Top Banner

of 16

PhilosophyBerkeley's Ideas

Jun 03, 2018

Download

Documents

Katie Soto
Welcome message from author
This document is posted to help you gain knowledge. Please leave a comment to let me know what you think about it! Share it to your friends and learn new things together.
Transcript
  • 8/12/2019 PhilosophyBerkeley's Ideas

    1/16

    anadian Journal of Philosophy

    Berkeley's Ideas and the Primary/Secondary DistinctionAuthor(s): Steven NadlerSource: Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 20, No. 1 (Mar., 1990), pp. 47-61Published by: Canadian Journal of PhilosophyStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/40231683.

    Accessed: 24/06/2014 12:58

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    Canadian Journal of Philosophyis collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to

    Canadian Journal of Philosophy.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Tue, 24 Jun 2014 12:58:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=cjphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/40231683?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/40231683?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=cjp
  • 8/12/2019 PhilosophyBerkeley's Ideas

    2/16

    Berkeley's

    deas

    nd the

    Primary/Secondary

    Distinction

    CANADIAN

    JOURNAL

    OF PHILOSOPHY

    47

    Volume

    20,

    Number

    1,

    March

    1990,

    pp.

    47-62

    STEVEN

    NADLER

    University

    of Wisconsin-Madison

    Madison, WI 53706

    U.S.A.

    Partof

    Berkeley's

    trategy

    n his attackon

    materialism

    n

    the ThreeDi-

    alogues

    Between

    Hylas

    and Philonous1s to

    argue

    that

    the

    epistemologi-

    cal

    distinction

    between ideas

    of

    so-called

    primary

    qualities

    and

    ideas

    of

    secondary qualities, especially

    as

    this distinction is found

    in

    Locke,

    is untenable.

    Both

    kinds of ideas -those

    presenting

    to

    the

    mind

    the

    quantifiable

    properties

    of

    bodies

    (shape,

    size, extension,

    motion)

    and

    those

    which are

    just

    sensations

    (color,

    odor, taste,

    heat)

    -are

    equally

    perceptions

    in the

    mind,

    and

    there is no reason to believe that

    one

    kind

    (the

    ideas of

    primaryqualities) represents

    true

    properties

    of in-

    dependently

    existing

    external

    objects

    while the

    other

    kind

    does not.

    In

    fact,

    close

    examinationreveals

    that the

    same or

    equally strong

    ar-

    guments

    can be

    used to

    prove

    either set of

    qualities

    mind

    dependent.'

    Since

    these

    two sets

    together comprise

    all the

    possible

    properties

    of

    a

    body,

    bodies

    are thus reducible to collections of

    sensible

    qualities,

    all similarlyin the mind of some perceiver.

    However,

    when

    Berkeley's

    rguments

    against

    the

    primary/secondary

    quality

    distinction are

    taken

    in

    conjunction

    with

    his

    solution to the

    problem

    of

    how it is that God

    (who

    provides

    us with all

    our

    sensible

    ideas

    of external

    objects) perceives pain,

    it

    becomes clear that

    while

    he

    may

    have

    proven

    his

    point

    against

    the materialist

    (and

    I

    do

    not

    examine

    this

    question here),

    he

    appears, ultimately,

    committed to a

    1 All references are to the Works

    of George Berkeley,

    Bishop

    of

    Cloyne,

    9

    vols.,

    A. A.

    Luce and T.E.

    Jessop,

    eds.

    (London:

    Nelson &

    Sons

    1949).

    TD

    =

    Three

    Dialogues

    Between

    Hylas

    and

    Philonous,

    in

    vol.

    2;

    PHK

    =

    Principles

    of

    Human

    Knowledge,

    in

    vol.

    2;

    PC

    =

    Philosophical

    Commentaries,

    n

    vol. 1. 1

    have also

    provided

    in

    brackets

    the

    corresponding page

    number from the

    readily

    available

    Berkeley's

    Philosophical

    Writings,

    David M.

    Armstrong,

    ed.

    (New

    York: Macmillan

    1965),

    abbreviated as

    'A.'

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Tue, 24 Jun 2014 12:58:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 PhilosophyBerkeley's Ideas

    3/16

    48

    Steven Nadler

    primary/secondary ualitydistinctionon epistemological rounds.That

    is,

    Berkeley's

    account

    of

    the differencebetween the

    way

    in

    which

    God

    perceives pain

    and

    the

    way

    in

    which we

    perceive pain provides

    an

    opening

    for a

    distinction between

    two

    kinds of

    sensory

    ideas:

    those

    which are

    perceived

    by

    God and

    us

    in

    the same

    way,

    and those which

    God

    perceives

    one

    way

    and

    which we

    perceive

    another

    way.

    And

    since

    God's

    perceptions

    or ideas are

    archetypal,

    one

    way

    in which

    they

    func-

    tion is as the standard

    by

    which

    our

    perceptions

    or

    sensory

    ideas

    are

    to be

    judged

    regarding

    the

    degree

    to

    which

    they

    succeed

    in

    making

    known their

    causal

    originals.

    Thus,

    the distinction

    s

    an

    epistemologi-

    cal one which falls along the same lines proposed by Locke.

    I

    Locke on

    Primary

    and

    Secondary

    Qualities

    The form of the

    primary/secondary

    uality

    distinction

    with

    which

    Ber-

    keley

    is

    immediately

    concerned is that

    found

    in Locke's

    An

    Essay

    Con-

    cerning

    Human

    Understanding,lthough

    the

    ancestry

    of the distinction

    goes

    back

    through

    Descartes, Galileo,

    and ancient

    Epicureanism.2

    All

    ideas,

    Locke

    nsists,

    are

    equally

    clear

    and

    positive

    ideas

    in

    the

    mind'-

    each can be clearlydistinguished from any other and identified as a

    discrete item

    in

    the

    understanding.

    And our

    perception

    of

    them is

    thoroughly

    adequate

    as

    long

    as we do not

    inquire

    nto the causes

    that

    may

    have

    produced

    them

    (Essay,

    Book

    II,

    ch.

    viii,

    sec.

    2,

    132-3).3

    The

    perception

    of

    white or

    heat,

    considered

    in

    itself,

    is no less

    a 'real

    posi-

    tive idea' than

    the

    perception

    of

    shape

    or size.

    These ideas

    in

    the

    mind

    are

    the effects of certain

    powers

    in

    external

    objects

    to

    produce

    them,

    powers

    which Locke calls

    'qualities.'

    Some

    of

    these

    qualities

    are

    'utterly

    inseparable

    from the

    body,

    in what

    es-

    tate soever

    it

    be,'

    and

    constitute what it means to be

    a material

    body.

    These qualities, which Locke calls 'primary,' nclude solidity, exten-

    sion,

    figure,

    motion,

    and number

    (Essay

    U, viii, 9-10,

    134-5).

    Other

    qual-

    ities which we

    perceive

    and

    (erroneously)

    attribute

    o bodies are

    really

    nothing

    but certain

    powers

    in

    the

    object

    to

    produce

    various sensations

    in

    us. These

    'powers'

    are a

    function

    of

    the

    arrangement

    of

    the

    primary

    qualities

    of the insensible

    particles

    of

    a

    body,

    and include

    among

    their

    effects our

    perceptions

    of

    color, sound, taste,

    smell,

    pain,

    pleasure,

    2

    See

    Descartes,

    Meditationson First

    Philosophy,

    Med.

    II; Galileo,

    TheAssayer,

    in

    Dis-

    coveries

    and

    Opinions

    of

    Galileo,

    trans. Stillman Drake

    (Garden

    City,

    NY:

    Double-

    day

    1957),

    274ff. See Edwin Arthur

    Burtt,

    The

    Metaphysical

    Foundations

    of

    Modern

    Physical

    Science,

    rev. ed.

    (New

    York:

    Harcourt, Brace,

    and Co.

    1932),

    75ff.

    3

    All

    page

    references to Locke's

    An

    Essay Concerning

    Human

    Understanding

    are to

    the text edited

    by

    P.H. Nidditch

    (Oxford:

    Oxford

    University

    Press

    1975).

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Tue, 24 Jun 2014 12:58:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 PhilosophyBerkeley's Ideas

    4/16

    Berkeley's

    deas

    and the

    Primary/Secondary

    Distinction 49

    heat, etc. All of this might be termed the ontologicalide of the prima-

    ry/secondaryquality

    distinction- that

    part

    of the distinctionconcerned

    with the

    physical

    basis for the actual

    and

    apparentproperties

    of mate-

    rialbodies.

    Thus,

    while

    primaryqualities

    reallybelong

    to

    objects,

    secon-

    dary

    qualities

    (at

    least as

    we know

    them)

    are

    merely

    the effects

    in

    the

    mind of the

    object's

    own

    primary

    qualities

    and of the

    bulk, texture,

    and motion of

    the insensible

    parts

    of which the

    object

    is

    composed

    (although

    the term

    'secondary

    quality'

    can also refer

    to that

    particular

    arrangement

    and

    organization

    of the

    corpuscles

    in the

    object

    causing

    this mental

    effect).

    The

    primary/secondary

    distinction can also be consideredfrom the

    'inside

    out,'

    so

    to

    speak;

    that

    is,

    as

    a

    theory regarding

    the

    epistemic

    value

    of our

    ideas or

    perceptions.

    Locke

    insists

    that our ideas of the

    primary

    qualities

    of bodies

    'are

    Resemblances

    of

    them,

    and the Pat-

    terns

    do

    really

    exist

    in

    the Bodies

    themselves.' For

    example,

    the

    square-

    ness

    I

    perceive

    (allowing

    for the

    distortion of

    perspective)

    really

    characterizes

    he table

    I

    am

    looking

    at;

    it is

    an

    actual

    property

    of the

    external

    object

    accurately

    reflected

    in

    that

    object's appearance

    to

    my

    mind. The

    ideas of

    (or

    produced

    by)

    secondary qualities,

    on the other

    hand, 'have no resemblanceto them at all. There is nothing like our

    Ideas

    [of

    secondaryqualities]

    existing

    in the Bodies

    themselves'

    (Essay

    II,

    viii, 15,

    137).

    There

    is

    nothing

    even

    remotely

    similarto the redness

    I

    perceive

    in the

    object

    causing

    that

    perception:

    only

    a

    corresponding

    'texture'

    of the

    body's

    minute

    particles.

    Thus,

    the

    distinctionbetween

    primary

    quality

    ideas

    and

    secondary quality

    ideas

    is,

    in

    an

    important

    sense,

    an

    epistemological

    istinction.

    The

    former

    provide

    us

    with

    accurate

    knowledge

    of the

    external

    world,

    telling

    us

    in

    detail

    about the

    proper-

    ties

    that

    really

    characterize

    material

    objects

    (at

    least at the

    macroscop-

    ic

    level).

    As Locke

    puts

    it,

    'we have

    by

    these an Idea of the

    thing,

    as

    it is in itself' (Essay I, viii, 23, 140). Secondary quality ideas, on the

    contrary,

    do

    not

    at all

    resemble the

    properties

    in

    the

    object

    that cause

    them,

    and

    thus

    are

    not

    a

    reliable source of

    knowledge

    about

    the

    true

    nature

    of that

    object

    (though

    they

    do tell us much

    about

    how

    those

    objects

    relate

    to us-

    which

    are

    painful

    and to be

    avoided,

    which are

    pleasurable,

    etc.).4

    In

    other

    words,

    a

    primary

    quality

    idea

    resembles

    4

    It should be noted

    that the

    primary/secondary

    distinction,

    even

    at

    the level

    of

    ideas alone, need not be only an epistemological distinction. Malebranche, for

    example,

    argues

    that

    sensations,

    which do

    not

    at all resemble

    external

    objects,

    are modifications of the human

    mind,

    while

    pure

    ideas

    (truly

    representing

    the

    quantitative properties

    of

    objects)

    are

    not

    part

    of the human

    mind

    but

    are

    in

    God.

    Thus,

    in

    Malebranche,

    the

    epistemological

    difference between

    sensations and ideas

    is

    paralleled

    by

    an

    ontological

    difference.

    See De

    la

    recherchede la

    viriti,

    especially

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Tue, 24 Jun 2014 12:58:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 PhilosophyBerkeley's Ideas

    5/16

    50 Steven

    Nadler

    and makes known its causal original;a secondary quality idea does

    not.

    This

    particular

    ormulationof the distinction

    will

    be

    important

    or

    my

    argument

    below.

    II

    Berkeley

    on

    Primary

    and

    Secondary

    Qualities

    Berkeley

    has two tacks for

    establishing

    the

    general

    claim that

    the

    per-

    ceived

    properties

    of

    objects

    are all

    really

    nothing

    more

    than

    sensible

    qualities

    existing

    in

    the mind. With

    regard

    to

    what Locke calls

    secon-

    daryqualities(heat, cold, color, taste, smell, etc.), his strategyis first

    to

    show that

    the

    quality

    is identical

    with either

    a

    pleasure

    or a

    pain

    of

    some

    degree.

    He then

    argues

    that

    since

    it is clear

    that

    a

    pleasure

    or a

    pain

    cannot

    exist

    except

    n a

    perceiving

    mind,

    the

    respective

    quality

    is

    only

    a

    mind-dependent

    sensation.

    To

    take,

    for

    example,

    the case

    of

    heat,

    Berkeley argues

    along

    the

    following

    lines:

    1.

    Intense heat is a

    pain.

    2. No

    unperceiving thing

    is

    capable

    of

    pain

    or

    pleasure.

    3. Materialsubstance is a senseless, unperceiving thing.

    4.

    Therefore,

    materialsubstance cannot

    be the

    subject

    of

    pain

    or

    pleasure.

    5.

    Therefore,

    material

    substance

    cannot

    be the

    subject

    of intense

    heat.

    6. There

    must

    be some

    subject

    n

    which

    a

    pain

    or

    pleasure

    exists.

    By

    2,

    this

    subject

    must be

    a

    perceiving

    thing.

    7.

    Therefore,

    ntense

    heat exists

    only

    in a

    perceiving

    subject;

    or,

    alternately, ntenseheatexistsonly in a mindperceiving t. (TD

    I,

    175-8

    [A, 139-42])

    The

    argument

    is

    then extended

    to

    'any degree

    of

    heat

    whatsoever/

    both

    painful

    and

    pleasant.

    I

    do not here examine

    the

    validity

    of the

    argument

    as

    a whole or its

    premises.

    Philonous

    argues

    at

    length

    for 1

    (TD

    I,

    176ff.

    [A,

    140ff.]).5

    And

    Hylas

    himself

    readily

    grants

    3

    Book

    I,

    chapter

    13;

    Book

    III,

    part

    2;

    and fidaircissement

    X.

    An excellent

    discus-

    sion of

    the

    primary/secondary

    distinction

    in Locke is

    in Peter

    Alexander, Ideas,

    Qualities,

    and

    Corpuscles:

    Locke

    and

    Boyle

    on the

    External

    World

    (Cambridge:

    Cam-

    bridge University

    Press

    1985),

    esp.

    ch. 6-8.

    5

    For a

    discussion

    of the first

    premise,

    see

    George

    Pitcher,

    Berkeley

    London:

    Rout-

    ledge

    and

    Kegan

    Paul

    1977),

    lOOff

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Tue, 24 Jun 2014 12:58:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 PhilosophyBerkeley's Ideas

    6/16

    Berkeley's

    deas and the

    Primary/Secondary

    Distinction

    51

    (TD1, 176[A, 140])and 6 (TD1, 177[A, 141]).WhatBerkeleycleverly

    does

    here is

    identify

    intense heat

    with

    something

    which is

    evidently

    and

    undeniably ncapable

    of

    existing

    outside

    of a

    perceiving

    mind:

    pain.

    He

    argues

    similarly

    with

    respect

    to

    warmth,

    reducing

    it

    to a

    pleasure,

    and

    with

    respect

    to an intense

    degree

    of cold

    (TD

    1,

    178

    [A, 142]).

    While

    Philonousdoes

    not

    explicitly

    apply

    the

    pleasure/painargument

    o lesser

    degrees

    of

    cold,

    this seems

    to be due less to

    its

    inapplicability

    o these

    sensations

    than to

    Hylas'

    ntractability.

    believe that

    Berkeley

    does con-

    sider the

    argument

    to work

    in

    regard

    to

    all

    degrees

    of

    cold,

    just

    as he

    believes

    it to

    apply

    to

    all

    degrees

    of heat.

    He then moves on to

    taste

    (179

    {A, 143])

    and odor

    (180 [A, 144])

    n the same manner: each

    quali-

    ty

    is

    perceived

    n

    some

    degree

    as either a

    pleasure

    or

    a

    pain,

    and there-

    fore

    cannot

    exist

    in

    anything

    but

    a

    perceiving

    substance

    (mind).6

    It is

    important

    o

    note that

    Berkeley'spoint

    is not

    merely

    that

    heat,

    tastes,

    and

    other

    'secondary qualities'

    are

    invariablyaccompanied

    by

    pain

    or

    pleasure,

    nor even

    that

    they

    always

    cause

    pain

    or

    pleasure.

    Rather,

    these

    qualities

    just

    are

    pains

    or

    pleasures.

    Berkeley

    s

    identify-

    ing

    intense

    heat

    with

    a

    certain

    kind of

    pain,

    warmth

    with a certainkind

    of

    pleasure,

    and so

    on. When

    Hylas suggests

    that

    pain

    is

    'something

    distinct from heat, and the consequence or effect of it,' Philonous

    responds

    by arguing

    that the

    immediatelyperceived

    heat and the

    pain

    are 'one

    simple

    or

    uncompounded

    idea...

    the intense

    heat immediate-

    ly perceived

    is

    nothing

    distinct

    from a

    particular

    ort of

    pain'

    (TD

    I,

    176

    [A,

    140]).

    Likewise,

    sweetness

    and bitterness

    just

    are

    'particular

    sorts

    of

    pleasure

    and

    pain'

    (180

    [A, 144]).

    What

    we have here is

    a

    strict

    identification

    f sensible

    quality

    with

    pleasure

    or

    pain.

    With

    regard

    to

    light

    and

    colors,

    Berkeley

    does not

    explicitly

    use the

    pleasure/pain

    argument

    for their mind

    dependence,

    preferring

    o

    rely

    instead

    mainly

    on

    an

    argument

    from the

    relativity

    and

    variability

    of

    appearance TD1,183f [A, 148-9]).Butit is quiteconceivablehow the

    6

    Berkeley

    also backs

    up

    this

    pain/pleasure

    argument

    or

    the

    mind-dependence

    of

    sensible

    qualities

    with

    arguments

    from the

    relativity

    and

    variability

    of

    appear-

    ance

    ('that

    which at other

    times seems

    sweet,

    shall,

    to

    a

    distemperedpalate,

    ap-

    pear

    bitter7).

    ee

    Pitcher,

    104-6.

    Berkeley

    ometimes

    appears

    o believe

    that either

    argument

    s,

    in

    itself,

    sufficient

    o

    prove

    his

    point.

    For

    example,

    after

    Philonous

    uses

    the

    pain/pleasureargument

    with

    respect

    to

    taste,

    Hylas

    gives up:

    'I see no

    purpose

    to hold

    out,

    so

    I

    give up

    the cause

    as to

    these

    mentioned

    qualities'

    TD

    1,

    180

    [A,

    144]).

    Philonous

    only

    introduces

    he

    relativity

    argument

    for

    your

    far-

    thersatisfaction/1have yet to come acrossany commentatorswho look on the

    pleasure/pain

    argument

    as

    anything

    more than

    a mistake.

    See,

    for

    example,

    GJ.

    Warnock,

    Berkeley

    Notre

    Dame:

    University

    of Notre

    Dame Press

    1983),

    146ff For

    a more

    general

    discussion of the distinction

    and

    relationship

    between ideas

    and

    pleasure

    or

    pain

    in

    Berkeley,

    ee Genevieve

    Brykman,

    Tleasure

    and Pain

    Versus

    Ideas

    in

    Berkeley/

    Hermathena

    39

    (1985)

    127-37.

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Tue, 24 Jun 2014 12:58:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 PhilosophyBerkeley's Ideas

    7/16

    52

    Steven Nadler

    pleasure/painargumentcan (indeed, should, or Berkeley)be applied

    to color and

    other

    phenomena

    of

    light.

    It

    is clear

    that a

    light

    or color

    can be so

    intense as to

    be

    painful

    or

    discomforting;

    and it can be

    of

    such a

    degree

    as makes it

    soothing

    and

    pleasant.

    The same

    move

    (how-

    ever

    mistaken)

    which allows

    Berkeley

    o

    identify

    heat

    or cold or tastes

    or odors with

    pleasures

    and

    pains

    will

    clearly

    lead

    him

    to

    make

    the

    same

    identificationwith

    regard

    to

    light

    and

    colors.7

    This

    is,

    I

    believe,

    merely

    a

    logical

    extension of

    Berkeley's rgument,

    and one

    that he

    him-

    self would

    sanction

    though

    it

    may

    also lead us

    to see more

    clearly

    ome

    of the

    problems

    in

    the

    general

    kind of identification

    Berkeley

    wants

    to make between sensible

    qualities

    and

    pains

    or

    pleasures).

    Thus,

    as

    part

    of

    his

    argumentagainst

    the

    materialist,

    Berkeley

    den-

    tifies those

    qualities

    which Lockeclassifies as

    'secondary7

    color,

    heat,

    odor,

    etc.)

    with

    pains

    or

    pleasures,

    and thus

    gives

    them

    an undenia-

    ble

    dependence

    on

    a

    perceiving

    mind.

    His

    strategy

    with

    regard

    to

    what

    Locke classifies

    as

    'primary'

    quali-

    ties is

    different.

    In

    order to

    prove

    that there is no Lockean

    distinction

    between

    primary

    and

    secondary qualities,

    Berkeley argues

    that

    both

    kinds of

    qualities

    are

    equally

    'in

    the

    mind/

    and that the ideas

    present-

    ing them are on the same epistemicfooting with respect

    to

    represent-

    ing something

    external

    o

    the

    mind. But

    Berkeley's

    arguments

    hat this

    is so

    with

    regard

    to

    shape,

    size, motion,

    extension,

    and

    solidity

    make

    no

    reference

    (and

    wisely

    so)

    to

    pleasures

    and

    pains.8

    Rather,

    in both

    the

    Principles

    of

    Human

    Knowledge

    and the

    Three

    Dialogues,

    Berkeley

    re-

    lies

    mainly

    on the

    relativity

    and

    variability

    of

    perception

    argument

    to

    establish

    the

    mind-dependence

    of these

    qualities.

    To take the cases

    of

    extension

    and

    texture,

    an

    object

    that

    appears

    to

    an adult

    human

    ob-

    server as

    extremely

    small

    and

    barely

    discernible

    appears

    to a mite

    as

    extremely large.

    Or,

    the same

    object appears

    different

    in

    figure

    and

    texturewhen viewed by the naked eye and when viewed through a

    7 The case of color

    might

    be

    a

    bit more

    complex

    and

    problematic

    han

    the

    others,

    since

    it is clear

    that an

    intense

    and

    sharp perception

    of

    red,

    however

    painful

    or

    uncomfortable,

    nvolves

    something

    more

    than the

    sensation

    of

    pain,

    i.e. redness.

    It

    does

    not

    seem, however,

    that this

    fact,

    in

    itself,

    seriously

    weakens

    Berkeley's

    argument,

    since

    the

    painfulness

    would

    be for

    him

    an essential

    and

    inseparable

    part

    of

    the

    sensible

    quality.

    Its

    painfulness

    would

    be essential to

    its

    identity

    as

    this

    particular

    ed-perception.

    And its

    inherent

    ainfulness

    would

    place

    it,

    with

    the

    other

    qualities,

    in the mind.

    8

    Berkeley

    notes

    that

    a version

    of the

    pleasure/pain

    rgument

    probably

    layed

    some

    kind of role

    in the

    genesis

    of the

    primary/secondary

    istinction,

    since the

    pres-

    ence or

    absence

    of

    pleasure

    and

    pain

    constitutes

    a clear

    differentiation

    etween

    the two sets

    of

    qualities.

    See

    TD

    I,

    191-2

    (A, 155).

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Tue, 24 Jun 2014 12:58:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 PhilosophyBerkeley's Ideas

    8/16

    Berkeley's

    deas

    and the

    Primary/Secondary

    Distinction

    53

    microscope. Since one and the same thing cannot at the same time

    be of two different

    dimensions,

    or have two different

    textures

    (and

    we are

    assuming

    that

    no

    change

    takes

    place

    in

    the

    object

    itself),

    the

    extension

    or texture

    perceived

    does not exist

    in

    the

    external

    object,

    but

    rather

    in

    the

    perceiving

    mind.

    Philonous:

    Was

    it not admitted as

    a

    good argument,

    that neither heat nor

    cold

    was in the

    water,

    because

    it seemed

    warm to one hand and cold

    to the other?. . .Is

    it not the

    very

    same

    reasoning

    to

    conclude,

    there is no

    extension or

    figure

    in an

    object,

    because

    to one

    eye

    it

    shall seem

    little, smooth,

    and

    round,

    when at the

    same time it

    appears

    to the

    other,

    great,

    uneven,

    and

    angular?

    (TD

    1,

    189

    [A, 153])

    The kind of

    argument

    Berkeley

    s

    using

    here

    is,

    by

    now,

    quite

    famil-

    iar. From

    the

    variability

    relative

    to

    a

    single

    observer

    at one or

    differ-

    ent

    times,

    or

    to several

    observers)

    of the

    appearance

    f

    a

    quality

    shape,

    color),

    it is concluded

    that

    the

    quality

    does

    not

    belong

    to an external

    object,

    but

    is

    a

    perception

    or idea

    in the mind.9

    To insist otherwise

    would

    be

    to ascribe

    ncompatible

    properties

    to the same

    object

    at

    the

    same

    time

    (two

    different

    colors

    or

    shapes);

    or to claim

    that different

    successive

    properties

    really

    belong

    to the same

    object

    although

    the ob-

    ject

    itself

    has

    not

    undergone

    any

    alteration. As

    Berkeley

    claims,

    Let

    any

    one

    consider

    those

    arguments

    which

    are

    thought

    manifestly

    to

    prove

    that

    colors

    and tastes

    exist

    only

    in the

    mind,

    and he shall

    find

    they may

    with

    equal

    force

    be

    brought

    to

    prove

    the same

    thing

    of

    extension,

    figure,

    and motion.

    (PHK

    15,

    47

    [A,

    66-7])10

    Berkeley

    has

    in

    mind

    here

    only

    the

    relativity

    argument,

    not

    the

    pain/pleasure

    argument.

    And

    he

    applies

    it

    equally

    to

    extension,

    fig-

    ure,

    motion,

    solidity,

    and number

    Locke's

    primary

    qualities

    as

    I

    note

    above,

    in

    the

    Dialogues

    e

    also

    applies

    it to

    secondaryqualities

    n order

    to supplement the pain/pleasure argument).11

    9 See

    also

    PHK

    9-15,

    where

    Berkeley incorporates

    into his

    argument

    a claim

    regard-

    ing

    the

    inseparability

    of the

    so-called

    primary

    and

    secondary qualities.

    10

    This

    application

    of the

    relativity argument

    to

    primary qualities

    has

    its most evi-

    dent

    source

    in

    Pierre

    Bayle's

    Dictionnaire

    Historique

    et

    Critique,

    article on

    Zeno,

    remark

    G.

    For

    a

    study

    of

    this

    influence,

    see Richard

    H.

    Popkin,

    'Berkeley

    and

    Pyrrhonism/

    in

    Myles

    Burnyeat,

    ed.,

    The

    Skeptical

    Tradition

    (Berkeley:

    Universi-

    ty

    of California

    Press

    1983),

    377-%.

    11

    Margaret

    Wilson

    argues

    (against

    Mandelbaum, Alexander, and Mackie) that Ber-

    keley

    does

    not

    make

    the

    mistake

    of

    overestimating

    the

    importance

    for Locke of

    the

    relativity

    argument

    in

    establishing

    the

    primary/secondary

    quality

    distinction.

    See

    her

    Did

    Berkeley

    Completely

    Misunderstand the

    Basis of the

    Primary-

    Secondary

    Quality

    Distinction

    in

    Locke?/

    in Colin

    Turbayne,

    ed.,

    Berkeley:

    Criti-

    cal and

    Interpretive

    Essays

    (Manchester:

    Manchester

    University

    Press

    1982),

    108-23.

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Tue, 24 Jun 2014 12:58:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 PhilosophyBerkeley's Ideas

    9/16

    54 Steven

    Nadler

    Thus, by the middle of the firstdialogue, Berkeleyhas gained much

    ground

    n

    his

    argument

    against

    he

    materialist.He

    thinkshe has shown

    that there is

    good

    reason

    to

    dispense

    with the distinction

    between

    pri-

    mary

    and

    secondaryqualities,

    at

    least

    in

    its traditional orm.

    All

    of

    our

    perceptions-

    both those of

    colors, tastes, sounds,

    and

    odors,

    and those

    of

    extension,

    figure,

    solidity,

    and motion- are on the same

    ontologi-

    cal and

    epistemological

    evel.

    All

    of these are sensible

    qualities

    in the

    mind,

    and none of them

    are,

    in

    themselves,

    more accurate

    represen-

    tations

    of an

    'external

    eality'

    han

    any

    others. The so-called

    secondary

    qualities

    are

    all

    species

    of

    pain

    or

    pleasure,

    and

    therefore

    necessarily

    exist in a

    perceiving

    mind. The so-called

    primaryqualities

    vary

    in

    ap-

    pearance

    as much as

    do

    colors,

    tastes,

    and

    odors,

    and therefore

    are

    not

    inherent

    properties

    of

    an

    independently

    existing

    external

    object,

    but are

    (like

    other

    sensible

    qualities)

    in

    a

    perceiving

    mind.

    Ill

    God's

    Pain

    Berkeley's

    oncern to account

    for,

    on his

    principles,

    the distinction

    be-

    tween ideas of sense and ideas of imagination,or between

    those

    strong

    and

    vivid ideas which we

    undergo involuntarily

    and those

    less-lively

    ones which we

    conjure

    up

    on our

    own,

    leads him

    to

    maintain

    hat our

    ideas

    of

    sense,

    our

    perceptions

    of external

    objects

    and all those

    sensa-

    tions

    which we feel

    and

    suffer,

    are

    produced

    in

    our

    mind

    by

    God.

    Philonous: It is

    evident that the

    things

    I

    perceive

    are

    my

    own

    ideas,

    and

    that

    no

    idea can exist

    unless it be

    in

    a

    mind;

    nor

    it

    is

    less

    plain

    that

    these

    ideas

    or

    things

    by

    me

    perceived,

    either themselves

    or their

    archetypes,

    exist

    independently

    of

    my

    mind,

    since I know

    myself

    not to be

    their

    author,

    it

    being

    out

    of

    my power

    to determine at

    pleasure

    what

    particular

    deas

    I

    shall be affected

    with

    upon

    opening

    my eyes or ears: they must therefore exist in some other Mind, whose Will it is

    they

    should be exhibited to

    me.

    (TD

    II,

    214-15

    [A, 177])

    This efficacious

    Mind or

    Will

    is

    God.

    And

    this

    passage

    (among

    others)

    clearly

    indicates

    that

    Berkeley's

    God,

    as the

    governing

    mind

    which

    causes ideas

    to

    appear

    in

    the

    human

    mind,

    is

    him/herself

    the

    subject

    of

    ideas.12

    12 See TD m, 239 (A, 202): 'A thing which hath no ideas in itself cannot impart them

    to

    me';

    and PC

    641,

    78: 'We

    find

    in our own

    minds a

    great

    Number of different

    Ideas. We

    may Imagine

    in

    God

    a Greater

    number....'

    J.D.

    Mabbott

    argues

    that

    Berkeley

    did not

    make the

    Divine

    Ideas an essential

    part

    of his

    system,

    and that

    there is

    good

    reason

    to doubt

    whether

    Berkeley's

    God

    has ideas at

    all;

    see 'The

    Place of God

    in

    Berkeley's

    Philosophy/

    Philosophy

    (1931),

    reprinted

    in CD. Martin

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Tue, 24 Jun 2014 12:58:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 PhilosophyBerkeley's Ideas

    10/16

    Berkeley's

    deas and the

    Primary/

    Secondary

    Distinction

    55

    This leads Hylas to raise the question of God's pain. It is an imper-

    fection to suffer

    pain.

    We are sometimes affected with

    pain

    and

    un-

    easiness

    by

    some other

    Being,

    as Philonous

    claims.

    And

    whatever deas

    we

    perceive

    from without are

    in

    the

    mind

    which so

    affectsus

    ('A

    thing

    which

    hath no

    ideas

    in

    itself cannot

    impart

    them

    to

    me').

    Therefore,

    the ideas

    of

    pain

    and uneasiness

    are

    in

    God,

    and

    (it

    would

    seem)

    God

    suffers

    pain.

    But this would

    be tantamount

    to

    admitting

    an

    imperfec-

    tion

    in the divine nature.

    Berkeley

    has several

    responses

    to this

    conundrum,

    the most worka-

    ble

    and consistent

    of which is

    to draw

    a distinction between the

    wayin which God knows

    pain

    and the

    way

    in which we know

    (or

    suffer)

    pain-

    in

    essence,

    to draw

    a

    qualitative

    distinction

    between

    some of

    God's

    ideas

    and the

    corresponding

    ones

    in our

    minds

    (or,

    alternately,

    between

    God's

    perception

    of

    some

    qualities

    and

    our

    perception

    of

    the

    same).13

    Philonous:

    That God

    knows or understands

    all

    things,

    and that

    He

    knows

    among

    other

    things

    what

    pain

    is,

    even

    every

    sort

    of

    painful

    sensation,

    and

    what it

    is

    for

    His creatures

    to suffer

    pain,

    I make no

    question.

    But,

    that

    God,

    though

    He

    knows

    and sometimes

    causes

    painful

    sensations

    in

    us,

    can

    Himself suffer

    pain,

    I positively deny. . .To know everything knowable is certainly a perfection; but

    to

    endure,

    or

    suffer,

    or

    feel

    anything

    by

    sense,

    is

    an

    imperfection.

    The

    former,

    I

    say, agrees

    to

    God,

    but

    not the

    latter.

    God

    knows

    or

    hath

    ideas;

    but

    His ideas

    are

    not

    convey'd

    to

    Him

    by

    sense,

    as ours

    are.

    (TD

    III,

    240-1

    [A, 202-3])

    This

    kind of

    problem

    had

    clearly

    occurred

    to

    Berkeleyearly

    on.

    Thus,

    in the

    Philosophical

    ommentaries,

    erkeley

    nsists

    that 'God

    May

    com-

    prehend

    all

    Ideas

    even

    the

    Ideas

    which

    are

    painfull

    &

    unpleasant

    with-

    out

    being

    in

    any

    degree

    pained

    thereby.

    Thus we our

    selves can

    imagine

    the

    pain

    of

    a

    burn,

    etc.

    without

    any misery

    or

    uneasiness at

    all'(PC675, 82 [A, 365]).God thus has an idea of pain, or knowledge

    of

    pain,

    without

    feeling

    or

    suffering pain.

    This solution

    raises

    ts own

    questions.14

    or

    example,

    Berkeley

    s

    com-

    mitted

    to the

    claim

    that

    all

    of

    our

    ideas either

    have

    their

    immediate

    and D.M.

    Armstrong,

    eds.,

    Locke

    and

    Berkeley

    Garden

    City,

    NY:

    Anchor

    Books

    1968)

    364-75.

    George

    Thomas

    argues

    that

    Berkeley's

    God

    may

    have

    ideas,

    but

    His relation

    to these

    ideas

    is

    not

    that

    of

    perception;

    see

    'Berkeley's

    God

    Does Not

    Perceive,' Journalof the History of Philosophy 14 (1976) 163-8.

    13

    For a

    good

    discussion

    of

    this,

    and

    a

    comparison

    of

    Berkeley's

    several

    arguments

    concerning

    God's

    pain,

    see

    Donald

    Gotterbarn,

    'Berkeley:

    God's

    Pain,'

    Philosophical

    Studies 28

    (1975)

    245-54.

    14

    See

    Gotterbarn,

    250ff

    .

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Tue, 24 Jun 2014 12:58:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 PhilosophyBerkeley's Ideas

    11/16

    56 Steven Nadler

    sourcein the senses or innerexperience,or are derivedsomehow (e.g.

    by imagination)

    rom these

    primary

    ones

    (PHK

    1,

    41

    [A, 61]).

    But,

    as

    the

    passage immediately

    above

    indicates,

    none of God's

    ideas are con-

    veyed

    to

    him/her

    by

    sense

    as ours are.

    How,

    then,

    can

    our

    ability

    to

    imagine

    pain

    without

    feeling

    it

    (an

    ability

    founded on some

    prior

    sen-

    sory

    experience

    of

    pain) help

    us understand

    the

    kind

    of

    knowledge

    or

    idea God must have of

    pain?

    Nonetheless,

    this is

    Berkeley's

    solution

    to the

    problem

    raised

    by

    Hylas.

    There is

    a

    generic

    difference

    between the

    idea we have

    of

    pain

    and

    God's idea of

    pain.

    Ours is

    a

    painful

    sensation;

    God knows

    pain

    but does not sense it. And it is clearthat this samesolutionmust

    apply

    to

    pleasure:

    God can be no more

    susceptible

    to

    pleasures

    (at

    least as

    we

    experience

    them)

    than to

    pains.

    To

    feel

    pleasure

    is to

    undergo,

    to

    receive,

    or to 'suffer7

    pleasant

    feelings.

    It is to be

    passive,

    to be affect-

    ed from

    without.

    Pleasures are

    involuntary

    and

    capricious,

    although

    we can take

    steps

    to

    help

    insure

    that certain

    pleasures

    are forthcom-

    ing.

    But

    none of

    this

    can

    apply

    to God.

    God,

    'whom no external

    being

    can

    affect. whose

    will

    is absolute

    and

    independent,

    causing

    all

    things,

    and

    liableto be thwartedor resisted

    by

    nothing.

    can

    suffer othing,

    nor

    be affectedwith any painfulsensation,

    or indeed

    any

    sensation

    t all'

    (TD

    III,

    241

    [A,

    203],

    emphases

    added).

    God

    is no more

    capable

    of

    feeling

    pleasure

    han

    s/he is of

    feeling pain.

    S/He does

    (indeed,

    s/he

    must)

    have

    an idea

    (a

    knowledge)

    of

    pleasure

    and of

    pain.

    This is

    necessary

    or God

    to be able

    to cause

    them

    in

    us. But

    God's

    idea or

    knowledge

    of each

    is

    radically

    different

    from

    ours,

    which

    is

    conveyed

    by

    the senses.

    IV

    Reintroducing

    Primary

    and

    Secondary

    Qualities

    I argue that the result of Berkeley'ssolution to the problemof God's

    pain

    is

    the reintroduction

    of the

    epistemological

    side

    of the

    distinction

    between ideas of

    primary qualities

    and

    ideas of

    secondary

    qualities,

    although

    this distinction does

    not have the

    same

    ontological

    founda-

    tions

    which

    it

    has

    in

    Locke. More

    particularly,

    when

    Berkeley's

    argu-

    ments

    for the

    mind-dependence

    of such

    qualities

    as

    colors,

    tastes,

    and

    odors,

    along

    with his different

    arguments

    for

    the

    mind-dependence

    of

    such

    qualities

    as

    extension,

    figure,

    size,

    and

    motion,

    are

    taken

    in

    conjunction

    with the distinctionbetween

    God's

    ideas of

    pain

    and

    pleas-

    ure and

    our

    deas of

    pain

    and

    pleasure,

    it becomes

    clear

    that

    Berkeley

    is committedto an epistemologicaldifferencebetween two classes of

    ideas,

    and

    the class line falls

    precisely

    along

    the line drawn

    by

    Locke

    between

    primary

    and

    secondary qualities.

    Berkeley's

    arguments

    or the

    mind-dependence

    of

    colors,

    tastes, etc.,

    while

    also

    making

    referenceto

    the

    variability

    and

    relativity

    of

    appear-

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Tue, 24 Jun 2014 12:58:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 PhilosophyBerkeley's Ideas

    12/16

    Berkeley's

    deas and

    the

    Primary/Secondary

    Distinction

    57

    ance, rely mainly, as we saw, on identifying these sensible qualities

    with

    species

    of

    pain

    or

    pleasure.

    This

    is

    explicitly

    true of

    heat,

    cold,

    taste,

    and odor.

    And,

    I

    argue,

    it

    must also

    be true of color. On

    the

    other

    hand,

    his

    arguments

    for

    the

    mind-dependence

    of

    the

    quantita-

    tive

    properties

    of bodies

    (figure,

    extension,

    etc.)

    are based

    only

    on the

    variability

    nd

    relativity

    of

    appearance,

    and not at all

    on the

    pain/pleas-

    ure

    argument.

    Colors, tastes, odors,

    and their

    like

    just

    are,

    for Ber-

    keley,

    kinds of

    pleasure

    and

    pain,

    as his

    arguments

    n

    the First

    Dialogue

    explictly

    state.

    This is not true of the other ideas

    in

    the

    mind.

    But

    this means

    that for a whole

    class

    of

    qualities,

    there is a radical

    differencebetween the

    way

    in which we know them and the

    way

    in

    which

    God knows them.

    If

    colors, tastes,

    and odors are

    pains

    or

    pleas-

    ures,

    then

    Berkeley's

    solution to the

    problem

    of God's

    pain implies

    that

    our deas of

    colors,

    tastes,

    and odors are

    genetically

    different rom

    God's.

    We sense

    hese

    qualities,

    we

    feel

    them in

    their

    painfulness

    and

    pleasantness.

    It is not

    simply

    a difference

    n

    the

    way

    in

    which the ideas

    are

    conveyed

    into the

    mind

    (we

    have

    bodily

    sense

    organs,

    God does

    not),

    but a difference

    in

    the

    phenomenological

    characterof the

    per-

    ception

    of

    the ideas. Since

    for us the essence of

    pain

    or

    pleasure

    is

    its feltcharacter,ourperceptionof eachof these sensiblequalitiesdoes

    not,

    in its most essential

    aspect,

    correspond

    to God's

    perception

    or

    knowledge

    of the same

    quality.

    This is

    not true

    of our ideas of

    extension,

    solidity, figure,

    and

    mo-

    tion.

    Since,

    for

    Berkeley,

    these

    qualities

    are not identical with

    pleas-

    ures

    or

    pains,

    there is no

    reason to

    suppose

    that God's

    ideas or

    perceptions

    of

    them

    are,

    in

    any

    essential

    aspect,

    different from ours.

    The

    only purpose

    for which

    Berkeley

    ntroduces

    n

    the

    Dialogues

    dis-

    tinction

    between

    God's ideas

    and our ideas is to cover the

    problem

    of

    pain

    (and

    pleasure).

    And

    in

    the absence of the

    problems attending

    the case of pain, there is good reason to think that God's perception

    of

    these

    'primary'

    qualities

    and our

    perception

    of them

    correspond,

    since

    God

    is

    the cause of ours.

    Thus,

    there is

    one class of

    qualities

    (color,

    heat, cold, odor,

    taste)

    our

    perception

    of

    which doesnot

    correspond

    o God's

    perception.

    There

    is

    another class of

    qualities

    (extension,

    figure,

    solidity,

    motion,

    num-

    ber)

    our

    perception

    of which

    does

    correspond

    o God's

    perception.

    And

    note

    that the two classes

    are

    extensionally

    identical

    with

    those Locke

    calls

    secondary qualities

    and

    primary qualities, respectively.

    Why

    this should be

    a

    problem

    for

    Berkeley,

    and how it

    reintroduces

    an epistemologicalistinction between ideas of primary qualities and

    ideas

    of

    secondary qualities,

    becomes clear

    if

    we recall that

    for Ber-

    keley,

    God's

    ideas

    (or

    God's

    perceptions)

    are

    archetypal

    and

    original,

    while our

    ideas

    (or

    perceptions)

    are

    ectypal

    and derivative. What this

    means

    is that

    it makes sense

    to examine

    our ideas

    concerning

    their

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Tue, 24 Jun 2014 12:58:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 PhilosophyBerkeley's Ideas

    13/16

    58 Steven

    Nadler

    success or failure in accurately corresponding to, resembling, or

    representing

    God's ideas. God's ideas or

    perceptions

    are a standard

    according

    to

    which our

    perceptions

    can be

    judged,

    the model from

    which

    they

    are

    causally

    derived

    and

    to which

    they

    can be

    compared.

    Philonous:

    So

    may you suppose

    an external

    archetype

    on

    my

    principles;

    -external,

    I

    mean,

    to

    your

    own mind:

    though

    indeed it must be

    supposed

    to exist in that

    Mind which

    comprehends

    all

    things.

    (TD

    III,

    248

    [A, 210-11])

    I have no

    objection against calling

    the ideas in the mind

    of

    God,

    archetypes

    of

    ours.

    (Berkeley

    to Samuel

    Johnson,

    March

    24, 1730, Works,

    vol.

    2,

    292

    [A, 246])

    Three

    remarksare warrantedhere before

    proceeding.

    First,

    my

    claim

    about

    an

    epistemological

    istinction

    among Berkeley's

    deas should be

    distinguished

    from the

    claim,

    which

    I

    am not

    making,

    that for

    Ber-

    keley

    the

    primary

    source of the

    epistemic

    value of

    our ideas is their

    success

    or

    failure

    in

    corresponding

    to God's ideas.

    Epistemology

    for

    Berkeley

    s a matter internal to the world

    of our

    ideas -it

    regards

    co-

    herence

    and interrelations

    among

    them,

    not their

    correspondence

    to

    some extra-ideal

    reality,

    divine or material. So

    strictly

    speaking,

    the

    epistemic

    value of our ideas is

    a

    function

    of the

    degree

    to

    which

    they

    coherewith, and allow us to anticipate, orthcoming deas.15Myclaim,

    on

    the other

    hand,

    is that there is a

    clear,

    but

    different and un-

    Berkeleian,

    sense

    in

    which

    all

    of

    Berkeley's

    deas are not on

    the

    same

    epistemic

    footing.

    Second,

    my argument

    relies on

    treating

    an

    archetype

    as

    something

    which

    an

    ectype

    may

    be taken as

    purporting

    to

    represent

    and, thus,

    make known.

    And

    this is

    an

    understanding

    of the term

    which Ber-

    keley

    would be

    quite

    familiar

    with,

    and

    perhaps

    even be

    expected

    to

    have

    in

    mind

    in

    the

    Dialogues.

    Locke himself uses the terms 'arche-

    type'

    and

    'ectype'

    o refer o the

    capacity

    of ideas to

    represent

    or

    resem-

    ble (andthus makeknown) their causal

    originals.

    Ideas,he insists, are

    'ectypes'

    in

    the

    mind,

    and

    may represent perfectly,

    partially,

    or

    not

    at

    all 'those

    Archetypes,

    which the

    Mind

    supposes

    them taken

    from;

    which

    it intends them to stand

    for,

    and to

    which

    it

    refers them'

    (Essay,

    II,

    xxxi, 1,

    375).

    Throughout

    this

    chapter,

    he

    refers

    to

    idea-ectypes

    as

    'copies'

    and

    archetypes

    as 'models' or

    'originals,'

    and

    their

    intended

    relationship

    as one of

    'correspondence.'

    Now

    in

    the

    Dialogues,

    Ber-

    keley's

    use

    of the term

    'archetype'appears

    to be a

    concession to

    the

    Lockean-materialist

    ay

    of

    speaking,

    but not to its

    ontology.

    Forboth

    Locke

    and

    Berkeley,

    the

    epistemological

    relation

    signified by

    'arche-

    type'

    and

    'ectype'

    is the same

    (although

    the

    ontological

    status of the

    15

    PHK

    30, 33, 36;

    TD

    III,

    238

    (A, 200-1)

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Tue, 24 Jun 2014 12:58:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 PhilosophyBerkeley's Ideas

    14/16

    Berkeley's

    deas and the

    Primary/Secondary

    Distinction 59

    archetypesdiffers):the archetypeis the model or originalwhich the

    ectype

    (for

    both

    thinkers,

    an

    idea)

    ought

    to

    represent

    and

    resemble

    (and

    thus

    make

    known)

    but

    may,

    in

    fact,

    not.

    Finally,

    I

    should

    note

    that

    my

    reference here to God's ideas or

    per-

    ceptions

    as

    archetypal

    s neutral

    with

    respect

    to the issue of

    whether

    or not

    for

    Berkeley

    here

    is

    in

    God

    a

    set of

    archetypal

    divine

    ideas nu-

    merically

    distinct

    from our

    ideas,

    and of which our ideas are

    copies.

    There

    is

    much debate

    among Berkeley

    scholars on

    this

    problem,

    and

    the

    trouble

    to which

    a world of

    divine ideas would

    give

    rise

    are well-

    known.

    For

    example,

    it is claimed

    that it

    opens

    Berkeley

    up

    to

    exactly

    the same

    objections

    he raises

    against

    Locke's

    alleged representative

    theory

    of

    perception.16

    Note that

    I have been

    speaking

    alternately

    of

    God's

    ideasand God's

    perceptions,

    n

    order

    not to

    beg

    the

    question

    with

    regard

    o this issue.

    My argument

    can

    be described

    n terms of a differ-

    ence

    or

    correspondence

    between

    God's ideas

    and

    our

    ideas,

    or of a

    difference

    or

    correspondence

    etween

    God's

    perception

    of certain

    qual-

    ities

    and

    our

    perception

    of the

    (numerically)

    ame

    qualities.

    In

    order

    for

    the

    question

    of

    correspondence

    which

    I

    raise to be

    relevant,

    one

    only

    needs

    the

    claim,

    which

    Berkeley

    clearly supplies,

    that

    there is

    something archetypal n God's knowledge of things.

    Philonous: Do

    I not

    acknowledge

    a

    twofold

    state

    of

    things

    -the one

    ectypal

    or

    natural,

    the

    other

    archetypal

    and eternal?

    The former

    was

    created

    in

    time;

    the

    latter existed

    from

    everlasting

    in the

    mind

    of

    God.

    (TD

    III,

    254

    [A, 217])

    To

    be

    sure,

    my

    claim

    about

    Berkeley's

    reintroduction

    of a

    prima-

    ry/secondary

    distinction

    becomes

    particularly

    clear

    (and

    resembles

    Locke's

    distinction

    even

    more)

    if

    there is

    a

    realm

    of divine ideas which

    some

    of our

    ideas

    resemble

    and which others

    do not. But the distinc-

    tion

    is also

    reintroduced

    if

    it is a matter

    of some

    of our

    perceptions

    of

    qualities

    (or

    of

    ideas)

    resembling

    God's

    perception

    of

    them,

    while

    others

    do

    not.

    One could then call

    those

    qualities

    or

    ideas our

    percep-

    tion

    of

    which

    does resemble God's

    archetypal

    perception

    of

    them

    pri-

    maryqualities.

    Those

    qualities

    or ideas

    our

    perception

    of

    which does

    not

    resemble

    God's

    archetypalperception

    of them

    make

    up

    the class

    of

    secondary

    ualities.

    Thus,

    the

    epistemological

    distinction s the

    same

    as the

    one

    found

    in Locke:a distinction

    between those ideas or

    percep-

    16 See Gotterbarn, 251ff. Samuel Johnson, D.D., is the first to raise these questions

    regarding

    Berkeley's

    use

    of the

    archetype/ectype

    distinction;

    see his

    letter

    of

    Sep-

    tember

    10,

    1729

    (Works,

    vol.

    2,

    274-5).

    Genevieve

    Brykman

    argues

    that

    Berkeley

    is not

    willingly

    or

    deeply

    committed

    to a realm of

    archetypal

    divine

    ideas;

    see

    'La notion

    d'

    archetype

    selon

    Berkeley,'

    Recherches ur

    le XVIItme

    sikle

    7

    (1984)

    33-43. See

    also Mabbott.

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Tue, 24 Jun 2014 12:58:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 PhilosophyBerkeley's Ideas

    15/16

    60 Steven

    Nadler

    tions which succeed in resemblingand makingknown the nature of

    their

    (causal)

    originals,

    and

    those ideas or

    perceptions

    which fail to

    resemble

    and

    make known the nature of their

    (causal)

    originals.17

    Our

    perception

    of

    color,

    taste,

    odor,

    and

    sound tells us

    nothing

    about God's

    perception

    of

    the same

    qualities,

    even

    though

    God's

    (archetypal)per-

    ception

    of them

    plays

    a

    causal

    role

    in

    our

    (ectypal)perception

    of them.

    On the other

    hand,

    we have no reason

    to doubt that our

    perception

    of

    size,

    shape, solidity,

    and motion is

    a

    reliable source as to

    the

    way

    in

    which God knows these

    qualities.

    This is a

    problem

    for

    Berkeley

    because

    it

    is

    just

    this sort of

    epistemo-

    logical

    distinctionbetween kindsof ideas that he is

    hoping

    to do

    away

    with in

    the

    First

    Dialogue,

    as we saw. His

    aim

    there is

    to

    place

    all of

    our

    ideas,

    all

    sensible

    qualities,

    on the same

    epistemological

    and onto-

    logical ooting.

    If what

    I

    argue

    above is

    correct,

    here

    s at least one sense

    in which he has failed

    in

    this aim. It

    should

    be clear

    that this does not

    directly

    affect his

    arguments

    against

    materialism-

    both kinds of sensi-

    ble

    quality

    are still

    equally

    in

    the mind.

    And the

    ontological

    side of

    Locke's

    primary/secondary

    distinction,

    whereby

    primary

    qualities

    are

    those

    reallypossessed

    by

    external material

    objects,

    does

    not enter

    in

    with

    Berkeley.

    But the kind

    of epistemological qualityamong

    our

    ideas

    that

    Berkeley

    wants

    cannot,

    on his

    principles,

    be

    maintained. Once

    again, Berkeley gets

    into

    trouble

    in

    his

    attempt

    to deal

    with the rela-

    tion

    between the divine

    mind and

    the human

    mind

    in

    cognition, spe-

    cifically

    with

    the

    principle

    of the

    archetypal

    natureof God's

    knowledge.

    V Conclusion

    There

    may

    be a

    numberof

    ways

    in

    which

    Berkeley

    can

    escape

    the

    kind

    of problemattributedo him in thispaper.Eachof theseways demands

    a

    reconsideration,

    nce

    again,

    of certain

    problematic assages

    or

    aspects

    of

    Berkeley's

    philosophy

    with which

    Berkeley

    scholars

    have wrestled

    for decades.

    On the one

    hand,

    Berkeley

    could

    dispense

    with the

    pleasure/pain

    argument.

    This

    argument,

    which has never

    seemed

    very good

    in

    the

    first

    place, appears

    only

    in

    the

    Dialogues,

    ot

    in

    the

    Principles

    although

    it

    may

    seem

    suggested

    by

    some

    entries

    in

    the

    Philosophical

    ommen-

    taries).

    Moreover,

    Berkeley

    apparently

    believes

    that

    it

    needs to be

    17 For

    Berkeley,

    of

    course,

    ideas are

    not in

    themselves

    causally

    efficacious

    not even

    God's ideas.

    However,

    they

    do

    play

    an

    essential

    role in God's

    causing

    our

    ideas,

    since 'a

    thing

    which hath no ideas

    in

    itself cannot

    impart

    them to me/

    This content downloaded from 132.248.184.4 on Tue, 24 Jun 2014 12:58:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/12/2019 PhilosophyBerkeley's Ideas

    16/16

    Berkeley's

    deas and the

    Primary/Secondary

    Distinction

    61

    backedup by the relativity argument. This raises the question as to

    how much

    importance

    he

    pleasure/painargument

    bearsfor

    Berkeley's

    case.18

    The

    question

    is rendered

    particularly

    acute when we remem-

    ber that there

    is reason to think that

    Berkeley

    does not

    really

    believe

    that

    even

    the more common

    relativity

    argument

    (which,

    at

    least,

    has

    enjoyed

    some

    credibility

    among philosophers)

    establishes the

    mind-

    dependence

    of sensible

    qualities.19

    On

    the other

    hand,

    Berkeley

    could

    dispense

    with

    the arche-

    type/ectype

    model of

    the

    relationship

    between human

    and

    divine

    per-

    ception.

    He never seems

    wholly

    comfortable

    with

    such

    talk,

    as

    it

    always

    appears

    to be a concession of sorts. In his

    reply

    to

    Johnson

    quoted

    above,

    for

    example,

    he states

    in rather lukewarm terms that

    'I

    have

    no

    objectionagainst calling

    the ideas

    in the mind of

    God,

    archetypes

    of ours....'

    And the model does not

    appear

    at all

    in

    either the Princi-

    ples

    or

    the

    Philosophical

    ommentaries,

    eading

    one

    to wonder

    (as

    with

    the

    pleasure/pain

    argument)

    how

    integral

    t

    is

    to his

    system.

    But then

    how

    are we to

    describe

    the

    relationship

    between

    God's ideas or

    per-

    ceptions

    and our

    ideas or

    perceptions?

    This,

    ultimately,

    is one of the

    most

    interesting questions

    raised

    by Berkeley's

    theory

    of

    ideas,

    and

    one of the most problematic.20

    Received:

    January,

    1989

    18

    Brykman

    ('Pleasure

    and

    Pain Versus Ideas

    in

    Berkeley/

    129-30)

    argues

    that

    Philonous' use

    of the

    pleasure/pain

    argument

    should not be confused with

    a

    com-

    mitment

    to it on

    Berkeley's part.

    19 PHK 15:

    'It must be

    confessed

    this method of

    arguing

    does

    not so much

    prove

    that

    there is no extension

    or colour

    in an outward

    object,

    as that we do not know

    by

    sense

    which is the

    true extension

    or colour of the

    object'

    (47 [A, 66-7]).

    On

    the other

    hand,

    see

    TD

    1,

    189

    (A, 153),

    where Philonous calls the

    relativity argu-

    ment

    'a

    good

    argument'

    to the effect

    that

    secondary qualities

    are

    not

    in

    objects.

    For

    a discussion

    of

    Berkeley's

    change

    in

    attitude towards

    this

    argument,

    see Richard

    T.

    Lambert,

    'Berkeley's

    Use of the

    Relativity

    Argument,'

    IdealisticStudies 10

    (1980)

    107-21.

    20

    An

    early

    draft of this

    paper

    was read

    to the 1988

    meeting

    of the International

    Berkeley

    Society

    in

    Washington,

    D.C.

    I would like to thank the

    participants

    of

    the

    discussion there

    for their

    helpful

    comments and

    questions.

    I am

    particularly

    grateful

    to Kenneth

    Winkler,

    Douglas

    Jesseph,

    Robert

    McKim,

    and Richard Lam-

    bert

    for their extensive

    written comments.