Top Banner
Proof of Invalidity Kareem Khalifa Department of Philosophy Middlebury College
16

Proof of Invalidity Kareem Khalifa Department of Philosophy Middlebury College.

Jan 17, 2016

Download

Documents

Kory Hamilton
Welcome message from author
This document is posted to help you gain knowledge. Please leave a comment to let me know what you think about it! Share it to your friends and learn new things together.
Transcript
Page 1: Proof of Invalidity Kareem Khalifa Department of Philosophy Middlebury College.

Proof of Invalidity

Kareem Khalifa

Department of Philosophy

Middlebury College

Page 2: Proof of Invalidity Kareem Khalifa Department of Philosophy Middlebury College.

Overview

• Why this matters

• Proving invalidity– Discovery – Proof

• Exercises

Page 3: Proof of Invalidity Kareem Khalifa Department of Philosophy Middlebury College.

Why this matters

• Not every argument you encounter will be valid.

• But, just as with valid arguments, you want to avoid the cumbersome nature of truth tables and the unreliable nature of constructing counterexamples.

• Just as with formal proofs of validity, formal proofs of invalidity strike a balance between these two poles.

Page 4: Proof of Invalidity Kareem Khalifa Department of Philosophy Middlebury College.

Proving invalidity

• Take a well known example of an invalid argument: denying the antecedent.– PQ, ~P ├ ~Q

• How do we prove this is invalid?– Recall: An argument is invalid if it is possible for

all of the premises to be true and the conclusion to be false.

– So we set the truth-values of the simple propositions in the argument (in this case, P and Q) such that all of the premises are true and the conclusion is false.

Page 5: Proof of Invalidity Kareem Khalifa Department of Philosophy Middlebury College.

The two aspects of a formal proof of invalidity

1. Your process of discovery. • This is how you came to the answer you arrived at.• This belongs on your SCRAP paper.

2. The proof. • This is how you show that the a certain combination

of truth values yields a scenario in which the all of the premises are true and the conclusion is false.

• I ONLY care about the proof. This is your final answer.

• These two aspects often require thinking in opposite directions.

Page 6: Proof of Invalidity Kareem Khalifa Department of Philosophy Middlebury College.

Discovery in 3 steps

1. Set up a one-row truth table, with a column for each simple proposition, each premise, and the conclusion.

2. Fill in T’s under the premise-columns and F under the conclusion column.

3. Using your knowledge of &, ~, v, etc., make the columns under the simple propositions fit with the T’s and F you wrote in Step 2.

Page 7: Proof of Invalidity Kareem Khalifa Department of Philosophy Middlebury College.

Steps 1-2

• PQ, ~P ├ ~Q1. Set up a truth table

with only 1 row. The number of columns depends on the number of simple propositions and premises.

2. Fill in all P-columns as true, and the C-column as false.

P1 P2 C

P Q P Q ~P ~Q

T T F

Page 8: Proof of Invalidity Kareem Khalifa Department of Philosophy Middlebury College.

Step 3

P1 P2 C

P Q PQ ~P ~Q

T T F

• PQ, ~P ├ ~Q3. Using your

knowledge of the logical operators, fill in the remaining blanks in the truth table such that all of the premises remain true and the conclusion remains false.

If the conclusion, ~Q, is false, then Q is true.

T

If the premise, ~P, is true, then P is false.

If Q is true, then the premise, P Q, is also true.

√F

NOTE: You don’t need to write all of this out.

Page 9: Proof of Invalidity Kareem Khalifa Department of Philosophy Middlebury College.

Tips for discovery

• Use DM, MI, etc. to find simpler formulations of negated &, v, and propositions.o Ex. If you have ~(PvQ), switch it to ~P&~Q.

• Try to minimize wiggle room, i.e. find simple propositions that can only have one truth-value.

• When the main operator of the conclusion is ‘~,’ ‘v,’ ‘,’ or a simple proposition, the conclusion has minimal wiggle room.

• When a premise is ‘~,’ ‘&,’ or a simple proposition, the premise has minimal wiggle room.

Page 10: Proof of Invalidity Kareem Khalifa Department of Philosophy Middlebury College.

The Proof

4. Write down your completed truth-table from Step 3.

5. Begin by stating the truth-values of all the simple propositions.

6. Show that according to these simple truth-values and the rules for &, ~, v, etc., all of the premises are true and the conclusion is false.

Page 11: Proof of Invalidity Kareem Khalifa Department of Philosophy Middlebury College.

Step 4-6

5. Begin by stating the truth-values of all the simple propositions.

• Let P be false and Q be true.

6. Show that according to these simple truth-values, all of the premises are true and the conclusion is false.

P1 P2 C

P Q PQ ~P ~Q

F T T T F• Since P is false and Q is true, the premise PQ is also true.

•Since P is false, the premise ~P is true.

•Since Q is true, the conclusion ~Q is false.

•So there is at least one way in which the premises can be true and the conclusion can be false.

•So the argument is invalid.

This is your proof

Page 12: Proof of Invalidity Kareem Khalifa Department of Philosophy Middlebury College.

Contrast

• Discovery (scrap)• Start by assuming the

conclusion is false and all premises are true.

• Then show how the simple propositions must assume certain truth values.

• Proof (final answer)• Start by assigning certain

truth values to the simple propositions.

• Then show how it follows from this assignment of truth values that the conclusion is false and all premises are true.

Page 13: Proof of Invalidity Kareem Khalifa Department of Philosophy Middlebury College.

For the test…

• A single line of a truth-table, in which truth-values are assigned to all of the simple propositions, is sufficient. (No need for the numbered proof.)

P1 P2 C

P Q PQ ~P ~Q

F T T T F

Page 14: Proof of Invalidity Kareem Khalifa Department of Philosophy Middlebury College.

2) ~(E&F), (~E&~F)(G&H), HG ├ G

C P1 P2 P3

E F G H ~(E&F) (~E&~F)(G&H) HG

T F F F T T T

F T F F T T T1. Let E be true and F, G, and H be false.2. Since F is false, E&F is false.3. By 2, the premise ~(E&F) is true.4. Since E is true, ~E is false.5. Since ~E is false, ~E&~F is false.6. By 5, the premise (~E&~F)(G&H) is true.7. Since H is false, the premise HG is true.8. The conclusion G is false.9. So, by 3,6,7, and 8, the premises can be true when the conclusion

is false.10.So the argument is invalid.

Page 15: Proof of Invalidity Kareem Khalifa Department of Philosophy Middlebury College.

7) D(EvF), G(HvI), ~E(IvJ), (IG)&(~H~G), ~J├ D(GvI)

D E F G H I J D(EvF) ~E(IvJ) G(HvI) (IG)& (~H~G)

~J D(GvI)

T T F F F F T T T F

1. Let D and E be true; F, G, I, and J be false. (You can let H be either T or F)2. Since G and I are false, G v I is false.3. Since D is true and G v I is false, the conclusion, D(GvI) is false.4. Since J is false, the premise ~J, is true.5. Since I is false, IG is true.6. Since G is false, ~G is true.7. By 6, ~H ~G is true.8. By 5 and 7, the premise (IG)&(~H~G) is true.9. Since G is false, the premise G (HvI) is true.10. Since E is true, E v F is true.11. Since D and E v F are both true, the premise D (EvF) is true.12. Since E is true, ~E is false.13. By 12, the premise ~E -> (I v J) is true.14. By 3, 4, 8, 9, 11, and 13 it’s possible for all the premises to be true when the conclusion

is false.15. So the argument is invalid.

T T

Page 16: Proof of Invalidity Kareem Khalifa Department of Philosophy Middlebury College.

9.(ST)&(TS), (U&T)v(~T&~U), (UvV)v(SvT), ~U(W&X), (V~S)&(~V~Y), X(~Y ~X), (UvS)&(VvZ) ├ X&Z

1. Let S, T, U, W, and Z be true; V,X,Y be false.2. Since X is false, the conclusion X&Z is false.3. Since T is true, ST is true.4. Since S is true, TS is true.5. By 3 and 4, the premise (ST)&(TS) is true.6. Since U and T are true U&T is true.7. By 6, the premise (U&T) v(~T&~U) is true.8. Since U is true U v V and UvS are both true.9. By 8, the premise (UvV)v(SvT) is true.10. Since U is true, ~U is false.11. By 10, the premise ~U(W&X) is true.12. Since V is false V~S is true.

S T U V W X Y Z (ST)& (TS)

(U&T)v (~T&~U)

(UvV)v(SvT)

~U (W&X)

(V~S)& (~V ~Y)

X(~Y ~X)

(UvS) & (VvZ)

X&Z

T T T F T F F T T T T T T T T F

T T T F F F F T T T T T T T T F

13. Since Y is false, ~Y is true.14. Since ~Y is true, ~V~Y is true.15. By 12 and 14 are true, the premise (V~S)&(~V~Y) is true.16. Since X is false, the premise X(~Y~X)17. Since Z is true, VvZ is true.18. By 8 and 17, the premise (UvS) & (VvZ)

is true.19. By 2, 5, 7, 9, 11, 16, and 18 it is possible

for all the premises to be true when the conclusion is false. 20. So the argument is invalid.