Top Banner
Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1
65
Welcome message from author
This document is posted to help you gain knowledge. Please leave a comment to let me know what you think about it! Share it to your friends and learn new things together.
Transcript
Page 1: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

Research ethics

Jan Deckers

School of Medical Education

1

Page 2: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

Objectives

• To reflect on what ethics is.• To develop your skills as an ethical researcher.• To prepare yourself to apply for ethical approval

from research ethics committees.• To stimulate your ethical thinking in relation to

‘consent’ and your research projects.

2

Page 3: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

What is ‘ethics’?

• Ethics ‘deals with the standards and principles of moral reasoning’. (Rachels, 1998, 15)

• Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy: ‘ethics (or moral philosophy) involves systematizing, defending, and recommending concepts of right and wrong behaviour’

3

Page 4: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

So, what is ‘ethics’?

• a theory of – how we ought/ought not to act– which values or principles ought (not) to guide

our actions• ethics is about evaluating/justifying particular

actions

4

Page 5: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

What is ‘meta-ethics’?

• the study of the status/meaning of ethical theories

• the study of moral justification

5

Page 6: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

Three meta-ethical positions: e.g. ‘X is wrong’

• Moral absolutism– ‘I know that X is wrong (and anyone who

disagrees is wrong).’• Moral relativism

– ‘X might seem wrong to you, but what is right and wrong is entirely subjective (nothing but a matter of taste).’

• Pyrrhonian moral scepticism– ‘I believe/think that X is wrong (but those who

disagree may be right).’

6

Page 7: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

‘Pyrrhonian’ moral scepticism

• A school of thinking named after Pyrrho– a Greek philosopher who lived from c. 360 to

c. 270 BC

7

Page 8: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

Why do we need ethics?• Many people feel the

need to:– justify their behaviour– to explain why their

behaviour is (un)acceptable

• These explanations often relate actions to principles.

• A theory is an account of which principles should be followed, and how to balance them against each other.

• Many (or all?) things deserve moral consideration

= subjective aspect

= objective aspect8

Page 9: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

Objective dimension: What sorts of things should we value?

• Key questions– Which things are proper objects of ‘moral

consideration’?– How much ‘relative moral significance’ should we give

to different things?• Key distinction

– Intrinsic value: value for oneself

≠– Instrumental/use value: value for others

9

Page 10: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

What is bioethics, and what is research ethics?

• Bioethics = the study of how human actions that affect biological organisms can or can’t be justified.

• Research ethics = the study of ethical issues that pertain to research.

10

Page 11: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

Two dimensions

• 1. Law and professional guidelines• 2. Reflection

11

Page 12: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

How does it work?

• 1. Establishing knowledge of the relevant legal and professional guidelines

• 2. Exercise your ability to reflect........– How?

12

Page 13: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

The tools of the trade

• clarity• the principle of non-contradiction• the use of analogies and thought experiments

13

Page 14: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

clarity: the importance of defining concepts

• reportive definitions– = lexical definitions– to reflect the existing meaning of a term

• stipulative definitions– to assign new meaning to a term

• clarifying definitions – may combine the above– to give more precise meaning to a term

14

Page 15: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

rationale for emphasising clarity

• the ‘what do you mean?’ question may resolve a lot of moral disputes

15

Page 16: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

Example: a simple disagreement between James and John

• James: Animal research is unacceptable.– P (P= premise) 1 (major): Inflicting pain is unacceptable.– P2 (minor): Animal research causes pain.– Conclusion: Animal research is unacceptable.

• John: Animal research is not necessarily unacceptable.– Agrees with James about P1, but does not accept P2 as not all

research inflicts pain.– Conclusion: Animal research is not necessarily unacceptable.

16

Page 17: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

How to resolve this dispute?

• James may come to agree with John that not all animal research is unacceptable as he may question P2, e.g. after John has explained to him that his definition of ‘animal research’ includes studies that merely observe animals in nature.

17

Page 18: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

the importance of defining concepts = the virtue of clarity

• Aiming for clarity may help you to:– scrutinise what you think before you say something.– scrutinise what others say before you decide to

(dis)agree with it.

18

Page 19: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

the principle of non-contradiction/consistency

• example:

a researcher who carries out research on patients with advanced dementia says the following:

“I believe that researchers who want to carry out research on patients should only proceed if patients give their voluntary, informed consent to taking part in the research.”

19

Page 20: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

arguing by reductio ad absurdum (reduction to absurdity)

• 1. Start from the assumption that X is right.• 2. Try to find a counterexample.• 3. If a counterexample can be found, conclude that X

cannot be right.

20

Page 21: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

example

• Premise A: Research that involves research subjects should not happen unless subjects give their consent.

• Premise B: If no research was done with people who suffer from advanced dementia, people with this condition might be excluded from medical progress.

• Conclusion: People with advanced dementia should not be excluded and premise A should be rejected/modified.

21

Page 22: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

the use of analogies

• Example:– When a research project is likely to kill me

(healthy), research should not proceed.

↓– When a research project is likely to kill healthy

others, research should not proceed.• What is at work here is the principle of

universalisability

– Is this a valid analogy?

22

Page 23: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

the use of analogies

• Example:– When a research project is likely to kill human

research subjects, research should not proceed.

↓– When a research project is likely to kill nonhuman

research subjects, research should not proceed.

• Is this a valid analogy?

23

Page 24: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

the use of thought experiments

• A thought experiment is an analogy between a real case and an imaginary case whereby the latter is claimed to shed light on how to handle the former.

24

Page 25: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

The use of thought experiments

• Example: Julian Savulescu (2002)’s leukaemia case:– Imagine: A nuclear reactor has exploded, leaving your

child exposed to nuclear fall out. Numerous children develop leukaemia, including your own. Bone marrow can be generated most successfully by reprogramming brain cells from children. Unfortunately, a child must be killed, as no brains from those who have deceased are available. The extracted stem cells could then be reprogrammed to treat ten children.

25

Page 26: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

• Since a one in eleven chance of certain death seems preferable to a one hundred percent chance of imminent death, the question is: – Would you enter your child into a lottery and risk a

1/11 chance of your child being sacrificed (by being killed to treat others), or refrain from entering your child into such a lottery (which would mean certain death for your child)?

– If you do, Savulescu claims that you should also enter all human embryos into a similar lottery as the real world would be similar to this imaginary world: the real world is a world that lacks the great benefits that we would have had if there had been less objection to embryonic stem cell research.

26

Page 27: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

Why use analogies and thought experiments?

• Rachels (1998, p. 22): ‘like cases should be treated alike and different cases differently’

27

Page 28: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

Some common ethical theories

• Consequentialism• Deontology• Principlism

28

Page 29: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

Consequentialism

• Focus on consequences

Example:

Utilitarianism: consequences are measured in terms of whether or not they produce happiness

29

Page 30: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

Deontology

• Focus on rules and motives

30

Page 31: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

PrinciplismThe ‘four principles’ approach:

1. Autonomy (self-determination)

2. Beneficence (well-being)

3. Non-maleficence (no harm)

4. Justice

(1&4 are deontological?; 2&3 are consequentialist?)

= a very popular approach in bioethicsRef: Beauchamp & Childress, 2001.

31

Page 32: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

Why is research ethics important?

• Many people would agree that ‘not everything goes’ in relation to research.

• Some examples:– Tuskegee Syphilis Experiment

• For 40 years (between 1932 and 1972) 399 black men with advanced syphilis were told they were treated for ‘bad blood’ by the US Public Health Service. They were never told they had syphilis, and never received treatment for it. The aim of the study was to examine the effect of syphilis on the human body. The data were collected from the autopsies.

– The TGN1412 trial

32

Page 33: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

Ryan Wilson, one of the victims (picture from: http://news.bbc.co.uk/1/hi/health/5121824.stm)

33

Page 34: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

The TGN1412 trial

• Phase 1 clinical trial conducted in 2006 by Parexel, an independent clinical trials unit based in London

• £ 2000 paid to 6 healthy volunteers• All ended up in hospital• 4 developed multiple organ dysfunction and suffered

from a cytokine storm

34

Page 35: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

Applying the four principles

• 1. Did it respect the autonomy of research participants?– Could the fact that a financial incentive was provided have

undermined their autonomy?

• 2. Did it promote beneficence?– There may be little doubt that the research was done with the

aim to promote the well-being of future patients, but how important was this motive compared to the motive to make a profit? Does it matter which was the primary motive?

35

Page 36: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

• 3. Was it non-maleficent?– The research caused harm. Could this harm have been

avoided?– Could paying these participants be considered to have caused

harm? How does it compare with payments for other physical interventions, e.g.:• blood donations• tattoo adverts (Sandel, 2012)

• 4. Was it just?– Was it legal?– Other considersations, e.g. moral rights:

– Would I like to be treated like that? (The “how would you feel....” test, or “don’t do unto others what you would not want others to do unto you”)

36

Page 37: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

Case 1

• James Strong is a researcher who has drafted an information sheet that he would like to use to recruit research participants. He includes the following:– ‘This research will not expose you to any risks as

previous research has not found any evidence that the D drug is harmful. This research merely repeats what has already been shown by other studies, so you can trust what we are going to do. This research has already been funded and it has also been granted ethical approval from Newcastle University’s Research Ethics Committee.’

37

Page 38: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

Case 2

• Claire is working on a research project aimed at making tomato plants more resistant to frost. She hopes that isolating a gene from a flounder fish which can resist very cold temperatures and inserting this gene into tomato plants will make these plants resistant to frost.

38

Page 39: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

Case 3

• David does not support animal experimentation. Newcastle University is building a new facility to develop its research on animals. David wants to stop the University from building this facility, and speak up for the plight of animals. David decides to organise a protest in Newcastle with some like-minded people. They take to the streets and shout ‘stop the animal lab’. Afterwards, they go to the pub for a bar meal. David orders a pint of lager and a lamb pie with chips.

39

Page 40: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

Appendix 1: Further information in relation to the principle of autonomy:

• ‘consent’, a cornerstone of good research?– consent = closely related to ‘autonomy’

• Providing consent = giving permission• Research often requires legal consent from

those who participate in it.– Why?

40

Page 41: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

Legal context

• Common law duty to obtain consent• Statutory laws, e.g.

– Mental Capacity Act 2005 (MCA)

41

Page 42: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

What if consent is compromised?

• Researchers may be liable to assault/battery in criminal law:– Battery: ‘an act that directly and either intentionally or negligently

causes some physical contact with the person of another without that person’s consent’ (McHale & Fox, 2007, p. 352.)

• Researchers may be liable to criminal (gross/extreme) negligence in criminal law (= rare).

• Researchers may be liable to trespass to the person (infringing the bodily integrity or liberty of another) and negligence in civil law.

42

Page 43: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

The tort of negligence

• A person claiming negligence (= a claimant) must satisfy:– that the defendant owed him or her a duty of

care– that this duty was breached, and– that the claimant was harmed by this breach

and that this harm was not too remoteRef: Pattinson, 2009, p. 68, 78.

43

Page 44: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

Three requirements in relation to consent

• The research subject:– has capacity– is informed adequately– gives consent without being coerced (voluntariness)

44

Page 45: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

Three questions

• What is capacity and what to do if it is lacking?• What does it mean to be adequately informed?• Can research subjects give voluntary consent to

participate in research?

45

Page 46: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

First question: What is capacity?

• Necessary condition for valid consent =Person ‘has capacity’ (is competent)

• Legal presumption: every person has capacity from the age of 16

• If in doubt: assess • How?

46

Page 47: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

Mental Capacity Act 2005

• section 3.1: a person lacks capacity if a person is unable:– ‘(a) to understand the information relevant to the

decision,– (b) to retain that information,– (c) to use or weigh that information as part of the

process of making the decision, or– (d) to communicate his decision (whether by talking,

using sign language or any other means).’

• What should be done in situations where adults lack capacity?

47

Page 48: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

The law related to clinical research

• Medicines for Human Use (Clinical Trials) Regulations 2004

• The patient’s legal representative can give permission on behalf of the patient if the clinical trial has gained ethical approval from a Research Ethics Committee.

• This person can be• ‘the doctor primarily responsible for the medical

treatment provided to that adult’ or ‘a person nominated by the relevant health care provider’, provided they are not connected with the trial (Schedule 1, part 1, section 2)

48

Page 49: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

• This person must • speak to a member of the research team

about the risks and objectives • be provided with a contact point • be told that the subject can be withdrawn at

any time,• give informed consent to the subject’s

participation.

49

Page 50: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

Further conditions for participation:

• Par. 6: ‘The subject has received information according to his capacity of understanding regarding the trial, its risks and its benefits.’

• Par 9: ‘There are grounds for expecting that administering the medicinal product to be tested in the trial will produce a benefit to the subject outweighing the risks or produce no risk at all.’

50

Page 51: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

• Par 11: ‘The clinical trial relates directly to a life-threatening or debilitating clinical condition from which the subject suffers.’ (Schedule 1, part 5)

• Subjects who refuse to participate when they still have capacity cannot be entered once they have lost capacity.

51

Page 52: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

The law related to other research

• For non-clinical research with adults, the Mental Capacity Act 2005 should be applied: Research on adults who lack capacity is possible if:– It involves minimal risk;– relates to the person’s condition– cannot be done as effectively on people who have

capacity– (unpaid) carers or nominated third parties are

consulted– the person is not entered or is withdrawn if any

resistance is shown– and the research project has been approved by an

appropriate body, such as a Research Ethics Committee.

52

Page 53: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

The law related to clinical research with children

• normally, a person with parental responsibility should be asked to give consent.

• legal representatives should only be used in emergencies.

• consent from a person with parental responsibility is required even if children are deemed to have capacity. (Schedule 1, part 4)

53

Page 54: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

The law related to non-clinical research with children

• Apply common law:– Children may be able to give consent if they

are ‘Gillick competent’.– Children who are not Gillick competent may

be able to give their assent.– Children must be informed, even if they lack

competency.

54

Page 55: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

Second question: What does it mean to be informed adequately?

• Three different views:– Professional practice standard (legal standard in

criminal law) • Bolam test: ‘a doctor is not guilty of negligence if

he has acted in accordance with a practice accepted as proper by a responsible body of medical men’ (Bolam v. Friern Hospital Management Committee [1957] 1 W.L.R. 538)

55

Page 56: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

– Reasonable person standard (legal standard in civil law) • Bolitho v. City & Hackney Health Authority [1998]

A.C. 232 (HL) at 243: a court can reject medical opinion if it is not ‘reasonable or responsible’ (emboldening mine)

56

Page 57: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

– Individual person standard• J. Bridson et al., 2003 (p. 1160; emboldening

mine): ‘The professional standard is paternalistic, emphasising what clinicians consider appropriate to disclose rather than what patients want disclosed. The reasonable patient standard is inherently hypothetical, upholding the autonomy only of patients who behave like the typical patient. It asks what risks should be disclosed to a ‘reasonable’ patient in the particular patient’s position, not what risks the particular patient would regard as important.’

57

Page 58: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

Third question: how to ensure research subjects give their voluntary consent?

• Example: Miss Jackson is paid by a drug company for participation in their trial of the new Alzheimer’s drug. She is keen to contribute to the possibility of making a scientific breakthrough that could much improve the quality of life of patients suffering from Alzheimer’s. Miss Jackson thinks it is appropriate that her patients are paid a small amount as well.

• Are there any ethical issues here?

58

Page 59: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

• Some useful questions to ask in relation to personal research projects– What is the aim of my research?– What are the implicit assumptions about what science

is or should be?– Whose interests will be served by my research?– What are the risks?– What are the opportunity costs?

• The answers to these questions must feed into the overall ethical evaluation of your research.

Appendix 2: Some practical advice for your research projects

59

Page 60: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

Some golden advice?

• ‘a/ write early and write often; • b/don’t get it right, get it written’ (Delamont,

Atkinson, and Parry, 1997, p. 121)

60

Page 61: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

In defence of ‘write early and write often’

• ‘1. The more you write, the easier it gets.• 2. If you write every day, it becomes a habit.• 3. Tiny bits of writing add up to a lot of writing.

Break the writing up into small bits. Write 100 words on X, 200 words on Y, and file them safely. It all mounts up

• 4. The longer you leave it unwritten the worse the task becomes.’ (Delamont, Atkinson, & Parry, 1997, p. 121)

61

Page 62: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

In defence of ‘don’t get it right, get it written’

• ‘1. Until it is on paper no one can help you to get it right. Draft, show the draft to people, redraft.

• 2. Drafting is a vital stage in clarifying thought • 3. Start writing the bit that is clearest in your

head: not the introduction, but Chapter 4, or the appendixes, or the conclusions, or the methods. As you draft, other bits become clear.

• 4. Drafting reveals the places where ‘it’ isn’t right (yet) in ways that nothing else does.’ (Delamont, Atkinson, & Parry, 1997, p. 121)

62

Page 63: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

What makes for a good piece of written work?

• The words ‘making a contribution’ and ‘originality’ appear frequently (Delamont, Atkinson, and Parry, 1997, p. 113-114)

• For the Newcastle PhD: ‘show distinct ability in conducting original investigations and in testing ideas, whether the candidate’s own or others’. (…) ‘The exposition of the work in the thesis must be clear and must show that the candidate understands the relationship of the work embodied in the thesis and the theme of that work to a wider field of knowledge’ (Doctor of Philosophy by Thesis Examination Conventions, p. 149; http://www.ncl.ac.uk/regulations/docs/PhDExamConvThesis1112.pdf) 63

Page 64: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

References and recommended further reading• Beauchamp, T. and Childress, J., Principles of Biomedical Ethics, 5th edition, New

York/Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001.• Bridson, J., et al., Making Consent Patient Centred, in BMJ 2003; 327: 1159-1161.• Deckers J., The New EU Directive on the Use of Animals for Research and the Value

of Moral Consistency, in Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 2012; 9: 377-379.• Delamont, S., Atkinson, P., Parry, O., Supervising the PhD: A Guide to Success,

Bristol: Open University Press, 1997.• Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy (http://www.iep.utm.edu/ethics/)• Jamieson, D., Method and Moral Theory, in Singer, P. (ed.), A Companion to Ethics,

Oxford: Blackwell, 1993, pp. 476-490.• Knight, A. The Costs and Benefits of Animal Experiments. Palgrave MacMillan, 2011.• McHale, J., & Fox, M., Health Care Law, Second edition, Sweet and Maxwell, 2007.• Nuffield Council on Bioethics, The Ethics of Research Involving Animals, London,

2005.• Pattinson, S., Medical Law and Ethics, Second edition, Sweet and Maxwell, 2009.• Rachels, J., Ethical Theory and Bioethics. In Kuhse, H. & P. Singer (eds.), A

Companion to Bioethics, Oxford: Blackwell, 1998, pp. 15-23.• Sandel, M., What Money Can’t Buy. The Moral Limits of Markets, Allen Lane, 2012.• Savulescu, J., The Embryonic Stem Cell Lottery and the Cannibalization of Human

Beings, in Bioethics 2002;16: 508-529.

64

Page 65: Research ethics Jan Deckers School of Medical Education 1.

Conclusions

• Ethics is about the attempt to justify particular actions.• Logic and the making of valid analogies are the tools

of the trade.• In bioethics, the focus is on biological organisms.• Research ethics focuses on ethical issues in research.• Various formal theories exist on what ethics should be

about, including consequentialism, deontology, and the 4 principles approach.

• Many institutions have ‘research ethics committees’ and demand approval from them before research projects can commence.

65