merely a heuristic narrative aid to the reader that is

ultimately resolved into the Absolute Idea, but is altogether reified as persisting in the

empty identity of the two mutually exclusive, negating and unreal positive and

negative moments. The duality of consciousness and unconsciousness; of Ego and

non-Ego is then altogether absolutized in the Logic and the entirety of Hegel's system of

Absolute Idealism! The Trinitarian interpretation concludes in a third synthetic

moment that is epistemologically and ontologically enriched to afford to it a greater

truth and reality than either of the two preceding moments, while the Dualist

interpretation concludes in a bare and simple identity that contains the difference of its

mutually undifferentiated moments in the ceaselessly negativity of their empty formal

identity, from which no thought save paradox can emerge like the night in which all

cows are black.

In (C) the third and final thesis, I will argue that the consequence of the interpolation of

the unconsciousness of speculative reasoning, and the absolutization of the negation of

consciousness, is the absolutization of the unknown object; which is known only as

what is unknown and which Fichte calls the non-Ego; as an absolute non-Ego which

ceaselessly negates the absolutivity of what is called the Absolute.

Page 30: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

***

Third Counter-Thesis Against the Janos-Faced Dualist Interpretation of Hegel

Introduction

For every instance of duality, thought demands two should be mediated by a third.

Two things can only be thought to be separate and distinct in and through some third

thing, in which each is joined together with the other. This is the Principle of Mediation

that is the operative principle behind the Platonic-Aristotelian Third Man Argument

and F.H. Bradley's infinite regress arising from the duality of universals and particulars.

This principle had long ago been recognized in the geometrical cosmology of the

ancient Pythagoreans, who affirmed the logical necessity that any dyad should be

mediated by a third within a triad: Alexander Polyhistorius described how Xenophius

of Chalsis "regarded the 'monad' as the beginning of all things. From this the Dyad was

produced and from it numbers, from the numbers points, from the points lines, from

the lines surfaces and from the

surfaces solids." (Eduard Zeller,

Outlines of the History of Greek

Philosophy, p. 89) In Pythagorean

cosmogony, the Monad begets the

Dyad; the Dyad begets the Triad;

then the Triad begets numbers, points and lines; and lines beget the surfaces of

polygons, which beget the solids of polyhedra. The logical necessity of the Principle of

Mediation, both for Pythagorean cosmogony and for Hegelian phenomenology, is the

converse consequence of the impossibility of conceiving any two things without some

mediating relation: whenever two may be conceived together there must ineluctably be

some third relation between the two in and through which each are thought with the

other, and both are apprehended together as a duality within triplicity.

This third mediator may be thought of as something or nothing: as a minimally

substantival Aristotelian quintessesnce or as a totally contentless void. Hegel showed,

in the first part of the Science of Logic, that the concepts of being and non-being,

something and nothing, were the positive and negative moments of the individual

concept of becoming. Positive being and negative non-being are, in their opposed

duality, two abstract concepts that emerge concretely in the third concept of becoming,

through which each are subsumed and mediated in and through the self-particularizing

individual concept. Hegel's logic is trinitarian because the third moment of the synthetic

concept constitutes a fuller being and a richer truth than either the prior moments, of

self-satisfied or self-alienated concepts, or both together, in a formal identity of duality.

Page 31: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

The synthesis of opposites, through which a concept is estranged from and then

reconciled with itself, is the fundamental trinitarian pattern of Hegel's dialectical logic.

Summary of (A) First and (B) Second Counter-Theses

This Trinitarian interpretation of Hegel's logic is opposed to Alan Ponikvar's Janos-

faced Dualist interpretation. In the following, Alan's comments are colored red while

my comments are colored blue. Please allow me to briefly summarize the major points

of the previous (A) first and (B) second counter-theses before I precede to argue (C) the

third counter-thesis: the consequence of dualism is the absolutization of the object that

is known only as it is unknown, which Fichte calls the non-ego.

In (A) the first counter-thesis I contended that Alan had artificially interpolated the

Zizekian-Lacanian psychoanalytic notion of the unconsciousness in place of Hegel's

unconsciousness. I quoted Franz Brentano to define 'intentionality' as primarily

denoting "the mental representation of an object, as the mediating relation between

subject and object of conscious thought." Then I quoted Hegel and Inwood to define

consciousness as " the simple immediate phenomenological intuition of a uniform

manifold of totally indeterminate being. It is the abstract apprehension of a totally

indeterminate, self-identical and univocal ideal space of mental intuition." Finally, I

defined the unconsciousness as the contrary opposite of consciousness:

"The meaning of the 'unconsciousness' that you [Alan] interpolate is the Lacanian

psychoanalytic meaning of 'unconsciousness' that is an opposed mode of consciousness

that is submerged below ordinary conscious thought, like the body of an iceberg below

the water-line, which emerges unpredictably in the course of self-conscious reflection.

Where unconsciousness is for Hegel the simple negation of what is other-than

consciousness; i.e. the non-Ego; unconsciousness is for you the opposite of

consciousness that results in an original duality of consciousness and unconsciousness:

consciousness and unconscious operate in tandem with to one another; yet only the

conscious mind is immediately known; hence the unconsciousness is the unknown

aspect of mind, just as the non-Ego is the unknown aspect of the Ego; in which the

negativity of the unconscious non-Ego is submerged within the positivity of the

conscious Ego."

In (B) the second counter-thesis I argued that the Dualist interpretation was the

consequence of the mistaken hypostatization of this opposition between conscious Ego

and the unconscious non-Ego. I presented three pieces of textual evidence from the

Introduction to the Phenomenology of Spirit (§81 to §86) as evidence against the Dualist

interpretation of the Hegelian dialectic: first, Hegel announces in §85 that he will make

explicit "the new and true object"; second, Hegel describes how this object is contributed

Page 32: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

by an intentional "way of looking at the matter"; and third, Hegel distinguishes between

the bad skepticism, which negated the content of the conceptual moments as an "empty

nothing", and the good skepticism, which retained their positive content as the "truth of

the proceeding mode of knowledge." The new object preserves, through the positing of

conscious intentionality, the reality and truth of the perceiving moment and thereby

implies the Trinitarian interpretation in which "the third synthetic moment negates the

truth and reality of each of the previous moments just as it sublates and unites their

truth and reality," contrary to the Dualist interpretation which "denies that any of the

reality and truth of the previous moments persists to constitute a formally distinct third,

but rather affirms that each of the previous two moments remain in their mutual

untruth and unreality as they cycle around one another and just as much ceaselessly

contradict one another, in the paradox of their mutual negativity."

(C) Third Counter Thesis

The following third counter-thesis will present the speculative origin and absolute

consequences of the dualist interpretation of the philosophy of Hegel, in which the

seminal consequences of the prior theses (A) & (B) will blossom into the deadly poison

of the Janos-faced paradoxical Absolute.

Dualism and Trinitarianism in the Philosophy of Hegel

"Thus, we have my claim: consciousness actualizes a dialectic which it is

unable to comprehend. So the greatest mystery for Hegel's reader is why is it that out

of this dialectic the new true object arises."

The locus of the controversy surrounds what Alan has credibly described as the

"greatest mystery" of the Hegelian dialectic: how may the contrary opposition of theses

be resolved into a form of coherent knowing? The resolution of opposites is a mystery

because classical logic holds that contradictions result in the obliteration of one or both

of the opposed terms (ex falso quodlibet or ex contradictione sequitur quodlibet). Following

Aristotle's prohibitions, contradictions were held to destroy the truth of any proposition

and the conceivability of any concept (See Metaph IV 3 1005b19–20, 24 ,29-30, and IV 6

1011b13–20). In pre-critical philosophy, the fear of the danger of the explosiveness of

contradictions led philosophers (with rare exceptions such as Nicolas of Cusa) to

present systems of deductions whose premises and conclusions were altogether without

contradiction, or non-contradictory. Coherence means simply this: that there are no

contradictions between the premises and the conclusion; or, to say that same thing, that

the conclusion may be predicated as identical to the collective entailment of all of the

premises (e.g. A = A).

Page 33: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

Hegel's dialectical logic is frequently alleged to violate the classical prohibition on

contradiction which is the Law of Non-Contradiction. Rather Hegel should be said to

universalize contradiction by affirming a Law of Contradiction, in which 'all S is

contradictory', in absolute opposition to the Law of Non-Contradiction, in which 'no S is

contradictory'. Hegel does not so much seek to circumvent contradictions as to

instrumentalize their very explosive force within his concepts. This instrumentalization

of contradiction is motivated by a dialectical revolution in logic, beginning with the Port

Royale logic and culminating with Hegel's Science of Logic (See Evald Ilyenkov's

Dialectical Logic, 1974): for Spinoza every determination is a negation and the contrary

opposite of what is determined; for Kant the contradictory paralogisms of the

antinomies obliterate the transcendental conditions of conceivability; and for Fichte the

Ego self-posits all universal laws of logic. Alan and I agree that Kant's antinomies of

reason demonstrated the impossibility of conceiving of an encyclopedic system of

philosophy as a coherent and non-contradictory deduction. The "greatest mystery" of

the Hegelian dialectic is how Hegel conceives of the dialectical emergence of the "new

true object" from the contrary opposition of the prior objects of thought.

Modern philosophy can be viewed as a project to reconcile medieval theology and

modern natural science: the natural sciences presented the spectacle of a lawfully

ordered cosmos from the minutae to the gargantuan, while the theological notion of

truth demanded systematic unity. In Spinoza, this duality appears as that of extension

and thought in substance. In Leibniz, this duality appears as the manifold of intuition

and the windowless monads. From these sources of the infinite and the infinitesimal,

German Idealism inherited both the duality of thought and being as well as the dual

loci of their unity in the Absolute and in the Ego. For Kant, the duality of thought and

being is that of concepts and percepts; and the dual loci of their unity is the idea of God

(the All or omnitudo realitatis, and the most real being or ens realissimum) and the mind's

apperceptive unity. German Idealism sought to reconcile these dualities into a form of

systematic unity and place all conditions in their logical and systematic relations within

and for the unconditioned condition of all conditioned things (See Paul Franks's All or

Nothing, 2005).

The Hegelian dialectic of opposed concepts filially received the inheritance of both the

Spinozist doctrine - determinatio est negatio - of the negative opposite determination of

any single determination (See letter 50 to Jelles); as well as the Kantian antinomies of

reason; in which any determination of a definite deduction is just as much a negation of

some opposite determinable deduction, so that an antithesis is implicit in the positing of

every thesis: as the Kantian antinomies oppose contrary deductions any definite

deduction will be opposed by its contrary resulting in the opposition of possible

deductions which Kant called a paralogism, or a paradox or reason. As these two

Page 34: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

conditions apply to any definite syllogistic deduction, their conjoined effects are

operative in every exercise of reason, regardless of its degree of magnitude and

complexity.

Of course, I deny that such a moment exists because the first and second moments you

reference also do not exist. But leaving that aside for the moment, it seems that this

'synthesis' accomplishes two things at once: it exposes an unreality and it reveals an

identity in difference in its place."

The new synthetic object that emerges from the opposition of the antitheses of the first

and second moment (i) exposes the relative unreality of the former conceptual

moments, and (ii) replaces their mutual contrary opposition with an identity that

subsumes, unites and preserves their differences. The question remains as to the

relative (i) ontological status of these moments and (ii) epistemic nature of the 'revealed'

identity in difference. The Trinitarian interpretation holds the synthesis of opposites to

(i) subordinate the former conceptual moments to a single superordinating synthetic

concept, and (ii) reveals the untruth of the former moments even as it incorporates the

true content of each into the richer truth of the synthetic concept. On this account, the

Hegelian dialectic of opposites generally produces concepts of fuller being and richer

truth with the completion of each dialectical sequence, and may thus be said to

ontologically and epistemologically progress up the via delorosa of Spirit (PhG §77).

The Dualist interpretation denies any ontological and epistemological progress, and

contends, contrary to the whole purgative spiritual trajectory of the Trinitarian

interpretation, that the Hegelian dialectic ends no better than it had begun; in the

negativity of mutually contradictory conceptual moments, and exalts this totally empty

identity of mutual contradiction as an "insight" into paradox. Precedents for logical

dualisms are readily discovered throughout all of modern philosophy and especially in

the various systems of German Idealism: Kant opposed equally valid but mutually

contradictory deductions to one another and concluded in a general aporia; Fichte

proposed unconditioned activity of the conscious Ego posited any deduction in

opposition to what was not thought, the non-Ego, and subsequently resolved the

opposed deductions of Ego and non-Ego in an identity of their recursive alternation;

and Schelling absolutized the Fichtean non-Ego as the unconditioned Absolute,

opposed the deductions of conscious to the absolute deductions of nature, and affirmed

the parallel unity of thought and being known through intellectual intuition. Thus

Kant, Fichte and Schelling each reconceived of the dualisms of Kant in different ways:

as antinomies of reason; as Ego and non-Ego; and as consciousness and nature. The

Dualist interpretation is motivated to preserve the negative duality of modern

philosophy; the opposition between theology and substance; Leibniz and Spinoza;

Page 35: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

Jerusalem and Athens; so as to avoid the sacrifice of Cavalry, the speculative good friday,

in which all concepts are negated and systematically united in the Absolute.

Hegelian Hermeneutics

"You seem to suggest something dangerously close to my view. You reference

the third synthetic moment."

The dialectic of opposed theses admits for equally opposed readings. Reading Hegel is

the construction, for consciousness, of the systematic relations of concepts. Every

determinate concept may be abstractly empowered to determine its opposite in one-

sided domination. Thus logical opposition is the condition for hermeneutic opposition.

This is the consequence of the Spinozist doctrine determinatio est negatio, the Kantian

antinomies, and the reversibility of the syllogism (i.e. (S-M-P) = (P-M-S)): determinatio est

negatio demands that every determination of reason has an equally opposed negative

determination; the Kantian antinomies oppose contradictory determinative deductions

to one another; and the syllogism from the subject to the predicate may just as easily be

reversed as a syllogism from the predicate to the subject. Dialectic opposes conceptual

deductions to one another and invites the reader to judge their merit, both intrinsically,

in relation to themselves, and extrinsically, in relation to each other. Just as it is possible

to read Callicles and Thrasymachus as radical subverting Plato's grand Eleatic-

Pythagorean synthesis, so it is possible to read antitheses of contrary opposites in the

system of Hegel as a radical subversion of his grand Spinozist-Boehmian-Kantian

synthesis. In each case, the antithetical reading, which empowers one opposite to

dominate another, is motivated to subvert the prevailing interpretation of the

systematic unity of author's thought in favor of a counter-reading that, in emphasizing

disunity and a-systematicity, endeavors to emancipate an autonomously crafted

reading from the normative constraints of scholarly tradition.

In the philosophy of Hegel the reading that emphasizes the contrary opposition of the

antitheses is the Dualist interpretation, while the reading that emphasizes the systemic

unity of syntheses is the Trinitarian interpretation. Both interpretations acknowledge

that the initial theses of the dialectic are abstract untruths; oppose these theses to their

opposite antitheses; and affirm that the opposition of theses and antitheses reveals the

mutual unreality of the contrary opposites. Yet these interpretations differ on how to

understand the dialectical resolution of this contrary opposition: for the Dualist

interpretation duality is primary and unity is secondary, while for the Trinitarian

interpretation unity is primary and duality is secondary. The interpretations

consequently oppose one another as unity and duality seeking to mutually sublate one

another.

Page 36: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

"The moments of the dialectic are equally ideal. Neither is properly characterized as

positive or negative. In the Logic the common intellect will offer such a distinction. But

the dialectic will reveal this to have been a mischaracterization. The moments are

mutual, expressing the same dialectical identity in difference. There is no third

synthesizing agent that brings these two together. It is because they show themselves

as together in the dialectic that a new point of view is required to break the dialectical

deadlock."

For the Dualist interpretation, each of the opposed conceptual moments negates the

other just as it is negated by the other: each is positive in relation to itself and negative

in relation to the other; or each is both positive and negative as well as neither properly

positive or negative. The mutual relations of 'identity in difference' is no third concept

but merely the self-posited formal identity of two different concepts from the

standpoint of either (e.g. if M is formal identity, and S is the first thesis, and P is the

second antithesis, then S-M-P or P-M-S). The formal identity relation of the conceptual

moments appear to constitute a new concept in which contradictory opposites are

identified, yet this appearance is misleading because the self-posited formal identity is

nothing other than the mediating hypostatized contradiction in which nothing is

posited as something. The positing of nothing is, not a postulate of something

constitutive, but merely the postulate of the Kantian regulative principle of identity.

Hegel describes his system of philosophy as a ladder to the absolute knowledge and the

science of infinite being. The metaphor of the ladder implies a noetic ascent from a

lower to a higher stages of knowing, in which the lower stages are known as they are

sublated within the higher stages. The model of former narrative sections and lower

epistemological stages sublated into later narrative sections and higher epistemological

stages altogether suggests the classical Platonic epistemologico-ontological ascent from

the cave of ordinary knowing to the sunshine apprehension of the forms; in which

thought "passes from the dark void of the transcendent and remote super-sensuous,

and steps into the spiritual daylight of the present." (PhG §177) This ascent is what

Robert Wallace describes as the "vertical dimension" of Hegel's thought, from the naive

certainty of the reality of the phenomena to scientific knowledge of the pure forms of

essences. Hegel writes in the Phenomenology of Spirit:

"Science on its side requires the individual self-consciousness to have risen into this

high air, in order to be able to live with science, and in science, and really to feel alive

there. Conversely the individual has the right to demand that science shall hold the

ladder to help him to get at least as far as this position, shall show him that he has in

himself this ground to stand on. His right rests on his absolute independence, which

he knows he possesses in every type and phase of knowledge; for in every phase,

whether recognized by science or not, and whatever be the content, his right as an

Page 37: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

individual is the absolute and final form, i.e. he is the immediate certainty of self, and

thereby is unconditioned being, were this expression preferred." (PhG §26)

The Trinitarian interpretation of the Hegelian dialectic, as constituting a vertical

Platonic ascent from opinion and appearances to the pure forms of knowing, is

hermeneutically opposed by the Dualist interpretation of this same dialectic as no more

than a horizontal extension of the nothingness of the hypostatized contradiction. The

origin of this hermeneutic opposition is the conceptual opposition between the

univocity and multivocity of contradiction, or of one and many senses in which

contradiction is used. The hypostatic contradiction is the hermeneutic key to unlocking

the labyrinth of the Dualist interpretation; the eye of the storm from which reason may

enter into all sides; which simultaneously mediates, negates and divides all of the

dualisms within the paradoxical absolute.

What an uneducated reader is unable to see when they for instance consider

the bad and true infinite in the Logic is that these are not two distinct

concepts. They are two ways of speaking about the same thought movement.

The bad and the true infinite are ways of thinking rather than ways of speaking.

Thought is not separated from thought as a word is separated from the speaker in

gesticulation. Thought contains itself within itself even as it differentiates itself from

and is likewise differentiated within itself. The bad infinite of the indefinite

prolongation of the separation of thought from itself, in the bare repetition of the

isolated particular which never is resolved back into the self-mediating universality of

thought. The two aspects of the mind's apprehension which the reader sees are

together carried over into the domains of propositional judgment and speech, but

remain immanently mediated within the infinite self-movement of thought. Hegel

describes the understanding thinking the bad infinite in the Encyclopedia of Philosophical

Sciences:

"no doubt thought is primarily an exercise of Understanding; only it goes further, and

the notion is not a function of Understanding merely. The action of Understanding

may be in general described as investing its subject-matter with the form of

universality. But this universal is an abstract universal: that is to say, its opposition to

the particular is so rigorously maintained, that it is at the same time also reduced to

the character of a particular again. In this separating and abstracting attitude towards

its objects, Understanding is the reverse of immediate perception and sensation,

which, as such, keep completely to their native sphere of action in the concrete. It is by

referring to this opposition of Understanding to sensation or feeling that we must

explain the frequent attacks made upon thought for being hard and narrow, and for

leading, if consistently developed, to ruinous and pernicious results. The answer to

Page 38: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

these charges, in so far as they are warranted by the facts, is that they do not touch

thinking in general, certainly not the thinking of Reason, but only the exercise of

Understanding. It must be added, however, that the merit and rights of the mere

Understanding should unhesitatingly be admitted. And that merit lies in the fact that

apart from Understanding there is no fixity or accuracy in the region of theory or of

practice." - Enc. §80

The paradoxical Absolute of the Dualist interpretation is just such an opposition of

concepts that is falsely united by the insight of the faculty of imagination. No sense or

coherence can be made of contradictory opposites without some mediation. Thus the

Dualist interpretation imagines that contradiction itself may constitutively mediate

between the concepts. However, as contradiction is nothing more than the explosive

nothingness of opposed incompossibilities, the conceptual mediation of contradiction is

mistakenly imagined to be constitutive when it is, in fact, merely regulative. The

division of logic into Kantian and Hegelian infects all thought with disease of finitude.

Thus, the paradoxical Absolute is not so much discovered by an insight from the

standpoint of science, as it is continually posited by the imagination as a Fichtean

regulative postulate of what ought to be to make the contradictory opposite concepts

sensibly cohere. To his credit, Alan honestly concedes the indeterminateness, unreality

and inconceivability of the paradoxical Absolute:

"The absolute that transcends the ordinary – the absolute as such – is for Hegel

indeterminate. It appears at the inception of the Logic designated as pure being. The

thought of pure being actually is never thought. Before we can get to this thought we

find that we have been deflected towards nothing. And if we think that nothing is what

is before us we soon learn that before we can pin this thought down it has already

slipped away. All that we have is the negativity of the slipping. That is the absolute as

such for Hegel. So for Hegel, the absolute in all its glory is an unachievable thought.

That is the lesson of the beginning of the Logic."

We may well wonder how Hegel was able to write so many gothic paragraphs about

the indeterminate "negativity of the slipping" that is "unachievable in thought": just as

nothing may ever be said of anything that is not thought, so may Hegel not have

written so voluminously about an absolute nothing. Alan proposes that there is an

esoteric mode of reading the writings of Hegel, that justifies the Dualist interpretation

by remaining caught in the deception of the concepts exoterically written by Hegel:

"Interpretive readings will often say more than what is evident on the page... You like

every commentator are caught in Hegel's deception... Here we reach the height of

Hegel's deception... We then learn why Hegel cannot simply come at his readers with a

Page 39: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

direct presentation of science. It baffles his readers because they are in no position to

alter their natural assumptions about knowledge. Here Hegel briefly really says what

will happen. And no one seems to know what to make of this... Unfortunately, for

Hegel's readers they are only able to view what happens as does consciousness. It is for

this reason that when they first come upon this passage as we all did at one point it

reads as pure nonsense. It makes no sense unless one has been educated to the

standpoint of science... It is a deception that an educated reader will have to unravel."

The defense of the Dualist interpretation from esoteric reading crucially depends upon

the duality of the common intellect of consciousness and the speculative reason of the

unconsciousness. The "natural assumptions about knowledge" of the common intellect

are frustrated by the contradictory antinomies of reason, yet, from the educated

standpoint of science, speculative reason reveals these contradictions to be the absolute

paradox of science. The requirement that one be "educated from the standpoint of

science" betrays the explicit intentions of the The Phenomenology of Spirit to guide the

reader to the standpoint of science, for this requirement makes The Phenomenology of

Spirit altogether hermeneutically dependent upon The Science of Logic and The

Encyclopedia of Philosophical Sciences, even as it is presented as a prolegomena to them.

The consequence is a hermeneutical circle which the reader can neither tentatively enter

into nor successfully resolve; and which recapitulates the same bad infinity of the

closed-circle of Fichtean subjective idealism. On the contrary, Hegel explains the

systematic place and meaning of The Phenomenology of Spirit in the Introduction to The

Science of Logic:

"In the Phenomenology of Mind I have expounded an example of this method in

application to a more concrete object, namely to consciousness. Here we are dealing

with forms of consciousness each of which in realizing itself at the same time resolves

itself, has for its result its own negation — and so passes into a higher form . All that is

necessary to achieve scientific progress — and it is essential to strive to gain this

quite simple insight — is the recognition of the logical principle that the negative is

just as much positive, or that what is self-contradictory does not resolve itself into a

nullity, into abstract nothingness, but essentially only into the negation of

its particular content, in other words, that such a negation is not all and every

negation but the negation of a specific subject matter which resolves itself, and

consequently is a specific negation, and therefore the result essentially contains that

from which it results; which strictly speaking is a tautology, for otherwise it would be

an immediacy, not a result. Because the result, the negation, is a specific negation, it

has content. It is a fresh Notion but higher and richer than its predecessor; for it is richer

by the negation or opposite of the latter, therefore contains it, but also something more,

and is the unity of itself and its opposite. It is in this way that the system of Notions as

Page 40: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

such has to be formed — and has to complete itself in a purely continuous course in

which nothing extraneous is introduced." - Hegel, The Science of Logic, § 62

A Dualist Psychology

"the choice of 'unconscious' to designate what is enacted by consciousness but is for us

is probably a bad choice of words... Consciousness is aware of the dialectic it brings

into being but interprets it as a failure to know... the common and speculative are

simply two points of view. They both see the same dialectic but interpret it

differently. 'Unconscious' is too weighty a word to employ to get this point across. That

is why I prefer the intentional/inadvertent distinction to describe this situation."

The Dualist interpretation divides Hegelian psychology into two views or two aspects:

intentional conscious common intellect and inadvertenent unconscious speculative

reason. Intentionality is the simple relation of subject to object in consciousness. Thus

the negation of intention, i.e. inadvertency, is just as much the negation of

consciousness, or the unconsciousness. The Dualist interpretation of consciousness

ideally posits its object of dialectic and "brings it into being" but does not know it.

Speculative reason knows the dialectic that the consciousness of common intellect has

created. Both aspects of the mind apprehend the same object, yet speculative reason

knows it more truly than the understanding of common intellect. Were the object truly

united in the "same object" then the Dualist interpretation would be a triad of common

intellect, object, and speculative reason, such that the same object would be seen by

both aspects and mediate between the opposed aspects of mind. Such a dualism of

psychological aspects then conceptually collapses into the Trinitarian interpretation of

moments of consciousness. To avoid this consequence, the Dualist interpretation can

avoid the reduction to the Trinitarian interpretation by absolutizing the duality of mind

in the duality of the paradoxical Absolute.

"Second, I still want to maintain that you reference a synthesizing activity that never

takes place... What I wish to assert is that dialectics frees what appears from that of

which it means to be an appearance. In Hegel's language, it is appearance qua

appearance. As such, we have appearance that can now be viewed in two distinct

ways."

Alan denies the possibility of an ultimate synthesis of opposed concepts, and, in place

of this synthesis, presents the Scotistic doctrine of un-instantiated accidents, or pure

appearances. Appearance qua appearances can mean nothing else than the

appearances which have as the summation of their qualities to be appearances. For

Duns Scotus the phenomenal appearances of a thing, like the unconsecrated Eucharistic

host, can possibly be individuated from their essential ground in the substance of the

Page 41: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

thing-in-itself: through God's direct intervention in the Eucharistic sacrifice, the

substance of the host comes to consubstantially locate the body of Jesus Christ

simultaneously remains located in the host and in Heaven (viz. bilocation). Lewis

Caroll satirized the Scotistic doctrine of pure appearances with the lingering appearance

of the Cheshire Cat in Alice in Wonderland. Alan seems to believe that this doctrine is

necessary to explain the view of speculative reason of the negativity of paradox,

because the void resulting from an absolute paradox is nothing at all; hence all of the

appearances are appearances of nothing, or appearance qua appearances by themselves.

That is the whole point of a dialectical exposition. It shows how the breakdown of

common thinking/knowledge frees thought from treating what appears as an

instrument or medium for the unimpeded access to what is true. It frees thought from

the singular gaze so that what is in view can be viewed from two distinct points of

view. This is only possible when thought ceases to intend and becomes dialectical.

Alan describes how dialetics "frees thought from the singular gaze... to be viewed from

two distinct points of view" negates the truth of unilinear apprehension to become dual

apprehending, and yet mistakenly holds the Trinitarian interpretation to affirm the an

"unimpeded access to what is true", i.e. the direct realism of things-in-themselves of

sense-certainty. Having progressed through the dialectic of (A.I) Sense-Certainty and

(A.II) Perception, through the Trinitarian interpretation holds, not that the direct

realism of sense-certainty should be re-affirmed, but that both moments should be

synthesized in (A.III) Force and Understanding. The Dualist interpretation, on the

contrary, affirms that the self-contradictoriness of the first and second moments "frees

thought" from direct realism so that "what is in view can be viewed" under the dual

aspects of common intellect and speculative reason. Notice that Alan affirms that the

object of apprehension for both aspects is "in view" even before it "can be viewed" by

the mind, which suggests there to be a real and not merely apparent object of dialectic,

which can only be the paradoxical Absolute. Finally, Alan affirms that thought

becomes dialectical only when it "ceases to intend." Hence, thought under the aspect of

speculative reason is held by him to be non-intentional, opposed to consciousness and

altogether unconsciousness. The psychological dualism of conscious, Ego and non-

conscious non-Ego was presented by the subjective ideas J.G. Fichte. Hegel criticizes

Fichte's dualism of intentional consciousness and inadvertent unconsciousness in the

Lectures on the History of Philosophy:

"ordinary consciousness as the active ego finds this and that, occupies itself, not with

itself, but with other objects and interests, but the necessity that I [intentionally] bring

forth determinations, and which determinations — cause and effect, for example, —

lies beyond my consciousness: I bring them forth instinctively and cannot get behind

Page 42: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

my consciousness. But when I philosophize, I make my ordinary consciousness itself

my object, because I make a pure category my consciousness. I know what my ego is

doing, and thus I got behind my ordinary consciousness. Fichte thus defines

Philosophy as the artificial consciousness." - G.W.F. Hegel, Lectures on the History of

Philosophy, Pt. 3, Section 3, C.1

The Dualist interpretation reproduces this Fichtean dualism between active intentional

ordinary consciousness and inadvertent non-intentional unconsciousness "behind...

ordinary consciousness." The philosophic striving of ordinary consciousness to get

behind and negate consciousness is, for the dualist interpretation, the emergent

breakdown of ordinary consciousness through dialectical self-contradiction. What is

called speculative reason is the distinct point of view that results from this contradiction

of consciousness and unconsciousness. The contradiction of all thought and all truth is

what becomes known through the Hegelian dialectic as "identity in difference":

"We have Hegel giving a preliminary account of the contradiction inherent to the truth

of a particular form of consciousness. The knowledge actualized then is revealed to

correspond to Hegel's preliminary account. The split inherent to truth becomes the

split revealed in actual knowing as the dialectical identity in difference."

For the Dualist interpretation, truth is the self-contradictory duality of concepts, split

and divided between themselves, self-posited together in formal identity, as an

"identity in difference." For the Trinitarian interpretation, the ostensible contradiction

of the first and second conceptual moments are intentionally incorporated into a third

synthetic concept with greater reality and richer truth. The thesis and the antithesis are,

together with their differences, each incorporated into a common concept and self-

identical truth. For the Dualist interpretation, on the contrary, the difference between

the contradictory conceptual moments remains only as real and true as they have each

been united in a merely formal identity of mutual cycling. Thus, for the Trinitarian

interpretation, difference is subsumed within identity, while, for the Dualist

interpretation, difference subsumes identity. Alan explains that for the Dualist

interpretation "the truth" is that the "contradiction is absolutized" in the "absolute form"

of the identity of contradictory opposites:

"The contradictory two in one that Hegel exposes is actualized as a dialectical knowing

that for us is a speculative identity in difference. The contradiction is actualized as

absolute form. This is the truth."

How can contradiction be absolutized if contradiction is nothing? Contradiction must

be hypostatized in thought; its inherent explosive nothingness must be made something

for thinking. The hypostatization of the contradiction is the motive and mediator of the

Page 43: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

Hegelian dialectic which connects mind to the Absolute. The Absolute is opposed by its

contradictory opposite, just as consciousness is opposed and contradicted by

unconsciousness; an absolute non-Ego erected to oppose an absolute Ego in a cycling

duality, an eternal "tarrying with the negative", that may never be resolved to reach any

end. In Plato's Thaetetus Socrates juxtaposes the idealist philosopher 'friends of the

gods' with the materialist philosopher 'titans' and describes how each school of

philosophy battles ceaselessly as though partaking in a never-ending wrestling match:

"... for little by little our advance has brought us without our knowing it, between the

two lines, and unless we can somehow fend them off and slip through, we shall suffer

for it, as in the game they play in the wrestling schools, where the players are caught by

both sides and dragged both ways at once across the line." (181a)

The Trinitarian and Dualist interpretations of the philosophy of Hegel recapitulate the

titanomachy between the idealist 'friends of the gods' and the materialist 'titans', for the

Trinitarian interpretation of the Hegelian system philosophically mediates between the

minds of men and the Absolute, while the Dualist interpretation of the Hegelian system

just as absolutely abolishes the possibility of philosophical mediation, shatters the paths

to Mount Olympus, and leaves only a vacuous chasm between the mind and the

paradoxical absolute. For the Trinitarian interpretation, the Absolute mediates all

differences by a self-identical synthetic concept which simultaneously enriches its truth

and elevates its reality. For the Dualist interpretation, the Absolute is mediated only by

the hypostatized contradiction between the formally united contradictory opposites.

The former interpretation enriches and elevates the concept while the latter

interpretation announces the contradictoriness of the opposed yet formally united

concepts, precludes any vertical ascent from mind to Absolute, and nullifies the truth

and reality of philosophical science.

"what is original for consciousness is the transparent identity of certainty and truth in

actual knowing. What happens is that this actualization elicits an unintended split

that appears as the dialectical cycling that blocks knowledge and indicates a

breakdown of knowing. A transparent identity breaks up into moments that cycle

seemingly to no purpose. What is intended is replaced by this non-intentional seeming

nonsense."

On the Dualist interpretation, the contradictions of the first and second conceptual

moments "elicits an unintended split" viz. their mutual contradiction of the other

moment; a contradiction which simultaneously motivates their mutual cycling and

'blocks' consciousness's intentional knowledge of its object. Yet this split of

consciousness is a separation rather than a reconciliation and consequently is not

sufficient to account for any resolution of the aporia of the mutually opposed

Page 44: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

conceptual moments. The Dualist interpretation concludes in the self-satisfaction of this

aporia which it idolizes as the absolute paradox, while the Trinitarian interpretation

progresses the dialectic even further. The mysterious power of insight is to account for

the knowledge of the aporetic paradox that concludes the Dualist interpretation. The

veil of mystery that obfuscates insight is torn asunder once it is recognized to be merely

the Schellingian mental faculty of intellectual intuition. Here Alan responds to the

criticism in (B) the second counter-thesis that the insight of speculative reason is really a

hypostatized negative opposite of consciousness, i.e. the unconsciousness:

"This dialectic which you here call the hypostatized negative opposite of consciousness

[i.e. unconsciousness] is not subsumed in the concept as difference within unity. This

hypostatized negative is the bad infinite that is the endless cycling of ideal

moments. But when properly viewed this very same hypostatized negative is the true

infinite. One appearance; two views. This is the thought that I am challenging you to

think. I contend that it is the thought that most closely accounts for what Hegel actually

presents."

Alan concedes the negative opposition between consciousness and the unconsciousness;

or alternatively between the thesis and the antithesis; to be the "bad infinite that is the

endless cycling of ideal moments", but further contends that this is also the "true

infinite" of the paradoxical Absolute. Hence, is shown to result in both the Dualist

interpretation results in both self-contradiction and a bad infinity of endless ideal

cycling. I had suggested this at the conclusion of (B) the second counter-theses when I

wrote that "I envisage Alan's dialectic to never advance beyond tarrying with the

negative in a bad infinite of negating the positive moment." Alan seeks to escape from

the thorns and bushels of this criticism into the rarefied clouds of speculative reason.

Hegel predicted that such a dialectic that did not escape from the Kantian antinomies of

the understanding would cycle in just such a bad infinite that could never achieve

knowledge of the infinite ideas:

"If no advance is made beyond the abstract negative aspect of dialectic, the result is only

the, familiar one that reason is incapable of knowing the infinite; a strange result for-

since the infinite is the Reasonable it asserts that reason is incapable of knowing

Reasonable” - Hegel Science of Logic, Miller trans. § 68

The bad infinite of the endless ideal cycling of conceptual moments seems to proceed

onward in an infinite series, as though to fulfill reasons purpose, the bad infinity, but in

fact turns reason back upon itself, into its own self-made aporetic enigma which, by this

ceaseless cycling, never escapes from within its own self-enclosed circuit to fulfill the

absolutely unlimited freedom of reason. Alan seeks to justify the speculative

perspective upon the bad infinity of the dualist interpretation by distinguishing

Page 45: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

between the two aspects of mind as classical logic that adheres to the Law of Non-

Contradiction and a logic that does not adhere to this prohibition, but rather "seeks

insight" into the truth of the emergent Absolute:

The basic distinction [of common intellect and speculative reason] is between a logic

that adheres to the law of non-contradiction and thus seeks to grasp truths as realities

and one that does not and instead seeks insight into the truth as the emergent absolute

form of idealized moments. Like Kant, all consciousness is able to see are the

antinomies made evident in the dialectic. Hegel looks at the antinomies and sees truth.

These are the two views, the first negative or skeptical and the second positive or

speculative.

For the Dualist interpretation consciousness is limited by the Kantian prohibition of

metaphysical reasoning beyond the contradictory paralogisms of the antinomies, while

speculative reason is, in some way, unlimited and spreads its wings like the Owl

Minerva with Hegel's dialectic far above the crumbling deductions of classical logic.

There is a great chasm between the two aspects of mind which no finite deduction of

classical logic may ever bridge. Yet in its purview the unconsciousness of speculative

reason is able to look the contradictory antinomies in the full negativity of their

paradoxical cycling and see the truth. Moments of mind emerge in dual pairs: "first

negative or skeptical" and second "positive or speculative." Alan then accounts for how

the Dualist interpretation explains how the unconsciousness of speculative reasoning

inadvertently achieves the synthesis:

"The first and second moments are engendered for the first time when they appear as

ideal within the dialectic. The synthesis is not intentional but an inadvertent

achievement of a misguided consciousness attempting to avoid the split in its actual

knowing. As you say, it is what is exposed."

I have previously defined the term intentionality as "the mental representation of an

object, as the mediating relation between subject and object of conscious thought."

Intentionality is an essential property of conscious thought. Hence, all conscious

thought is necessarily intentional thought, and all non-intentional thought is non-

conscious, or unconscious thought. It cannot be objected that the Dualist interpretation

does not describe its own notion of non-intentional speculative reason in this way as the

unconsciousness, for this is precisely the point of the present criticism. The (B) second

counter-thesis criticized your Dualist interpretation for implicitly dividing

consciousness from unconsciousness according to the oft-repeated dualism between the

intentional consciousness of common intellect and the non-intentional insight of

speculative reason. Moreover, the opposition between consciousness and

unconsciousness follows immediately from the standard definition of intentionality as

Page 46: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

an essential property of consciousness: the negation of intentional consciousness is just

as much a negation of consciousness as it is the unconsciousness.

"For the common intellect or natural way of viewing things first we need to expose the

error. For the speculative way of viewing things the supposed exposed error is the

truth."

This duality between exposed error as error, and exposed error as truth, can partly be

explained by Alan's insistence that the contrary opposition of the first and second

moments is a repetition of the Kantian antinomies, which he describes as the "the split

in actual knowing" that exposes common intellect to error. On this Dualist

interpretation, each conceptual moment is, like the Kantian antinomies, a valid

deduction of reason, which may be opposed to an equally valid deduction, so that their

individually valid conclusions must mutually contradict one another, in a paralogism of

reason. However, Alan further maintain that Hegel resolves this ostensibly

inconceivable paralogism through an inexplicable "perspective shift" to a "speculative

way of viewing things" in which the very same mutually contradictory paralogism is

revealed as a coherent and cycling paradox. On this account the duality of

consciousness and unconsciousness is itself simply a duality between Kantian and

Hegelian logic of concepts: the first two contrary opposed conceptual moments are

interpreted as mutually paralogistic Kantian deductions, while their speculative

resolution is interpreted as a Hegelian paradox of 'identity-in-difference'. This division

between the Kantian and Hegelian logics is hermeneutically problematic because the

distinction between the first and second moments and their mutual resolution is never

conceptually isolated from previous conceptual moments of the wider philosophical

system. Whereas for Kant all judgments float in relative indifference, for Hegel all

judgments find an absolute place in and through the systematic coherence of the

Absolute idea. The relation of all concepts is intrinsic and essential to the Absolute

Idea. Each of the conceptual moments subsumes within itself, and operates upon the

presupposition of, all of the moments of the preceding stages of being and

consciousness. For example, the first moment of Desire in B. Self-Consciousness

subsumes within itself and operates with the presupposition of the entire preceding

stage of consciousness of A. Consciousness, for there can be no self-conscious desires

without conscious intentionality. Hence, any attempt to isolate and divide the

conceptual moments; as conscious and unconscious or Kantian and Hegelian; is bound

to be exposed as mutually inconsistent caprice when the concepts are cut open and

found to contain all of the preceding conceptual stages; so that the Kantian

consciousness will contain Hegelian unconsciousness just as the Hegelian

unconsciousness contains Kantian consciousness and each is intrinsically the other.

Neither the first and second conceptual moments can be said to be simply Kantian

Page 47: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

common intellect nor can their mutual resolution be said to be simply Hegelian

speculative reasoning; for each is intrinsically contained within and identical with the

other; neither is exorcizing the Hegelian speculative reason from the Kantian common

intellect, the unconsciousness from consciousness, any more plausible than the

Cartesian dualism of mind and body, which equally attempted to tear the animating

principle of the whole organism from within its corporeal embodiment. Rather than

any such duality between static Kantian conscious intellect and dynamic Hegelian

unconscious speculative reasoning, every concept must be thoroughly Hegelian,

speculative and syllogistic; both in its infinitesimal intension and in its infinite

extension. The unity of consciousness and speculative reasoning is the only way in

which the concepts may be mutually sublating and absolutely cohering in a system of

philosophy. The system may be conceived as either finite static determinations for

ordinary understanding or as the infinite self-movement of speculative reason, yet the

thought of each remains within and through itself. To affirm the contrary is to produce

a-systematic and unreasoning schisms throughout Hegel's entire system of philosophy.

Alan affirms such an original duality of consciousness and unconsciousness, as the

results of dualisms throughout Hegel's broader system, when he describes the

"contradiction inherent in the truth object":

"What consciousness intends is that knowledge and object are transparently one and

never two in a true knowing. What we have now [in speculative reasoning] is the truth

of knowing as a two in one that is the dialectical identity in difference. This truth

reflects the contradiction inherent to the true object. Thus contradiction may expose

consciousness but it also exposes the truth, the contradiction that correlates with the

dialectic."

On the Dualist interpretation, the intention of the conscious subject to know the

transparent unitary object is deceived in the intention of knowing the object, for "the

truth of knowing" is, not one, but "two in one": what was thought to be one is in fact

two non-identical concepts that are united in self-posited formal identity which Alan

calls "identity in difference." The difference in identity is the mutually contrary

opposition of the conceptual moments that results from the dualisms throughout the

contradictory system that Alan celebrates as the true paradox of speculative reasoning.

The absolute paradox is at once the hightest illumination and bleakest subterfuge of the

Dualist interpretation, for its dualisms and contradictions are the mistaken consequence

of the dogmatic original dualism between consciousness and unconsciousness, and

between the Ego and the non-Ego, that results in a paradox that does not cohere but

remains totally incoherent, self-contradictory and altogether intellectually self-

destructive. The absolutization of contradiction between the Ego and the non-Ego is not

Page 48: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

any grand paradox but rather a monstrous suicide of reason in which nothing is

thought but the totally vacuous positing of formal identity.

On Dialectical Logic

Hegel often describes organic concepts through the metaphor of seeds and plants. For

example, Hegel writes: "[T]he great necessity in Philosophy is to possess one living

Idea; the world is a flower which is eternally produced from one grain of seed." The

Trinitarian interpretation of exhaustive dynamism is consonant with this embryonic

metaphor but the Dualist interpretation of merely extrinsic dynamism is not. The

embryo is the synthesis of the gamete cells of spermatozoa of the father and the ova of

the mother, and each of these cells is negated upon their mutual copulation: nucleic

meiosis totally dismembers their very DNA and RNA strands and afterwards

recombines each together. Thus the child is born through the negation and synthesis of

the reality and truth of the parents. Parents are thus present within the child as abstract

concepts of their essential genetic inheritance. However, on the Dualist interpretation

we would be compelled to presume just the opposite: the parents would be presumed

to continue to exist as static miniscule persons within the child, like the pre-formationist

homunculi of 16th-Century alchemy!

The Dualist interpretation seeks to reduce the synthetic moment of the Trinitarian

interpretation into the naive realism of the first moment, so that it may be sublated

during the first moment of the Dualist interpretation. This interpretation may seem

plausible simply because every non-Absolute synthetic moment of a syllogism begets

the first moment of a further opposed syllogism viz. determinatio est negatio. The Dualist

interpretation intends to further demonstrate that this alternation of opposed

determinations progresses neither epistemologically nor ontologically, but cycles in an

eternal and totally empty paradox. For the Dualist interpretation there is indeed

nothing new under the Sun: every synthesis is just as much a thesis as an antithesis and

never moves beyond this mutually negating contradiction. Hence, Alan challenges the

Trinitarian interpretation to explain the very necessity of the contradictory moment of

the dialectic:

"why is this gap exposed and shown to be a contradiction? Why isn't there just a

series of demonstrations of how consciousness is unable to match what is for

consciousness with what is in itself? That is, why does a dialectic appear rather than a

failed comparison between the positive and negative moments. That is, if consciousness

examines itself – makes the comparison itself – then why isn't this failed comparison

what we see in the exposition?"

Page 49: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

The gap or negation, that is shown in the progression of the Hegelian dialectic is

necessary to motivate the concepts own self-movement. The concept must move itself

to resolve its own intrinsic contradictions. Because of the self-negation of any finite

determination that was made explicit in Kant's presentation of the antinomies of reason,

no simple series of demonstrations will suffice to describe what is for consciousness and

in the concept. The self-movement of the concept is necessary because consciousness

must come to know; through the full depth, despair and suffering of "tarrying with the

negative"; how each and every positive and negative moments are intrinsically self-

contradictory. It is not enough for the concepts to be compared to one another as a

merely extrinsic finite static objects, for each of the concepts must be related to one

another through the mediation of a third: the finitude of each concept, indicates that,

through this mutual comparison, they are each finite and self-contradictory just as each

contradicts the other. Hegel describes these two problems of the Kantian antinomies in

the Science of Logic:

"True, Kant's expositions in the antinomies of pure reason... do not indeed deserve any

great praise; but the general idea on which he based his expositions and which he

vindicated, is the objectivity of the illusion and the necessity of the

contradiction which belongs to the nature of thought determinations: primarily, it is

true, with the significance that these determinations are applied by reason to things in

themselves; but their nature is precisely what they are in reason and with reference to

what is intrinsic or in itself. This result, grasped in its positive aspect, is nothing else

but the inner negativity of the determinations as their self-moving soul, the principle

of all natural and spiritual life." - Hegel Science of Logic, Miller trans. § 68

The necessity of the contradiction that essentially belongs to thought determinations is

also the inner negativity of the self-moving spirit. Spirit must be self-moving if it is to

develop from within and through itself, rather than from without and through another.

Plato described in the Sophist how the explosive force of negation can generate

movement:

"Then we must admit that motion is the same and is not the same, and we must not be

disturbed thereby; for when we say it is the same and not the same, we do not use the

words in the same sense. When we call it the same, we do so because it partakes of the

same in relation to itself, and when we call it not the same, we do so on account of its

participation in the other, by which it is separated from the same and becomes not that

but other, so that it is correctly spoken of in turn as not the same." (Sophist, 256a-b)

The difference between the same in-itself and the same for-others is the negation of sense

of the same as intensive and extensive. Motion is the result of the negation of the

Page 50: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

concept that is the same and the not the same, that is negated between two senses,

which when equivocated is this semantic difference united in identity. Both the Dualist

and the Trinitarian interpretations of Hegel's dialectic agree that a contradictory

moment is necessary for the concept to be resolved by its own intrinsic self-movement,

yet each disagree on the nature and consequences of this contradictory moment.

"In effect, we have an organic unity or a unity of dynamic moments. A contradiction

references static moments. So for Hegel what subsists as true only does so as the

moments as ideal do not subsist. The difference of respect folded into Hegel's thought

is between the dynamic and static conception of truth. Both are moments of a

speculative truth. Only if there is a perishing is there a persistence."

The identity-in-difference of the first and second moments is without a doubt organic

and dynamic. Hegel inherits the doctrine of the hylozoism, in which all concepts are

living, from the influence of Schelling's Naturphilosophie. The Trinitarian and Dualist

interpretations diverge both on the nature of this identity-relation and as to the degree

of difference afforded by it: the Trinitarian interpretation holds the dynamism of the

concept to be exhaustively dynamic with no perpetually static parts, while the Dualist

interpretation holds the dynamism of the concepts to be, not intrinsic to the content of

the first and second conceptual moments, but rather the mere cycling mutual

contradiction of independently static determinations. The Dualist interpretation thinks

of the Absolute like a pair of diploid cells, in which the individual organism is divided

within itself into two distinct yet adjacent cells which each possess the full set of nucleic

chromosomes. The nucleic chromosomes signify the essence of the organism, while the

diploids signify its intrinsic division into two essentially self-contained parts. The

Trinitarian interpretation holds that this pair of diploid cells is not essentially self-

contained, but rather is essentially related to the whole dynamic organism. The reason

for absolute dynamism of the concept is that any perpetual static immutability of a

conceptual moment must result in its causal independence in relation to Absolute;

independence is division; division is negation of the infinite becoming of the Absolute;

and this negation entails that both the Absolute and the conceptual moment are

mutually finitized contrary to the unity and absolutivity of the Absolute.

The conceptual moments are also essentially preserved rather than annihilated in the

dynamism of the conceptual synthesis. In an absolute sense the preservation of the

concepts is only abstract, for the previous conceptual moments are intrinsic within the

conceptual synthesis as abstracta of the real concrete concept. The Hegelian doctrine of

the essential preservation of the sublated conceptual moments is a development of John

Duns Scotus's doctrine of formal distinctions: between the distinctions among real

substances and the distinctions among ideal imaginings, there is a third distinction;

midway between reality and ideality; between real substances and their formal

Page 51: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

essences. For Scotus allows for substances to have many essences but only one

haecceitas, (the ultimately individuated this-ness of the thing in-itself) and it is this one

haecceitas that ultimately individuates and unites the substance for Scotus, just as it is

the conceptual synthesis that unites the substance for Hegel. For Hegel, abstract

moments of concrete concepts are just like Scotus's formal distinctions of essences from

real substances: one concrete concept has many abstract conceptual moments, just as

one individuated substance has many essences. Thus, just as essences are for Scotus

intrinsic within real substances, abstract conceptual moments are for Hegel intrinsic

within all concrete synthetic concepts. For example, in the Phenomenology of Spirit

(A.I) sense-certainty and (A.II) perception are both abstract conceptual moments

essentially contained within the (A.III) understanding of (A) consciousness, just as (A)

consciousness and (B) self-consciousness are essentially contained within (C) reason.

The Dualist interpretation denies that the conceptual moments are exhaustively

dynamic, and contends, to the contrary, that they are each preserved as mere static

deductions of finite understanding and "common intellect." Each of the deductions is

conceived to be a discrete individual concept that contains a series of propositions and

inferences within itself: the propositions are the matter and the inferential relations are

the forms that together constitute the individual concept. Each of the opposed concepts

essentially contradicts the other in virtue of their contradictory conclusions which

produces the explosive negativity of their mutual cycling. The dynamism of the

concepts in there relation of identity-in-difference is thus a totally extrinsic relation of

their mutual contradiction, rather than an intrinsic differentiation and re-combination in

a thoroughly united synthetic concept. For the Dualist interpretation conceives of the

static concepts as Kantian deductions and dynamic Hegelian concepts. Each concept

extrinsically negates the other as a consequence of their mutually contradictory

conclusions.

"Another way to put this is that this negativity is not what you are calling

the difference within unity. It is not subsumed. It is the difference that

is unity. We do not move beyond difference. We see difference differently."

Alan confirms that the difference of the concept is altogether not subsumed but remains

a difference of opposition of dual of discrete ideal moments. Whatever unity there is

does not really exhaustively negate the opposed moments, for the moments remain

unsubsumed.

"What I propose Hegel means here is what I have been saying all along: the

nothingness of the first object – the dialectical identity in difference of the object's

inherent contradiction – is the truth about this object, a truth that is new and comes to

be posited as the new object for a new form of consciousness. The dialectical downfall is

Page 52: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

also a new truth. One experience of consciousness; two points of view on what this

experience means."

The nothingness of the contradiction, inherent to the first object of consciousness among

the mutually contradictory paradoxical cycling of the opposed concepts, is the

purported truth of the Dualist interpretation of the Hegelian dialectic. The one

experience of the paradoxical object gives meaning to the two aspects of the mind. In

the previous counter-thesis (B) I asked:

"How, may we ask, does the negativity of the opposed moments, become coherent in

an identity? Alternatively, we may ask; what is the nature of the identity-relation

between the two opposed moments, and how is this coherent? Recall the contradiction

is traditionally taken to be the universal sign of incoherence, just as identity is

traditionally taken to be absence of difference between two terms. What then could it

mean for the negative opposition of the "movement of the cycles" to become coherent,

i.e. non-contradictory, and identical, i.e. non-different?"

Alan answered:

"We do not judge what consciousness reveals. We just note that whether we focus in

on one moment or the other each exhibits the same dialectic identity in difference. So

in Perception if we begin by taking the thing as what is a being for self or whether we

begin by taking the thing as a being for another what we get in the end are simply two

ways of expressing the same truth: the two mutually implicate. This is the identity

relation when two moments mutually implicate. The identity is the coherence of the

cycling through moments."

Alan distinguishes between intentional judgment and non-intentional noting of the two

aspects of the mind. Both aspects of mind are said to "mutually implicate" one another,

in which to 'implicate' means to be involved in or to be causally related to. Hence, both

aspects of mind are held to be mutually causally related. How are the two opposed

moments causally related to one another? Alan answers that this mutual causation of

implication is the identity relation. However mutual causation supposes some prior

non-identity of the agents of causation; for whatever is no simply self-caused must

cause an effect in what is other-than and non-identical to itself; and the non-identical

agents relate to one another not through identity but only through their mutual effects

upon one another. Alan has repeatedly affirmed that there is never any synthesis of the

two agents of causation, or the two objects of the first and second moment of the

dialectic. Thus there is an identity between the different conceptual objects.

"So the cycle does not become coherent. It is coherent because it cycles."

Page 53: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

Alan affirms, as though anticipating this argument from the non-identity of mutually

causing agents, that the cycle of the agents' mutual causation is also an identity-relation

that only becomes coherent for speculative reason, even while it is not coherent for

common intellect. This interpretation is plausibly suggested by Hegel, yet this response

affirms, contrary to dualism, the Trinitarian interpretation in which there is a third

synthetic moment of identity that is itself irreducible to duality of the former two

conceptual moments: if the first and second objects of the Hegelian dialectic are

thoroughly united in some further identity, then this self-same identity of the former

two objects can be nothing other than the third synthetic conceptual moment of the

Trinitarian interpretation. The Trinitarian interpretation accounts for the former two

conceptual moments as essentially preserved abstract moments of the concrete synthetic

concept. The Dualist interpretation cannot simply account for both the real identity of

the former two conceptual objects without also simultaneously denying their non-

identity? Two cannot be one any more than one can be two, without a contradiction. If

Alan both denies and affirms the identity of the two objects then he commits a

contradiction, but if Alan chooses to affirm the real identity of the two objects then he

must also affirm the third synthetic moment of the Trinitarian interpretation. With the

former option the Dualist interpretation violates the law of non-contradiction and is

totally incomprehensible to our common understanding, while with the latter option

the Dualist interpretation is subsumed within the Trinitarian interpretation, which may

without contradiction explain both concrete identity and abstract non-identity among

concepts. Hegel describes this same problem of identity and dualism for Fichte's self-

positing Ego:

"The first proposition [of the self-identical Ego] must be simple, in it predicate and

subject must be alike; for were they unlike, their connection — since in accordance with

their diversity the determinations are not directly one — would have to be first of all

proved by means of a third. The first principle must thus be identical." - G.W.F. Hegel,

Lectures on the History of Philosophy, Pt. 3, Section 3, C.1

Unless the mind is a simple self-identical proposition, i.e. Ego = Ego, then it is unlike,

not alike, and non-identical. If the mind is a non-identical duality then, lest it cascade

into schizophrenic duality, it requires some third principle to unite the non-identical

principles. The Platonic principle of the One over Many applies in this way to the old

Platonic problem of the Third Man: any set of many things that are alike in any way

must, to be alike have a principle that is common to all things; just as for any duality

between the individual man and the idea of man there must be an idea of a 'third man'

that mediates between them. This principle and this problem of Platonism were first

systematically addressed by the Neo-Platonic philosophy of Proclus, who influenced

Hegel through the medieval mysticism of Ekhart and Boehme. The principle of One

Page 54: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

over Many is applied to the problem of the Third Man, by the doctrine of intrinsic

relations of all terms, and by the essential relatedness of all things in A.III

Understanding. Hegel holds that all thought and existence are syllogistic and

Trinitarian: just as the syllogism has a subject, a predicate, and a mediating copula; and

the Trinity has the three persons of Father, Son and Holy Spirit; so does Hegel's dialectic

have a thesis, an antithesis and a synthesis. Upon this principle of the Trinitarian

dialectic are all dualities resolved into an absolutely synthetic and systematic unity.

Benedeco Croce writes this about opposed dualisms in the first chapter of What is Living

and What is Dead in the Philosophy of Hegel?:

"Opposition gives rise to deep fissures in the bosom of the philosophic universal and

of each of its particular forms, and to irreconcilable dualisms. Instead of finding the

concrete universal, the organic whole of reality which it seeks, thought seems

everywhere to run against two universals, opposing and menacing each other. In this

way, the fulfilment of philosophy is impeded; and since an activity which cannot attain

to its fulfilment, thereby shows that it has imposed an absurd task on itself, philosophy

itself, the whole of philosophy, is menaced with failure. "

Hegel describes the Fichtean dualisms between the Ego and the non-Ego for which

there is no "third thought" to synthesize the duality of the Ego and its opposite:

"This Notion [being as such], which is immediately actuality, and this actuality which is

immediately its [Ego's] Notion, and that indeed in such a way that there neither is a

third thought above this unity [of Ego and non-Ego], nor is it an immediate unity

which does not possess difference, separation, within it, is the ego; it is the self-

distinction of opposites within itself. That whereby it distinguishes itself from the

simplicity of thought, and distinguishes this other, is likewise immediately for it; it is

identical with, or not distinguished from it." -ibid.

For Fichte, as for the Dualist interpretation, the distinction of opposites within the self is

not resolved in any further conceptual synthesis but is merely reaffirmed in the

immediate individual thought that retains the non-identity of contradictory concepts in

the appearance of self-posited conceptual unity. Any dualist interpretation must thus

affirm the former lemma which concedes that the Dualist interpretation is, at least for

the understanding of the common intellect, self-contradictory, and deny the latter

lemma in which the Dualist interpretation is subsumed within the Trinitarian

interpretation, by contending that, even in spite of self-contradiction, only speculative

reason may have "insight" into the paradoxical Absolute. Alan intends to flee from the

wreckage of the understanding into the salvific insight of self-contradictory speculative

reason. The (C) third counter-thesis argues, that, even if Alan affirms that the Dualist

Page 55: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

interpretation escapes the self-contradiction of identity and non-identity by contending

that the paradoxical Absolute is known through the intellectual intuition of "insight",

then the Dualist interpretation will nonetheless suffer from Hegel's criticism of

Schelling's identity-philosophy, in which the identity of non-identical concepts is an

empty, non-conceptual, and unintelligible relation between concepts; nothing other

than an immediate imagined self-posited identity-form among non-identical concepts -

the night in which all cows are black.

On the Nature of Contradiction

A small mistake at the beginning is a big mistake at the end. All of the dualisms of the

Dualist interpretation originate from a mistaken univocal understanding of

contradiction, in which contradiction is thought of as negating its object in just the same

way without regard to the specificity of its object. Only that which in some sense exists

may be spoken of with the same, i.e. univocal, reference, for reference directs thought to

that which exists and never to that which does not exist. Hence, if the notion of

contradiction is univocalized then this notion must in some sense exist. Aristotle and

Plato held negation to crucially depend upon the prior positivity of the object that is

negated. The nature of the objects confer to negation this specific sense in which it

negates its object. Negation is not a self-subsistent separate Platonic form which self-

exemplifies as negation negating itself, but rather only exists insofar as it negates what

already exists. This is the asymmetry of being and non-being, positing and negating

that the Eleatic Stranger elaborates in Plato's Sophist. As negation negates according to

its object, and the sense in which all objects are spoken of differs according to the nature

of the object, so must the sense in which negation is said to negate differ according to

the object which is negated. Hence, this understanding of negation and contradiction is

multivocal because it holds these to be used in many different ways according to the

nature of whatever is negated. For example, the negation of a proposition (e.g. ¬ P)

differs from the negation of a numeral (e.g. -1) just as propositions differ from

numerals.

Contrary to this, the Dualist interpretation understands contradiction to negate all

objects in a manner that is univocal and indifferent to the content of the object negated.

Contradiction is conceived of as subsisting in-itself prior to whatever it contradicts.

This conception of contradiction may only be possible on the assumption that negation

and contradiction have some existence which is altogether prior and independent to

what is contradicted and negated. Contradiction is a form of the mutual

incompossibility of propositions. According to Aristotle's Prior Analytics, contradiction

only explodes the mutual possibility of opposed propositions (e.g. All cows are black

[i.e. All S is P] and no cows are black [i.e. No S is P]). The philosopher writes: “It is

impossible for the same thing to belong and not to belong at the same time to the same

Page 56: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

thing and in the same respect” (Metaph IV 3 1005b19–20) Negation is more general than

contradiction, for negation applies universally to terms, propositions, substances and

concepts (e.g. All cows are not black [i.e. All S is not-P]). Consequently, where two

propositions which are mutually affirmed and denied in the same sense necessarily

contradict one another, two terms, substances or concepts that are affirmed and denied

do not necessarily contradict one another, but only possibly contradict according to the

time, thing, and respect in which they are negated.

The subtle distinction between negation and contradiction has been woefully obscured

by the influence of nomimalism in Stoic, Late Medieval and contemporary Analytic

philosophy (See J.M. Bochenski's Formale Logik, 1956 and Paul Redding's Analytic

Philosophy and the Return of Hegelian Thought, 2007). The nominalization of formal logic

has resulted in the indifference of negation and contradiction to the proposition that is

negated and contradicted. Once contradiction and negation are conceived of as self-

identical and self-subsistent names, then they can be conceptually atomized and

isolated from the existence and reason of the Absolute. Nominalism consequently

hypostatizes the syncategormatic functions (e.g. v, &, ¬, =, etc.) as concepts that float in

the air, distinct from any application to categorematic terms and propositions (e.g. dog,

Socrates, Sun etc.) just as Platonism hypostatizes categorematic predicates as universal

forms or Platonic Ideas. For the Dualist interpretation, the syncategormatic function of

negation is hypostatized as the univocal nothingness of contradiction. Hypostatization is

the conceptual combination of form and matter, in which form is the universal structure

while matter is the ground of subsistence: sublime Kant used the term hypostatization to

describe how abstract categories of the Understanding may be capriciously reified; that

is, wantonly fixed as the concrete ground of thinking without any critical or

transcendental justification. For example, Kant holds Isaac Newton to have

dogmatically hypostatized the pure intuitions of space and time as the substantive

ground of all celestial mechanics and motion. So similarly does nominalism hypostatize

the syncategorematic functions, and the dualist interpretation hypostatizes the logical

function of negation along with its species of universal propositional negation which is

contradiction.

The nominalization of and univocalization of contradiction is attractive to the common

intellect because of the simplicity and expediency of employing the fixed concept of

negation indifferently to what is negated. Nominalism wrenches concepts from their

absolute place and systematic relations, holds them aloft as fixed names, and tosses the

concept into free floating thought as it is beheld in their lonely finitude by the

Understanding. The Dualist interpretation adopts the nominalist hypostatization of

negation and contradiction because, even in spite of protestations to the contrary, this

interpretation follows the letter rather than the spirit of the encyclopedic philosophy of

Page 57: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

Hegel: according to the letter of his texts, we are led to understand that the master uses

the same words, of contradiction and negation, in the same univocal sense; but

according to the spirit of his philosophy, speculative reason has insight into the

multivocal sense in which these words are used according to the many different objects

of negation and contradiction. The Trinitarian interpretation follows this spirit and

apprehends negation as it applies to the speculative proposition in many different and

multivocal senses. Contradiction of sense-certainty is contradiction in a different sense

than contradiction of being, simply because what is contradicted differs as sense-

certainty and being; from the perspective of the subject as well as from the standpoint of

the Absolute.

The hypostatic fixed concept of contradiction is essential to the Dualist interpretation

for it alone mediates and unites both aspects of mind: consciousness and

unconsciousness. Mediation require something that is common to both terms of a

syllogism (e.g. S-M-P). Alan has repeatedly insisted that on the Dualist interpretation

neither consciousness nor intention are common to both conscious common intellect

and unconscious speculative reason. For instance, Alan explains that the dialectic is

itself subsistent and intrinsically coherent:

"For us this dialectic is what subsists or coheres. It is the new truth. We only provide a

recollective insight into what consciousness has brought into being."

Dialectic is a method of discourse that brings forth the implicit contradiction within and

between arguments. Its operating principle is contradiction. Contradiction is, in-itself,

the nullifying explosion of two mutually incompossible propositions (e.g. P & ¬P).

How then may dialectic be understood to subsist in and by itself? If dialectic is

essentially contradictory, and contradiction is explosive nothingness, then dialectic also

is nothingness. Nothingness is opposed to substance, as non-being is opposed to being,

as negation is opposed to positing. To assert that dialectic is self-subsistent is then to

contradict the essential ontological status of dialectic, and hold that nothing is

something. Just as dialectic is contradictory and hence nothing, so similarly is dialectic

incoherent: what coheres is that which has an identity relation between the premises

and the conclusion, or alternatively that which is mediated between subject and

predicate; but because dialectic is essentially contradictory it is necessarily non-identical

and incoherent. How, then, may the Dualist interpretation hold what is essentially

nothing and incoherent to be subsistent and coherent? Alan will no doubt appeal to the

mysterious faculty of speculative reasoning, but this will not suffice for him to escape

from this contradiction: a faculty of speculative reasoning which cannot be made

intelligible to the understanding of common intellect is nothing more than the empty

name: it is not the infinite aspect coupled with the aspect of finite thinking, but the

Page 58: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

empty identity of disunited modes of knowing held together by the barest formal

identity of their mutual imagining, which is an aesthetic intuition.

Absent of any speculative escape, the Dualist interpretation may only intelligibly hold

the self-contradictory belief that the dialectic is mediated by contradiction, if it holds

that contradiction to be hypostatized, as a self-subsistent and self-cohering contradiction.

Without mediation, the two aspects of mind remain totally separated: an unmediated

dualism is not in any way united in a third term but is left entirely disunited in

complete duality; the absolute separation of one term from the other; between which

lies only the unsearchable chasm of the infinite void. Alan insists, however, that there is

a perspective shift of a logical transition from the intentional consciousness of common

intellect to the non-intentional unconsciousness of speculative reason and, presumably,

back again. This transition requires some medium through which the former may pass

over into the latter, just as Aristotle required a universal medium of prime matter to

permit the complete transformation of one substance to another, and Leibniz required

some common property between two distinct substances, for without a medium there

can be no relation. With no relation there is can be no logical transition from common

intellect to speculative reason or back again. The problem of the relation of disunited

objects is the greatest difficulty that Parmenides raises for Plato's Middle Period Theory

of the Forms in the Parmenides (133a). Contradiction is the form of nothingness (nihil)

that results from the mutual incompossibility of two existentially opposed propositions.

Hence, contradiction must in some sense exist if it is to provide the mediation required

for the transition between the common intellect and speculative reason. When

contradiction is conceptually hypostatized it is supported by the matter of thought to

becomes something altogether more than nothing, for it is posited by thought in the

manner of the self-positing of Fichtean subjective idealism.

The nature of the hypostatized contradiction for the Dualist interpretation is

mysterious, for since contradiction is nothing and hypostasis is something it would

seem as though no self-subsistent contradiction could be thought. If we were to scour

the widest geographic breadth and plunge the deepest archaeological depths of

philosophy might we, even with the clearest eyes and most discerning vision, ever

discover such a notion? There is one idea in the archaeology of philosophy which

matches the description of contradiction given by the Dualist interpretation. It is just as

soon inconspicously found as it is forgotten within the most unlikely of texts. In Plato's

Phaedrus, Socrates describes the ungenerated self-movement of the soul just as the

Dualist interpretation describes the hypostatized contradiction:

"First, then, we must learn the truth about the soul divine and human by observing how

it acts and is acted upon... Only that which moves itself, since it does not leave itself,

never ceases to move, and this is also the source and beginning of motion for all other

Page 59: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

things which have motion... But since that which is moved by itself has been seen to be

immortal, one who says that this self-motion is the essence and the very idea of the

soul, will not be disgraced. For every body which derives motion from without is

soulless, but that which has its motion within itself has a soul, since that is the nature

of the soul; but if this is true,— that that which moves itself is nothing else than the

soul,—then the soul would necessarily be ungenerated and immortal. " (245c-246a)

The ungenerated soul moves itself from within the self-motion of the simple idea. The

hypostatized contradiction is, in just the same way, a self-moving simple idea that is the

"source and beginning of motion for all other things which have motion." The

hypostatized contradiction must exist in some way if it is to impart motion; for just as

prior positivity precedes negativity so must a substance actual exist if it is to cause any

movement from potentiality to actuality. The hypostatized contradiction is self-moving

because it is contradictory. Contradiction imparts the negation of its nothingness to the

negativity of movement between alternating states of being and non-being (Sophist,

256a-b). Hence the self-contradiction within a substance is also the self-movement of a

substance. For Hegel, the Ego's subjectivity is its own self-contradiction, that motivates

the process of its becoming; towards the actualization of its essence and the

determination of the concept. The Absolute is substance become subject. Thus Hegel

affirms the Law of Contradiction, in which all finite substances are self-contradictory, so

that he may consequently affirm that all substances are subject, self-moving, and free.

Subjective consciousness is self-contradictory consciousness. However, the Dualist

interpretation does not predicate self-contradiction of a unitary consciousness, but

rather holds the simple idea of the hypostatic contradiction apart from the mind in an

original duality: when the hypostatic contradiction is applied to mind it divides mind

in two, as intentional conscious and non-intentional unconsciousness; when the

hypostatic contradiction is applied to thought it divides thought into the two thinking

modes of common intellect and speculative reason; and finally when the hypostatic

contradiction is applied to the Absolute it absolutely and endlessly divides the universe

within itself in the ceaseless schisms of an absolute paradox. The hypostatic

contradiction is the common term that mediates between all of the dualisms of the

Dualist interpretation: consciousness and unconsciousness; common intellect and

speculative reason; and thesis and antithesis. Contradiction is the great chain of

nothing that unites the loftiest firmament of the paradoxical absolute to the uttermost

foundation of totally indeterminate non-being in a grand syllogism of the nothing that

nothings its own nothingness.

Contradiction is constituted by nothing in and of itself, yet for the Dualist interpretation

contradiction serves the regulative function of mediating between all of the dualisms

once it has been hypostatically postulated by and with the being of thought: thinking

Page 60: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

postulates the hypostatic contradiction by imparting its own intellective being into the

bare concept of the nothingness of contradiction. The Dualist interpretation must

necessarily postulates the hypostatic contradiction for there to be any possible

conceptual self-mediation of the many dualisms. The necessity of the postulate makes

the Dualist interpretation essentially Fichtean. In the philosophy of Fichte, both the self

and the Absolute, subject and object, consciousness and unconsciousness, are

ceaselessly posited. The ceaseless postulation of hypostatic contradictions is the self-

positing activity, i.e. positivity, of the Fichtean Ego, while the paradoxical Absolute is

the absolute form of what is posited, the object of intellection, and the absolute non-Ego.

The Dualist interpreter is the lonesome Fichtean self that gazes into the starry heavens

above while possessing all the riches of moral law within. The hypostatic contradiction

is the engine of the ceaseless contradiction of both the Fichtean ego and the non-ego of

the paradoxical absolute. Yet because contradiction is univocal, it contradicts every

stage, object and part of the absolute in just the same way, and produces the very same

dualisms in and throughout every substance. Consequently both the mind and the

Absolute become divided within themselves: when the hypostatic contradiction is

applied to the mind it divides mind into the two aspects of intentional conscious

common intellect, and non-intentional unconscious speculative reason; and when the

hypostatic contradiction is applied to the Absolute it similarly produces self-subsistent

absolute for common intellect, and the paradoxical absolute for speculative reason. For

both the mind and the Absolute the two aspects are united by and through the

mediation of the hypostatic contradiction, which is nothingness made something

through the artifice of thought.

Meontotheology

The Trinitarian and Dualist interpretations differ on the epistemological and ontological

consequences of the dialectic: where the Trinitarian interpretation holds that the minds'

synthesis of opposite conceptual moments produces a richer truth and fuller reality, the

Dualist interpretation holds the same to result in a non-intentional perspective shift

behind the back of consciousness into an insight of unconscious speculative reason. The

non-intentional perspective shift is the transition from intentional conscious common

intellect to non-intentional unconscious speculative reason mediated by the hypostatic

contradiction. The purported insight of unconscious speculative reason is Schelling's

intellectual intuition, in which the mind intuitively self-posits the formal identity

between subjective being-for-self and objective being-in-itself. For the Trinitarian

interpretation, the mind intentionally mediates between the opposed conceptual

moments as each intrinsically contradict themselves, recoil into the other, and are

synthesized together; while for the Dualist interpretation, it is the nothingness of the

hypostatic contradiction which mediates between the opposed moments, divides mind

Page 61: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

and absolute within themselves, and motivates the transition from conscious intellect to

speculative reason that reveals the paradoxical Absolute. For the Trinitarian

interpretation the consequence of the dialectical movement is the richer truth and fuller

being of the synthesis of the opposed concepts, while for the Dualist interpretation the

consequence is merely a revelation of the paradox and nothingness: the former

constructs an infinite scientific system, while the latter abolishes all finite ontological

phantasms. Alan explains how the opposition of the conceptual moments is

engendered, or made to come into existence, by the agency of the hypostatic

contradiction, and affirms that this identity between the opposed moments pre-exists

the dialectic, even as it is "made evident" by attending to the "dynamic identity" in

difference of the dialectic:

"First, the opposition is not retained; it is engendered. And second, the

identity is not empty but already is an identity in difference. All that is

required of us is that we shift from the common way of attempting to grasp a

self-standing identity to attending to the dynamic identity made evident in

the dialectic."

For the Dualist interpretation contradiction is conceived of as a univocal hypostatic self-

moving being; that mediates between subject and object, intellect and reason, and mind

and absolute; just as it divides altogether them in the same obliterating nothing. The

hypostatic contradiction contradicts its object in same universal and univocal manner,

from the greatest to the least, engendering schisms throughout the absolute extent of

thought and being. Then the univocal hypostatic contradiction of the Dualist

interpretation contradicts thought thinking itself, just as it contradicts thought opposed

to thought, with the universal negation of mutual obliteration. The engendering of

schisms is the negative moment in which contradiction negates and alienates substance,

while the mutual obliteration of opposites is the positive moment in which the

externality of contradiction is resolved back into its own barren nothingness. The

alternation of schism and mutual obliteration is the dual alternation of negative and

positive moment that continues without end in a bad infinite of eternal repetition (e.g.

+,-,+,-,+,-...). There is no third moment to escape from this bad infinite and speculative

reason is no more than a cynical insight into the Sisyphean banality of this pitiless

oscillation. Thus, the Dualist interpretation of dual aspects of mind, antithetical

moments, and contradictory deductions, is just as much a monism of uniform

nothingness: the univocal hypostatic contradiction reduces all being to non-being even

as it divides being into non-being; so that every contradiction is once again resolved

into the very nothingness from which it subsequently re-emerges, like Saturn devouring

his own children. Where the Trinitarian interpretation affirms that the Absolute

Page 62: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

produces itself from within itself and thinks its own thought, the Dualist interpretation

affirms only a nothing that nothings its own nothingness.

The Trinitarian interpretation saves Hegelian philosophy from this abyss of infinite

nothingness through the intentional positing of a third synthetic moment. The negative

opposition between the conceptual moments is retained as the dynamic self-movement

within the synthetic concept: both of the opposed conceptual moments are intrinsically

and mutually contradicted, broken asunder, and their components are reconstituted

into a new organic unity. The synthetic concept is more than the sum of its parts

because it contains, not merely the former opposed moments, but also the oppositional

relations of each of the preceding conceptual moments within itself and to one another.

Just as for Aristotle matter is actualized through form, so is for Hegel the bare univocal

being of basic concepts actualized through the essence which emerges from the intrinsic

self-contradiction of each and all prior conceptual moments. The combination of these

formal oppositional relations and the matter of the conceptual moments altogether

constitute the dynamic new synthetic concept. The emergence of form and essence

require some prior form and some prior essence. For Aristotle the thought-thinking-

itself - noēsis noēseōs noēsis - is the form of all forms - Forma Formarum - which brings

primordial matter to its fullest actualization, while for Hegel the Absolute idea

intrinsically contains all being and essence as abstract conceptual moments; is

intrinsically at the beginning what it will be at the end; "the circle which presupposes its

end as its purpose" (PhG §18); and determines the actualization of Nature according to

the providential and the providential unfolding of the Spirit of history. The Dualist

interpretation, on the contrary, understands the original principle; which

simultaneously motivates, resolves and reveals concept to thought, to be the mere

nothingness of hypostatic contradiction that nothings its own nothingness.

Consequently, for the Dualist interpretation, the Hegelian dialectic does not lead the

mind on a noetic ascent to the pure knowing of the Absolute idea, but is no more than

an insight that reveals the originary nothingness of the infinitely cycling absolute

paradox. Alan explains that the contradictory nothingness at the end of the dialectic is

just what it always had been since the beginning:

"Initially it [i.e. consciousness] expects the unessential moment to fall away. It does not

bring together what stands apart. When its knowing is true, there is the presumed

identity. If knowing is false an unwanted distinction is made evident. When this

distinction arises consciousness judges that it has failed. We in contrast do not judge.

We [i.e. speculative reason] simply attend to the coherent movement as the new

identity – the new object."

Speculative reason attends to the distinctions between the conceptual moments

engendered by intentional consciousness, as the purportedly coherent cycling

Page 63: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

movement of the new self-identical object. The distinctions of the preceding conceptual

moments are the many contradictions between, within and throughout the opposed

concepts. The disunited mass of opposed concepts neither obliterate one another in

mutual strife, nor eject their opposites from the concept, but altogether mutually cohere

in the cycling identity of the new object. How is this new identity established and the

unity maintained? Neither the individual concepts in-themselves nor the oppositions

between concepts for-the-other will suffice; for the concepts are essentially related only

to themselves and only accidently related to others, while the opposition between the

concepts can be no more self-identical than the mutual negation of each by the other.

Only the hypostatic contradiction can simultaneously mutually negate the opposed

conceptual moments and resolve them together in a "new identity - the new object."

This most contradictory of contradictions does indeed arise "behind the back" of the

understanding of consciousness and common intellect, for the understanding could

never comprehend either the nature of the self-identical contradiction, nor how what is

intrinsically explosive nothingness may unite explosively opposed concepts.

"... the new and true object is the process in its entirety. You speak of a processing but

do not identify the processor. Hegel says that the process is what consciousness

exercises upon itself. It is inadvertent to what consciousness intends."

The Trinitarian and Dualist interpretations each hold the "new and true object" to be, in

some sense, a process that contains the previous conceptual moments in the motion of

their reciprocal contrariness: the contrary opposition of the first and second conceptual

moments simultaneously unites them and propels the internal motion of the concept.

The subject of the process, or the "processor", is disputed. There are at least three

potential subject processors: "(i) in the intentional subjectivity of the Absolute which is

what we call God; (ii) in the inter-subjective human community which Hegel calls

Spirit; or (iii) in the finite thinking of the speculative philosopher, posited by what

Fichte calls the Ego." Previously Alan has denied that either (i) the Absolute or (ii) the

inter-subjective human community were the processor, which leaves only (iii) the finite

thinking of the speculative philosopher. However, the Dualist interpretation describes

two processors: the consciousness of the common intellect and the inadvertent activity

of speculative reason; and consequently divides the remaining processor of (iii) the

finite thinking of the speculative philosopher into two separate modes of cognition: the

consciousness and the unconsciousness. This original opposition of consciousness and

unconsciousness is, through the dialectical sequence of Hegel's system of philosophy,

absolutized and conceptually taken up into the Absolute. The Absolute conditions all

things whether a priori or a posteriori. Consequently, the Absolute may, upon the

Dualist interpretation, be read as the origin and ultimate cause of the infinite opposition

of mutually contradictory concepts and of the consciousness and the unconsciousness.

Page 64: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

Hegel describes how such a duality of the Ego and the non-Ego emerged from the

simple self-identity of the Fichtean Ego:

"Relation requires two sides; the relating and the related are here, however, the same;

for on account of the simplicity of the ego, there is nothing but a relation of the ego to

the ego. I have knowledge of myself; but in so far as I am consciousness, I know of an

object which is different from me, and which is then likewise mine. But the ego is in

such a way identical with its difference that what is different is immediately the

same, and what is identical is likewise different; we have a difference without a

difference. Self-consciousness is not dead identity, or non-Being, but the object which is

identical with me. This is immediately certain; all else must be as certain to me,

inasmuch as it must be my relation to myself."

The Ego and the non-Ego are two aspects of the same simple Ego. The dual aspects are

manifestations of the difference between the Ego which knows itself and the Ego which

knows what is differentiated from itself. From the simple self-relation of the Ego to

itself (i.e. Ego = Ego) there emerges the relation of the subject to its object, the non-Ego.

The Ego and the non-Ego are a difference that are united within an identity. Thus the

non-identical difference of subject and object subsists within the self-identity of the Ego,

as an identity that is inwardly differentiated, just as the self-identical proposition is

inwardly differentiated into subject, predicate and copula (e.g. S = P). The difference of

two parts in singular self-identity is a triadic model of Hegelian philosophy in which

the proposition, the syllogism, judgment, consciousness, and all systematic philosophy

are thoroughly composed of conceptual triads. The dispute between the Trinitarian and

the Dualist interpretation turns upon the primacy of whether of the difference that

subsumes identity or the identity that subsumes difference; of one-over-two or two-

over-one; such that the concepts are ultimately dual and mediated by nothingness or

ultimately triadic and mediated by some third concept. For Fichte, self-identical

consciousness is inwardly differentiated into these two aspects of Ego and non-Ego:

"Fichte thus appeals to consciousness, postulates ego and non-ego in their

abstraction, and since philosophic knowledge is the consciousness of consciousness, it

is not sufficient that I should find its determinations in consciousness, for I produce

them with consciousness. Common consciousness [i.e. common intellect], indeed,

likewise brings forth all the determinations of the ordinary conception and of

thought... seeing, however, is my activity, the determinations of my faculty of

sensation are thus posited through me. The ego as theoretic is, indeed, aware in

philosophic consciousness that it is the ego which posits; but here it posits that the non-

ego posits somewhat in me. The ego thus posits itself as that which is limited by the

non-ego. I make this limitation mine; thus is it for me in me, this passivity of the ego

Page 65: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

is itself the activity of the ego." - G.W.F. Hegel, Lectures on the History of Philosophy,

Fichte

The Dualist interpretation presents mind in two aspects, of consciousness and

unconsciousness, just as Fichte had posited the Ego and the non-Ego as a limit upon the

unlimited Ego. The positing of the non-Ego is the negative opposite of the Ego, the

object opposed to subject. The duality of Ego and non-Ego, the two aspects of mind,

mutually limit each other so that both Ego and non-Ego are limited by one another. The

non-Ego is the negative of the Ego, which stands in relative independence to the Ego as

an opposed aspect of consciousness. Thus the Dualist interpretation passively posits a

limit upon itself even as it actively strives to surpass the limitation of all objectivity, in

an infinite self-limiting striving that may never come to realization.

"As a matter of fact, all reality which appears in the object for the ego is a determination

of the ego, just as the categories and other determinations were in Kant's case. Thus it is

here more especially that we should expect Fichte to demonstrate the return of other-

Being into absolute consciousness. However, because after all the other-Being was

regarded as unconditioned, as implicit, this return does not come to pass. The ego

determines the 'other,' indeed, but this unity is an altogether finite unity; non-ego has

thus immediately escaped from determination once more and gone forth from this

unity. What we find is merely an alternation between self-consciousness and the

consciousness of another, and the constant progression of this alternation, which

never reaches any end." - G.W.F. Hegel, Lectures on the History of Philosophy, Fichte

For Kant, the empirical intuition of real objects were ideally determined by the

transcendental categories of the Understanding. Fichte never demonstrates how the

Kantian categories of the non-Ego, the object of other-being, may be both unconditioned

non-Ego and absolutely posited by consciousness Ego. Hence there remains an

originary contradiction between the absoluteness of Ego and the unconditionality of the

non-Ego, which simultaneously stands apart from and limits the Ego by contradicting

its absolutivity. This contradiction between Ego and non-Ego results in a paradoxical

duality, in which each limits the other, even as the Ego strives towards unlimited

absolutivity. The mutual contradiction of Ego and non-Ego, together with infinite

striving of the Ego, result in a ceaseless alternation between the infinitude of the Ego

and its contradiction by finite non-Ego, in a "constant progression" of a bad infinite

"which never reaches any end."

"This absolute Notion or this absolutely existent infinitude it is which has to be

developed in knowledge, and its distinction as the whole distinction of the universe

has to be represented from itself, and this has in its distinction to remain reflected

Page 66: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

within itself in equal absoluteness." - G.W.F. Hegel, Lectures on the History of

Philosophy, Fichte

The Absolute Idea develops itself entirely from itself, from which the whole universe is

represented, as it is equally reflected within itself. The tautology of the Absolute is the

"circle which presupposes its end as its purpose" (PhG §18). The emergence of the form

and essence require that the Absolute possess some prior form and some prior essence.

For Aristotle the thought-thinking-itself is the form of all forms which brings primordial

matter to its fullest actualization, while for Hegel the Absolute idea intrinsically

contains all being and essence as abstract conceptual moments; is intrinsically at the

beginning what it will be at the end; and determines the actualization of Nature and the

providential unfolding of the Spirit of history. The Trinitarian and the Dualist

interpretations disagree on the prior conditions for this emergence: where the

Trinitarian interpretation holds the unitary self-positing consciousness to apprehends

and intend the processes of thought, the Dualist interpretation holds speculative reason

to possess a special insight into the paradox of the dialectic that operates "behind the

back" of intentional consciousness.

Bad Infinity

For the Dualist interpretation, the bad infinite of alternating aspects of the mind is

merely the result of the supervenience of the paradoxical Absolute. The Fichtean bad

infinite is not resolved into the good infinity of the Absolute, but rather the bad infinite

is itself absolutized as the paradoxical absolute. Restless modern subjectivity of

contradictory self-positing does not find its final rest in God, but erects itself as an idol

of its own private veneration. Consequently, the Dualist interpretation may affirm that

the mind's knowledge of the Absolute is nothing more than the correlation of

contradiction with contradictory truth:

"Rather than attempting to make correct statements that correlate knowledge and truth

we instead have to correlate contradiction with an actual knowing appropriate for

expressing a contradictory truth. We have to think dialectically of an identity in

difference."

Knowledge is the correlation of self-contradictory mind with self-contradictory

Absolute truth, and the hypostatic contradiction is both the efficient cause and formal

condition of their mediation of their "identity in difference." For the Dualist

interpretation, there can be no intentionality but only contradictoriness. All thought and

being is absolutely contradictory just as it is absolutely non-being and non-thought. The

dualisms of the Dualist interpretation engenders the nothingness of all, absolute

nihilism, or meontotheology, which is the theology of nothingness. A product of this

Page 67: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

dual-consciousness is the inexplicable Schellingian mental faculty of speculative reason,

or 'insight':

"Our observational restraints enables us to see what is before us without being oriented

naturally to assume that truth is given to consciousness. As so restrained we are able to

recollect what is before with WITH INSIGHT... Insight is not intentional. It actually is

the co-origination of thought and object thought... With insight something new

comes on the scene out of what was already in view but without insight. This is not a

guided intentional act. It is something that can only come about if we restrain

employing natural intentional guides... the activity by consciousness is consciously

enacted but is inadvertent to its intention. Speculative reason does nothing but see

what is enacted from a second point of view. It itself does not act other than by

providing insight into what is there to be seen. Thought moves not because we

intentionally synthesize but because we shift our point of view."

The dualism between intentional consciousness and non-intentional unconsciousness is

mediated by the common hypostatic contradiction of both subject and object, the mind

and the Absolute. The activity of non-intentional unconsciousness is the result of the

concurrent cooperation of both Ego and non-Ego, "thought and the object thought" in

their mutual "co-origination" in the hypostatic contradiction of the paradoxical

Absolute. The "co-origination" of the hypostatic contradiction, in both the mind and the

Absolute, motivates a "perspective shift" from intentional conscious common intellect to

the non-intentional 'insight' of speculative reason. Because contradiction obliterates all

coherent (i.e. self-consistent) thought, the coherence of insight is not any constitutive

conceptual relation but the merely formal identity of contradictory opposites. Insight is

not a Plotinian mystical ascent to truth but merely the abysmal void of Schelling's

intellectual intuition; a formal nothingness hypostatized as something; the idolization of

nothingness that is nihilism.

Everything is already done for speculative thought."

Insight is nothing more than the speculative revelation of the nothingness that nothings

nothing throughout all that common intellect holds to be something. The nothingness

of the paradoxical Absolute needs only to be confirmed, its eternal nothingness, by the

insight of speculative reason. Everything you are, were, or could have been is disclosed

to be absolutely nullified by a monstrous cycling paradox.

Rather than adoring the divine Absolute Idea apprehended through philosophical

sciences, the Dualist interpretation adores the titanic paradox that obliterates any

possible the concept of religion and science:

Page 68: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

Where do we find the ontic expression of the absolute if not in some ultimate grand

conception? We find it concealed as the inconsistency of matter itself when we probe

deeply enough. This inconsistency has effects. And these effects are the realities of

which we are familiar. The absolute that spins off these realities is the split or

inconsistency inherent to these supposed realities. It is not a divine being as creator

but matter's inner truth, its inherent divide.

Alan affirms that, for the Dualist interpretation, the paradoxical Absolute is the

"inconsistency of matter itself" as it is known by the effects that "spin off" from the split

opposition of contradictory concepts which cycle around the mediating hypostatized

contradiction, like the accretion disc of an all-consuming black hole. While the black

hole of the paradoxical Absolute does not consume actual matter, it even more

rapciously devours all forms of thought in the purely formal logical singularity of all

contradictory opposite concepts that stands behind the appearances as "matter's inner

truth." Even the thought of the dualist interpretation is annihilated by the logical

singularity of the self-contradictory paradoxical Absolute. What is greatest becomes

worse when corrupted. Thus the brilliant pan-generative Hegelian dialectic becomes

pan-destructive when Hegelian trinitarianism is denied and reduced to dualism. The

Dualist interpretation devours itself in an apocalyptic suicide of all reason more

catastrophic than any skepticism, absolutizes contradiction, and makes its purported

coherence the very sense of non-sense:

"On my view, it is the sense/nonsense divide where Hegel's unique thought expresses

itself. The dialectic is important because it is the form of expression that can be seen

as either sense or nonsense. No other philoophy does its work on this divide. Often

when two philosophies conflict there will be an attempt to reduce the alternative

philosophy to nonsense. What is uniquely Hegelian is the fact that only when thought

is reduced to nonsense - only when it appears as a dialectic - is thought where it

needs to be for the proper emergence of a new truth. Sense emerges as a second look

at what on first look has the appearance of nonsense. We do not dismiss nonsense. We

do not dismiss the dialectic of the finite and spurious infinite. We simply recollect the

seeming nonsense to bring out its inherent sense."

The sense that philosophy makes of the paradoxical Absolute is simply non-sense. For

the Dualist interpretation, there is no "grand conception" of scientific truth but only the

insipid mutual contradictions of the paradoxical Absolute. The vaunted emergent sense

of truth is nothing more than the non-sense of so many falsehoods, for the nothingness

of all contradictions is non-sense. For theDualist interpretation, all is contradictory -

panantiphasis - and all is non-sense. The Dualist interpretation absolutizes its own

inherent duality as the merely formal identity of contradictory opposites. All the

Page 69: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

differentia of concepts, whose matter are the contradictorily opposed concepts, are

absolutely united in this formal self-identity and which is altogether grounded in the

paradoxical Absolute. Thus, for the Dualist interpretation, as for the philosophy of

Fichte, the unconscious non-ego is absolutized. Hegel explains how this results was

implicit in the dualisms of Fichte:

"It is the absolute form which Fichte laid hold of, or in other words, the absolute form

is just the absolute Being-for-self, absolute negativity, not individuality, but the

Notion of individuality, and thereby the Notion of actuality; Fichte's philosophy is

thus the development of form in itself." - Hegel, Lectures on the History of Philosophy,

Fichte

Neither the conscious Ego nor the unconscious non-Ego can ever escape from the

cycling contradiction of their mutual opposition. Like the space-farer who travels to

close to the singularity of a black hole, each are ineluctably drawn towards the other

other in an infinite downward spiral into nothingness. The infinite movement which

accomplishes nothing beyond itself is the closed circle of the 'bad infinite'. Hegel

concludes that the dualisms of the philosophy of Fichte result in such a 'bad infinite'

circle of self-contradictory movement that, in being closed in upon itself, must be

limited by what is outside itself, in the unconscious non-Ego of the Kantian noumenon:

"In this return the ego is merely an effort, on its side it is fixed, and it cannot realize its

endeavours. Striving is thus an imperfect or implicitly limited action. The ultimate

result is consequently a “circle” which cannot be broken through, so that “the finite

spirit must necessarily posit an absolute outside itself (a thing-in-itself), and yet on

the other hand it must recognize that this same is only there for it (a necessary

noumenon)... There remains only the empty repulsive force, and that is the Kantian

Thing-in-itself, beyond which even Fichte cannot get, even though the theoretic reason

continues its determination into infinitude. “The ego as intelligence” ever “remains

dependent on an undetermined non-ego; it is only through this that it is intelligence." -

Hegel, Lectures on the History of Philosophy, Fichte

Alan affirms this duality of the Absolute when he writes:

"What thought emphatically is not is some grand synthesis in view for a master

synthesizer or for the reader as he comes to the end of the Phenomenology. Many

commentators have challenged what appears to be Hegel's endorsement of just such a

view. Consciousness fails in each of its forms but the reader gets off Scott free. By what

right are we to be exempt from the chaos visited on consciousness? We are not to be

exempt. We are to be transformed. We are to be educated to the standpoint of science.

Page 70: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

We are to come to appreciate that when thought is absolute it is inherently divided or

dual."

The Dualist interpretation originates in a Fichtean opposition between consciousness

and unconsciousness. For Fichte, all thought and being is posited by the simple Ego: the

conscious Ego posits itself as unlimited and the unconscious non-Ego as a limit upon

itself. In positing the contradictory opposites of the conscious Ego and the unconscious

non-Ego, the Fichtean Ego posits a contradiction within itself. This self-posited

contradiction is the hypostatized contradiction of the Dualist interpretation. Hegel

explains how this two-fold contradictory principle annihilates the unicity of the Ego:

“[The Ego must] have the principle of positing itself within it, and also the principle of

not positing itself. Hence the ego in its essence would be contradictory and self-

repellent; there would be in it a twofold or contradictory principle, which assumption

contradicts itself, for in that case there would be no principle within it. The ego would

consequently not exist, for it would abrogate itself. All contradictions are reconciled

through the further determination of contradictory propositions. The ego must be

posited in one sense as infinite, and in another as finite. Were it to be posited as

infinite and finite in one and the same sense, the contradiction would be insoluble;

the ego would not be one but two." - Hegel, Lectures on the History of Philosophy,

Fichte

For the Dualist interpretation, the finite common intellect and the infinite speculative

reason are posited together in one and the same sense as they are together mediated by

the hypostatic contradiction. Finite consciousness is posited in relation to infinite

unconsciousness and vice versa, so that each is mediated with the other by one and the

same hypostatic contradiction. Thus, in positing the finite non-Ego, the Ego is divided

in two; into the conscious Ego and the unconscious non-Ego; even as it remains united

only by the barest thread of the formally identity of contradictory opposites. The

difference of Ego and non-Ego is united, not in the self-identity of Ego, but in the totally

unconscious self-identity of the hypostatic contradiction of ideal self-posited thought.

The unconscious formal self-identity of the hypostatic contradiction is absolutized

according to this inherent duality. Fichte explains how the non-Ego groundless and

unlimited absolutely opposes the Ego:

“According to our hypothesis the ego must now posit a non-ego absolutely, and

without any ground, i.e. absolutely and without any ground it must limit or in part not

posit itself.” - Fichte, Grundlage der gesammten Wissenschaftslehre, pp. 233

Hegel concludes his criticism of the philosophy of Fichte by describing how any

attempt to reconcile these contradictions, to affirm the thought of something rather than

Page 71: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

nothing, is merely an infinite Kantian imperative, an 'ought', which may never resolve

but only remain within the annihilating bounds of the contradiction:

"If one occupies oneself only with this content, that form of subjectivity which is

dominant with Fichte, and which remains in his opposition, disappears. As the ego is

affirmative and determining, there now is in this determination a negative likewise

present; I find myself determined and at the same time the ego is like itself, infinite, i.e.

identical with itself. This is a contradiction which Fichte indeed endeavours to

reconcile, but in spite of it all he leaves the false basis of dualism undisturbed. The

ultimate, beyond which Fichte does not get, is only an 'ought,' which does not solve

the contradiction; for while the ego should be absolutely at home with itself, i.e. free, it

should at the same time be associated with another. To Fichte the demand for the

solution of this contradiction thus adopts the attitude of being a demanded solution

only, of signifying that I ever have to destroy the barriers, that I ever have to reach

beyond the limitation into utter infinitude, and that I ever find a new limit; a

continual alternation takes place between negation and affirmation, an identity with

self which again falls into negation, and from this negation is ever again restored." -

Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Lectures on the History of Philosophy, Fichte

Any purported resolution to the nothingness of the contradictions many amount to no

more than merely a repetition of the same self-limiting opposition of conscious Ego and

unconscious non-Ego, in a continual alternation between the positing of the identity

and the negation of the Ego. Finally, any concept of the self-contradictory mind and the

paradoxical Absolute must be a merely fictive phantasm; not as what is but only as

what ought to be, and that which we are not yet no less will to become - the infinite

ought-to-be of the virtuous heart:

"... the fact that the ego in going forth at once finds its activity checked by a limitation,

and returns once more into itself, brings about two opposite tendencies in me,

between which I waver, and which I try to unite in the faculty of imagination." - Georg

Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Lectures on the History of Philosophy, Fichte

Having shown that there to be no constitutive paradoxical Absolute, that either

motivates or maintains this purported duality of consciousness or concepts, besides the

infinite Fichtean positing of the reader's imagination, it must be clear that there can be

no insurmountable obstacle to reading and understanding the philosophy of Hegel.

Although Hegel was no doubt a clever writer, it can be little more than a viciously

circular hermeneutic ruse to defend an interpretation by claiming esoteric insight into

the philosophy of the master. The duality of esoteric and exoteric interpretations

reiterates the Dualist interpretation's more general dualisms of finite common intellect

Page 72: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

and infinite speculative reason. The insight into the self-annihilating nothingness of

speculative reason is no better than the viciously circular hermeneutic of the esoteric

Dualist interpretation. Hegel ridiculed all such speculation of esoterism when he

lectured on the hermeneutics of the philosophy of Plato:

"How nonsensical! This would appear as if the philosopher kept possession of his

thoughts in the same way as of his external goods: the philosophic Idea is, however,

something utterly different, and instead of being possessed by, it possesses a man.

When philosophers discourse on philosophic subjects, they follow of necessity the

course of their ideas; they cannot keep them in their pockets; and when one man

speaks to another, if his words have any meaning at all, they must contain the idea

present to him. It is easy enough to hand over an external possession, but the

communication of ideas requires a certain skill; there is always something esoteric in

this, something more than the merely exoteric. This difficulty is therefore trifling."-

Hegel, Lectures on the History of Philosophy, Plato

The presentation of the philosophy of Hegel "follows of necessity the course" of the

Absolute Idea from the humblest barren abstraction of sense-certainty and being to the

majestic summit of Absolute Knowing. This necessity is the ladder of science that Hegel

marvelously invokes in the Preface to The Phenomenology of Spirit (§26). For the Dualist

interpretation, the ladder of science is, contrary to the surface meaning of a vertical

ascent, an exoteric red herring that is meant to conceal the esoteric importance of insight

into the paradoxical absolute, which is the toppling of all essence, being, and

knowledge into the absolute nothingness that nothings itself. The difference in how the

antitheses are resolved has the further epistemological and ontological consequences

that the Trinitarian interpretation is generative of richer truths and fuller realities, while

the Dualist interpretation languishes in paradoxical identity which affirms only its own

self-annihilating nothingness. Thus the Trinitarian Absolute is a self-surpassing infinite

becoming while the Dualist Absolute is no more than a meontotheology which

divinizes nothing as an absolute nihilism.

Conclusion

In Schelling's 1796 essay Of the Ego as a Principle for All Philosophy and the Unconditioned

in Human Knowledge, Hegel's erstwhile colleague describes such an opposition between

an absolute Ego and an absolute non-Ego: the absolute non-Ego is, not only not absolute

and limited by its other, but also, and all the more damningly, a species of idealist

Leibnizian or realist Spinozist dogmatism which simultaneously negates the very

possibility of any theoretical and all practical reason:

Page 73: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

"Insasmuch as the ego is the absolute ego, that which is not the ego can be determined

only in contrast to the ego and presupposing the ego. Any non-ego posited absolutely,

as if it were in no contrast to anything, is a contradiction in terms... The two extremes

are dogmatism and criticism. The principle of dogmatism is a non-ego posited as

antecedent to any ego; the principle of criticism, as ego posited as antecedent to all that

is not the ego and as exclusive of any non-ego... dogmatism contradicts itself because it

presupposes an unconditional thing-in-itself that is a thing that is not a thing." - F.J.

Schelling, Of the I as the Principle of Philosophy, §4

Schelling affirms that the non-ego, which is other-than the ego, can only be

apprehended in thought by first presupposing the ego, which is the positing of one's

own self-conscious mind. To posit the non-ego absolutely, as an omnipresent

unknowable thing-in-itself, would also be to posit the non-ego as logically prior to the

ego. The non-ego would then logically condition the ego to posit the non-ego. The ego

must know the truth as an unconditioned rather than a conditioned idea, just as the ego

must will itself towards the good unconditionally free rather than condtionally

enslaved to another. Dogmatism is the logical conditioning of the ego by the non-ego,

which denies the unconditionality of the ego to know the truth and to freely will the

good. Dogmatism is self-contradictory because, in denying the unconditionality of the

ego, it both affirms and denies the logical pre-conditions of true theory and free

practice. Schelling's criticism of dogmatism can be parceled into the traditional

criticisms of skepticism and determinism: any absolute skepticism, which denies truth,

also denies the truth of skepticism, and thereby self-contradictorily denies the very

thing that it affirms; just as any determinism, which denies free will, also denies that the

opinion of determinism is freely willed according to its truth, and thereby self-

contradictorily denies truth to be a necessary condition of opinion even as it affirms the

truth of the opinion of determinism. Hence, dogmatism must be rejected as theoretically

self-contradictory and practically self-defeating.

The Janos-Faced Dualist interpretation of the philosophy of Hegel, in which conscious

understanding is opposed to unconscious speculative reason, is simply the Fichtean

opposition between the Ego and the non-Ego. When absolutized this Fichtean

opposition becomes the no less gigantomachic clash of the absolute which we may

know and absolute which we can never know; or, in the language of Schelling, the

absolute Ego and the absolute non-Ego. Both the absolute Ego and non-Ego are limited

by the mutual externality of the other so that neither may be truly absolute. The

absolute ego and non-Ego mutually contradict one another without, however,

annihilating one or the other. Rather, each opposed pole is retained in its contrary

relation to the other. The mutual relationality of absolute Ego and non-Ego is the

mediation of the contradiction. Contradiction is explosive nothingness, but is posited by

Page 74: Ryan Hacker - Three Counter-Theses Against Alan Ponikvar

thought as something constitutive: the hypostatic contradiction. The hypostatic

contradiction is the ancient Platonic idea of the soul, that moves itself by negating itself

within itself. Speculative reason posits itself in-and-through the positing of the

hypostatic contradiction. The Dualist interpretation reduces the Plato's World-Soul and

Hegel's Weltgeist to the absolute positing the hypostatic contradiction, which is

nothingness made something in and through thought. For the Dualist interpretation,

the philosophy of Hegel reduces to the persistent self-positing of Fichtean subjective

idealism. Fichteanism reduces to an infinite ought-to-be which never comes to be

anything more than an unfulfilled expectation. The duality of mind and absolute

results in a schizophrenia of Kantian and Hegelian logic which eviscerates the subject of

consciousness, just as it absolutely negates the absolute object of the universe. Indeed,

the absolutization of the hypostatic contradiction is the absolutization of nothingness:

the mutual limiting of absolute Ego and non-Ego by one another within the paradoxical

Absolute consigns both Ego and non-Ego to be subsumed within the infinitude of the

nothingness of the contradiction which mediates and envelops both together. The

infinity of self-cycling contradiction leads irreversibly down the event horizon of a

logical black hole into a singularity of nothingness. Neither thought nor being may ever

escape from the infinite cycle of its own self-posited damnation. The Janos-Faced

Dualist interpretation necessarily implodes in upon itself in an absolute suicide of

reason. Students of Hegel would be advised to remember Nietzsche's admonition

"Battle not with monsters, lest ye become a monster, and if you gaze into the abyss, the

abyss gazes also into you." (Beyond Good and Evil, Aphorism 146)