Top Banner

of 43

Mwi Pref

Mar 03, 2016

Download

Documents

Ech Kon

Just a file
Welcome message from author
This document is posted to help you gain knowledge. Please leave a comment to let me know what you think about it! Share it to your friends and learn new things together.
Transcript
  • The many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics: psychologicalversus physical bases for the multiplicity of worlds.

    Howard Barnum

    Los Alamos National Laboratory, MS B256, Los Alamos, NM 87545

    Preface

    This hitherto unpublished 1990 paper presents my views on the many-worlds, or, as I prefer tocall it, following Everett, the relative state interpretation of quantum mechanics. It was rejectedby one journal in 1990, primarily on the (I think incorrect) grounds that it was too similar to theAlbert and Loewer many minds version. It has seen limited circulation since then. My viewsare quite similar to ones since put forth by Simon Saunders, and subscribed to by David Wallace,among others. I believe that, within the relative state interpretation, when an observer interactswith a system in a measurement process in such a way that the combination of the two evolvesinto a superposition of the observer seeing macroscopically different apparatus pointer readings(or other macroscopic states), the observers consciousness forks or splits, because only thosesubspaces of Hilbert space describing definite macroscopic measurement results satisfy psycho-logical/philosophical conditions for supporting a unified consciousness persisting through time.These conditions probably include things like the persistence of memory, and are probably closelylinked to the decoherence of certain subspace decompositions or approximate decompositions,corresponding to persisting macroscopic classical structures that can support such persistingmemoriesrelating the approach to the decoherence-based ones of, for example, Zurek, and Zeh,though this relation was not much stressed in the paper.

    I still agree with most of what is in the paper, with some notable exceptions. First, the dis-cussion of how one might have empirical evidence for nonprobabilistic indeterminacy seemsshaky: the evidence cited might just as well be taken to be evidence against independent trials,or against exchangeability. (This does not vitiate the point that relative state-ers may need toestablish not just that if there are probabilities they must be the Born ones, but that (on the relativestate interpretation) the indeterminism facing a quantum experimenter about what will be subjec-tively experienced as an outcome is correctly viewed as probabilistic at all.) Second, as I think the1990 referee pointed out, the improvement on Everetts derivation of probabilities (sec. 8.2),while it uses Gleasons theorem to avoid Everetts assumption that the probability of a wavefunc-tion component can depend only on its squared modulus, does not justify the noncontextualityassumption implicit in Gleasons theorem. There are also more minor exceptionsfor instance,I now see somewhat less value in de Broglie-Bohm-Bell nonlocal hidden variable theories thansuggested toward the end of this paper.

    Note that while I think it has much to teach us about quantum mechanics, I am not a committedbeliever in the relative state interpretation.

    The following pages were scanned from a hard copy, and the address in them is obsolete.

    Los Alamos, December 2002 and January 2004

    [email protected]

  • THE MANY-WORLDS INTERPRETATION OF QUANTUM MECHANICS:

    PSYCHOLOGICAL VERSUS PHYSICAL BASES FOR THE

    MULTIPLICITY OF "WORLDS".

    Howard N. Barnum 6401 Academy NE, #168 Albuquerque, NM 87 109 (505) 828-2567

  • THE MANY-WORLDS INTERPRETATION OF QUANTUM MECHANICS: PSYCHOLOGICAL VERSUS PHYSICAL BASES FOR THE

    MULTIPLICITY OF "WORLDS".

  • 1

    Abstract. A crucial distinction in discussions of the many-worlds interpretation of quantum

    mechanics (MWI) is that between versions of the interpretation positing a physical multiplicity

    of worlds, and those in which the multiplicity is merely psychological, and due to the splitting

    of consciousness upon interaction with amplified quantum superpositions. It is argued that

    Everetts original version of the MWI belongs to the latter class, and that most of the

    criticisms leveled against the MWI, in particular that it is illogical or incoherent, are not valid

    against such psychological multiplicity versions. Attempts to derive the quantum-mechanical

    probabilities from the many-worlds interpretation are reviewed, and Everetts initial derivation

    is extended to show that these are the unique possible probabilities. But there remains a

    challenge for proponents of the MWI: to show that their interpretation requires probabilities,

    rather than merely nonprobabilistic indeterminacy.

  • 1

    Introduction. While it has enjoyed some popularity, particularly among cosmologists, the

    relative state or many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics (henceforth MWI) appears

    to have fallen into disfavor among those concerned with the problem of interpreting quantum

    theory. D'Espagnat (1976) has criticized the theory in his seminal book, and Wheeler (1977),

    one of the best known proponents, has renounced it. Bell has said that "...the many-universes

    interpretation is a kind of heuristic, simplified theory, which people have done on the backs

    of envelopes but haven't really thought through. When you do try to think it through it is

    not coherent." (Bell, interviewed in Davies and Brown (1986)), and his view appears fairly

    widespread. Even among those who view the MWI as consistent, virtually no-one anymore

    believes with Everett that it shows that "the Schrodinger equation formalism yields its own

    interpretation." The major objective of this paper is to show that despite such criticism, the

    MWI is indeed a coherent and consistent interpretation of quantum mechanics arising naturally

    from the Schrodinger formalism, by developing a "psychological" version of the MWI in

    which the multiplicity of "worlds" appears as a multiplicity of perspectives on a single

    physical reality as seen from the points of view of different conscious subsystems' of this

    physical reality. This physical reality will be described by the usual quantum mechanical

    apparatus of a Hilbert-space statevector evolving over time according to the Schrodinger

    equation, with no extra physical structure introduced to account for "branching universes," and

    will be shown to give rise to the multiplicity of "worlds." It will also be shown to imply that

    there is only one acceptable probability distribution over them, which coincides with the

    quantum mechanical one.

    The term 'subsystem' is here meant in its general sense, not necessarily in its special quantum mechanical sense of one factor of a tensor product of Hilbert spaces.

    1

  • 2

    Sections 1 and 2 provide preliminaries, with section 1 reviewing the reasons for

    wanting an interpretation, such as the MWI, based solely on the Schrodinger equation and

    rejecting the projection postulate, and section 2 setting forth a variety of such interpretations,

    including different possible "many-worlds" interpretations, for comparison with the

    "psychological" version of the MWI which is the main subject of the paper. Section 3

    develops this psychological version in detail, and argues that it coincides with Everett's views,

    while sections 4 and 5 develop it further by comparing its approach to psychological unity through time and across subspaces of Hilbert space to that of other versions of the MWI--

    in the process setting to rest the fear, expressed by Bell (1981), that the MWI indulges in

    "solipsism of the present moment." Section 6 reviews criticisms of the MWI and attempts to

    answer them in the light of the psychological version. Sections 7 through 9 take up the

    question of the relationship between the MWI and the probabilities defined by the Born

    interpretation of the wavefunction. The key points in the discussion are section 8's argument

    that the Born probabilities constitute the only permissible probability distribution over different

    "worlds" corresponding to different observed experimental outcomes, and section 9's argument

    that we cannot yet rule out the possibility of nonprobabilistic indeterminacy. A variety of

    considerations bearing on the choice between the MWI and other "no-statevector-reduction"

    interpretations are noted as they arise throughout the paper, and some are touched on again

    in the concluding section. But the main thrust of the paper is that whatever such

    considerations may suggest about the choice between the MWI and other interpretations, the

    only problem with the consistency or coherence of the MWI lies in the need to arbitrarily

    postulate that the indeterminacy of which branch of the statevector one will end up in is of

    a probabilistic, rather than nonprobabilistic nature. The lack of an argument for this postulate

    based in the MWI itself, remains an obstacle to the claim that the MWI provides a consistent,

  • 3

    coherent interpretation of quantum mechanics which can generate the quantum mechanical

    predictions from the Schrodinger equation formalism without any extra structure or postulates.

    1. Reduction, Schrodinger Evolution, and the Many-Worlds Interpretation. The MWI can

    be viewed as an attempt to answer the question: why don't we observe superpositions of

    macroscopically different states? Schrodinger pointed out, with his cat example, that the

    Schrodinger equation implied that such states could be prepared. The "orthodox"

    interpretation's answer to the question of why we don't observe them was to postulate a mode

    of time evolution distinct from the continuous, unitary linear evolution according to the

    Schrodinger equation, that applied whenever a measurement was made on a system, throwing

    it from a superposition into one of the eigenvectors of the measured observable (with

    probabilities given by the squares of the amplitudes of the components of the statevector

    expanded in terms of these eigenvectors). This "collapse" or "reduction of the wavepacket"

    creates several difficulties. Particularly bothersome are: (1) there is no rigorous, physical

    specification of the conditions under which collapse, rather than Schrodinger evolution, occurs,

    and (2) gedankenexperiments in which one tests whether collapse has occurred by looking for

    the interference between the superposed alternatives which, on a view rejecting reduction,

    would persist after measurement, suggest such interference would be observed.2 In (2), I am

    thinking specifically of the reversal of the Stern-Gerlach experiment. (For classic discussions

    of this, see Wigner (1967) and Bohm (1951); for a modern treatment, see Englert, Scully, and

    Schwinger (1988) and even permutations thereof (1988), (1989)J While it has been argued

    Other difficulties are: (3) the orthodox view seems to require the postulation of a non-quantum-mechanically described outside system "observing" a quantum mechanical system, creating difficulties describing the whole universe in quantum- mechanical terms, and (4) it is probably not possible to describe the "reduction of a statevector" in a Lorentz-invariant way (see Aharonov and Albert (1980, 1981)).

    2

  • 4

    that thermodynamic considerations make even the partial reversal of macroscopic measurements

    impracticable (Daneri, Loinger, and Prosperi (1962); Peres (1980)) that does not resolve the

    issue of principle.

    What inclines us to accept reduction, rather than continual Schrodinger evolution, is that

    we dont directly observe macroscopic superpositions. One might make an acceptable theory

    by making physically precise the conditions under which reduction occurs, either by describing

    an instant where it occurs, or by slightly modifying the Schrijdinger equation so that it remains

    as it is for microscopic phenomena unobserved by macroscopic apparatus, but shades

    (continuously?) into statevector reduction as the system interacts with larger and larger apparati

    capable of correlating its state with more and more macroscopic phenomena. Either of these

    possibilities are in principle, experimentally distinguishable from pure Schrodinger evolution.

    But if we can find an interpretation of the quantum mechanical apparatus of state-vector and

    Schrodinger equation which implies that we wont observe macroscopic superpositions, then

    we wont have to assume reduction. Both Bohms (1952) theory (which adds a bit to the

    quantum mechanical apparatus, but doesnt alter its experimental implications) and the MWI

    are attempts to do this, in different ways.

    2. Different Versions of the MWI and Related Interpretations. Different proponents of

    the MWI present different versions, and are not always clear about what they have in mind.

    But clarity about ones interpretation and the assumptions behind it are essential to an adequate

    assessment of it. I will therefore outline several possible versions of the MWI, and some

    related interpretations which will help clarify the MWI by contrast and which I regard as its

    closest competitors. All of them attempt to solve the measurement problem by rejecting

    statevector reduction. Some of these versions were suggested by the incisive analysis of Bell

  • 5

    (1981) but I will concentrate on a distinction which Bell neglected, that between "physical"

    and "psychological" interpretations of the multiplicity of worlds.

    (A) The first version of the MWI is the simplest, and perhaps the closest to Everett's. The

    structure of the physical world corresponds just to the statevector in Hilbert space, evolving

    according to the Schrodinger equation. The multiplicity of "worlds" is really a multiplicity

    of consciousnesses, not a multiplicity of physical systems, and the "branching" that occurs is

    also an essentially psychological process that occurs when a consciousness observes a

    superposed system: the conscious system goes into superposition, as the Schrodinger equation

    implies, but thereby splits into several consciousnesses. There is no multiplication of physical

    worlds, only a complexification of the structure of the statevector of the universe, which has

    differentiated so as to support, indeed given the psychological conditions for the unity of

    consciousness to require, several consciousnesses where before there was only one. This

    interpretation will be my primary focus, and I will expound it at length below. (It might be

    clearer to call this the Relative State Interpretation, reserving the term 'Many-Worlds' for

    physical-multiplicity interpretations like B and C below; I refer to both types of interpretations

    as versions of the MWI, since this has become the established practice.)

    (B) Realism about the statevector as above, plus the statement that there is a physical

    multiplicity of worlds. The square modulus of the projection of the statevector on an

    eigenvector of an observable Z is stipulated to give us the proportion (or relative measure) of

    worlds in which a measurement of that observable yields the corresponding eigenvalue. (The

    usual probability assertions of quantum mechanics may then be derived from the assumption

  • 6

    that we are equally likely to be in any one of the existing worlds). Deutsch (interviewed in

    Davies and Brown (1986)) may have in mind something of this sort.

    (C) Interpretation B, with the stipulation that the worlds that exist correspond to position

    eigenvectors; this is essentially Bell's (198 1) version of Everett's (1957a,b) MWI. This gets

    rid of the difficulty with (B), that it introduces "observation" into the fundamental physics

    again in the choice of an observable whose eigenvectors determine the nature of the physically

    different worlds.

    (D) Interpretation (B), plus a linking of particular worlds at one time with worlds at other

    times, into physical trajectories. Just how to select which worlds get linked into trajectories

    is a problem seemingly susceptible to many solutions; one desirable criterion might be an

    "anti-solipsism" requirement: that what is in our memory of "events at time t-1" at time t,

    correspond to what happened in this branch at time t-1. (It would seem there is no way we

    could observationally distinguish theories which violate this requirement from those that don't,

    however.) A great variety of specifications of trajectories may be possible; a particularly

    interesting specification gives rise to trajectories like those in the de Broglie-Bohm pilot wave

    model.

    (E) B, but with the various worlds being merely possible worlds, and the real world being

    chosen with a distribution llv(z)I12 out of the class of possible worlds, where z ranges over

    the eigenvalues of the relevant observable Z. This is another of Bell's suggestions, though

    it is of course no longer a many-worlds interpretation.

  • 7

    (F) Like (E), but at each moment the actual world is chosen out of the comparison class of

    possible worlds with distribution lIw(x) 112, where x ranges over the eigenvalues of position.

    (G) Like (D), but there is a single actual trajectory. For a particular choice of form for the

    trajectories, interpretation G becomes the de Broglie-Bohm pilot wave theory of Bohm (1952).

    E,F, and G are of course not many-worlds theories (I would call them all hidden-

    variable theories); A through D are.

    Do any of these interpretations correspond to the classic expositions of the MWI by

    Everett, DeWitt and others (De Witt, and Graham 1973)? Despite formalized expositions like

    Everett's "relative state" formulation, the MWI is commonly thought to be rather unclear. The

    root of the unclarity is Everett's claim that the MWI is the natural interpretation of the

    quantum apparatus of statevector and Schrodinger equation, to which it adds nothing. This

    has seemed to conflict with talk of "branching universes" which appear to be an added

    structure imposed on the evolving statevector, since after all components of statevectors are

    not linked through time in the quantum formalism in any kind of tree structure. Moreover,

    if the additional structure really is a branching tree, the problem of reduction of the

    wavepacket has not really been avoided, but merely reformulated: the splitting of a universe

    appears to be basically the same process as reduction, with all the same problems as to when,

    precisely, it occurs. These difficulties stem from a fundamental ambivalence among critics and

    some proponents of the MWI about whether the "many worlds" reflect a physical multiplicity

    of universes, or simply a division of consciousnesses within one physical system. I will

    argue that Everett explicitly endorsed the latter view.

  • 8

    3. Version (A) of the MWI: Psychological Multiplicity Without Physical Multiplicity.

    3.1 Psychophysical parallelism. The MWI as presented by Everett is an attempt to interpret

    the statevector and Schrodinger equation without any extra mathematical formalism (and in

    particular, without the either the projection postulate or a physical multiplicity of worlds). I

    read Everett as endorsing version (A) of the MWI. On this reading there is one universe,

    represented by a statevector, which may however be a superposition of infinitely many

    macroscopically or microscopically different states. Evolution of this state vector is always

    according to the Schrodinger equation. To the question "Why don't we observe macroscopic

    superpositions like Schrodinger's cat?" a simple reply may be given. One system measures

    (observes, if it is conscious) another when its state becomes correlated with the other's through

    Schrodinger evolution. That is, letting y' represent the apparatus (or observer) state and $

    represent the observed system state, when the state of the total system A + S evolves from ~ o @ ( ~ l ~ ' , ) to ~,(tfI@u/s,). (v", represents the initial, nonregistering state of the apparatus, while the VI are distinct states which may be thought of as pointer positions (or states in which the observer sees a definite pointer position) or the like.) In attempting to observe a

    macroscopic superposition like Schrodinger's cat, my state would become correlated with the

    cat's, and I would go into a superposition of states "me seeing a dead cat" and "me seeing

    a live cat." Such a macroscopic superposition does not possess the necessary unity to be a

    "state of consciousness" (using 'state' in a non-QM sense here). Therefore what happens is

    my consciousness splits into two consciousnesses, for the components "me seeing a dead cat"

    and "me seeing a live cat," which are both elements of physical reality, do possess the unity

    required to be states of consciousness. And these components (and their subsequent histories,

    until their next encounters with amplified quantum phenomena) moreover possess the necessary

    continuity (of memory-contents, e.g.) with earlier and later states to form the history of a

  • 9

    consciousness persisting through time-- with the one bizarre aspect that when I observe an

    amplified quantum superposition (when I interact with it via a Hamiltonian which correlates

    components of my state to components of the superposition) my consciousness splits or forks

    into many branches. (Theoretically, though as a practical matter it would be impossible,

    someone could perform on me the analog of the reversal of the Stern-Gerlach experiment, and

    the branches could join again, but in such a process the results of measurement would be

    erased from my memory(s)--along, perhaps, with everything else that happened between the

    splitting and rejoining.) These branches are branches of my consciousness, and the branching

    is not a physical process, but one that occurs because of the conditions for personal identity,

    or identity of consciousness, which are more matters of philosophy or psychology than physics.

    It may seem strange to invoke psychological or philosophical criteria in explaining the

    results of physical processes, but it is not really. Any physical theory needs some crude

    account of how the theory links up with our observations, in order to be of interest to US

    (though of course the theory's meaning is not exhausted by statements about observations).

    These include crude theories about our eyes, bodies, sense-organs, and how they perceive what

    they do. Advocates of the MWI could argue that in order to get theory properly related to

    observation (part of interpreting the theory or mathematical formalism) in quantum mechanics,

    we simply need a slightly more sophisticated "stylized psychology" which takes into account

    conditions for the unity of conscious experience. This does not mix psychology into physical

    theory, so that we need psychological concepts like mind in the statement of the basic physical

    theory; we simply need to know a bit about the way psychological states supewene on

    physical states in order to get the observational implications of the basic physical theory

    (which however contains no psychological concepts) right. By contrast, it might be argued

  • 10

    that some proponents of versions of the more "orthodox" interpretation of QM, with the

    reduction postulate, do invoke psychological concepts at the level of basic physical theory:

    for example Wigner (1967, 1976), who suggests (in part because of his acceptance of the

    reverse S tern-Gerlach argument against early reduction of the statevector) that reduction must

    not be a purely physical process, but must rather be an effect of nonphysical mind on matter.

    This sort of thing is worrisome in physical theory (particularly as we have no precise way of

    deciding when we are in the presence of a "mind" or Cartesian "soul"), but the MWI is not

    guilty of it.

    3.2 Everett as a Subscriber to Version (A)

    Everett spends a lot of time on formalized relative state theory, and relatively little on

    the assumptions about psychophysical parallelism which I have argued are crucial to the

    success of the MWI. It is these assumptions which give certain "relative states" (states

    relative to particular states of conscious observers) their interest as potential "worlds" from the

    point of view of particular consciousnesses. Among supporters of the MWI, Zeh is most

    explicit about this: "The different components represent two completely decoupled worlds.. .. As the "other" component cannot be observed any more, it serves only to save the consistency

    of quantum theory .... This interpretation, corresponding to a "localization of consciousness" not only in space and time, but also in certain Hilbert-space components, has been suggested

    by Everett ..." (Zeh 1970) Everett himself, while stressing the importance of psychophysical parallelism and of representing the observer as a physical system within the theory, does not

    explicitly discuss the role of conditions for the unity of consciousness. There are strong hints

    that the view sketched above is implicit in his thought, however:

  • 11

    We thus arrive at the following picture: Throughout all of a sequence of observation processes there is only one physical system representing the observer, yet there is no single unique state of the observer (which follows from the representations of interacting systems). Nevertheless, there is a representation in terms of a superposition, each element of which contains a definite observer state and a corresponding system state. Thus with each succeeding observation (or interaction), the observer state "branches" into a number of different states. Each branch represents a different outcome of the measurement and the corresponding eigenstate for the object-system state. All branches exist simultaneously in the superposition after any given sequence of observations. (Everett 1957a)

    In a footnote, he adds "This total lack of effect of one branch on another also implies

    that no observer will ever be aware of any "splitting" process.

    This passage is somewhat ambiguous, and I suspect different interpretations of it and

    passages like it (Everett 1957b, p. 62n.) have given rise to many different suppositions about

    what Everett's MWI really is. One thing that suggests the splitting is a psychological splitting

    of consciousness, rather than some sort of physical splitting of one world into many, is that

    Everett clearly says that "the observer state "branches"" rather than, say, "the universe

    "branches"." That Everett always puts the terms 'split' and 'branch' in quotes suggests the

    same thing. Also, Everett states that throughout the process, there is only one physical system

    representing the observer.

    4. Psychological Unity Through Time in Various Versions of the MWI. Bell's

    strongest objection to the MWI is that he believes it implies a "solipsism of the present

    moment," in that the MWI shows that for an observer in given branch of the statevector at

    a given time, all of his memory-contents will be (statistically speaking) consistent with the

    usual quantum-mechanical predictions, but, Bell believes, there is no linking up of these time-

    slices of consciousnesses into histories: no guarantee that the "I" that has certain experiment-

    results recorded in its memory actually had those experiences (Bell 1981). Although Everett's

  • 12

    scheme implies the existence of an "I" at a previous time who had those experiences, Bell

    thinks there is no physical identification of this "I" with the current "I" who remembers the

    experiences. I think this problem stems from a misunderstanding of the relative importance

    of physics and psychology/philosophy in the MWI. The primary aim of the MWI was

    precisely to show that an interpretation of QM observationally indistinguishable from the

    orthodox one could be constructed by adding to the Schrodinger equation formalism only some

    assumptions about psychological or philosophical criteria for identity of consciousness. A

    minimal way of attempting this gives rise to Bell's time-slices. But if we have qualms about

    the metaphysical sparseness of the world thus construed, we may add additional suppositions

    about criteria for identity of consciousness through time, and recover a world of persisting

    (though branching) individual consciousnesses whose current memory-contents are generally

    reliable indicators of past experiences. (Moreover, we can get this unification through time

    whether we have a type (A), (B), or ( C ) version of the MWI: that is, whether one supposes

    the multiplicity of worlds at any given time is physical or psychological.) Thus if we want

    to require (1) some degree of physical causal connectedness and (2) some degree of

    consistency of content, such that memories generally correspond to earlier experiences, as

    conditions for identity of consciousness through time, we can link up the "right" components

    of the statevector into consciousnesses with branching histories, which are not solipsistic in

    the way Bell was worried about. Each component of the universal statevector at time t is

    causally linked to components at later times (requirement l), and some of these later

    components share enough conscious content (requirement 2) that they may be linked into a

    conscious history. It is a mistake to suppose that physics should be expected to supply the

    extra structure which ensures these trajectories link up. (Though if the physics does add

  • 13

    trajectories, as in (D), we will want them to be the right ones for psychological continuity.)

    At one point Bell likens Bohm's theory to the MWI plus trajectories (and of course,

    the singling out of one trajectory as the physically real one). He sees a major advantage for

    Bohm's theory in the specification, in the physics, of a trajectory--a single history for the

    world, which provides a basis for rejecting solipsism. Presumably the idea is that now I know

    I am identical with the previous person whom physics says existed and had experiences I now

    remember having, because there aren't all these other "versions of me" in other universes who

    I might worry that I'm really, metaphysically continuous with rather than the one whose

    experiences I remember. But this problem isn't unique to the MWI (There are other people

    even in a single branch of this universe and how, after all, do I know I wasn't really,

    metaphysically one of them a few seconds ago, instead of the person whose experiences I

    remember? How do I know I was really, metaphysically ANYBODY a few seconds ago, even

    if there are no other "versions of me in other branches of the universe" to worry about?). I

    think Bell is here expecting physics to solve puzzles which it need not solve. Finally, it is

    important that we can introduce psychological "trajectories" in version (A), since as I will

    show in Section 8, this is useful in the derivation of the correct probabilities from version (A),

    a crucial part of any argument for the observational indistinguishability of version (A) from

    standard quantum mechanics.

    5. Psychological Unity and Multiplicity Across Subspaces of Hilbert Space in Various

    Versions of the MWI. The considerations of the previous sections suggest two ways of

    viewing the measurement process, corresponding to different views of the psychophysical

    relationship between brains in different Hilbert-space components and consciousnesses. In one,

  • 14

    there is a single consciousness before the interaction, splitting into several afterwards. In the

    other, there are the same number of consciousnesses before and after the interaction: one for

    each component of the Hilbert space decomposition in terms of eigenvectors of the relevant

    observable. Everett appears to plump for the former, and it indeed version (A) of the MWI

    appears to provide no basis for a psychological multiplicity of consciousnesses before

    measurement. In the case of type (B) or (C) theories, which have physical mutiplicity but no

    trajectories, one might imagine either that consciousness unifies across physically distinct

    worlds in which its state is identical, or that it remains numerically distinct.

    6. Critics of the MWI.

    6.1 Bell. Bell's views on Everett, as I have suggested above, provide an example of how an

    excessively physical interpretation of Everett's statements about "branching" and "multiple

    worlds" can lead to trouble. Bell's view of Everett's theory is summarized in the statement

    that:

    The Everett (?) theory of this section will simply be the pilot-wave theory without trajectories. Thus instantaneous classical configurations x are supposed to exist, and to be distributed in the comparison class of possible worlds with probability lh@ll. But no pairing of configurations at different times, as would be effected by the existence of trajectories, is supposed. (Bell 198 1)

    Bell then makes a series of points, labelled (A) through (D), about how this Everett (?)

    theory seems to differ from what Everett (and/or DeWitt) actually say. I think it is fair to

    say that Bell supposes a coherent version of the Everett theory must differ from what Everett

    and DeWitt seem to 'be saying on these four points. But in my view, Bell misinterprets

    Everett, at least, on these points, precisely because he takes his statements too physically.

    Bell's point (A) is that it is unnecessary to multiply worlds. Bell begins by making

    what I have taken to be the main point of the MWI, that "The psychophysical parallelism

  • 15

    is supposed such that our representatives in a given "branch" universe are aware only of what

    is going on in that branch." But he goes on: "Now it seems to me that this multiplication

    of universes is extravagant, and serves no real purpose in the theory, and can simply be

    dropped without repercussions. So I see no reason to insist on this particular difference

    between the Everett theory and the pilot-wave theory-- where, although the wave is never

    reduced, only one set of values of the variables x is realized at any instant." Now this is

    an interesting point--that one could throw out all worlds but one, and if it were true that one

    would lose nothing essential, one might want to do it. Everett and DeWitt believe that one

    does lose something; the existence of all branches is essential to the Everett-DeWitt-Graham

    demonstrations, discussed by Bell under (C), that one can recover the Born statistical

    interpretation from the formalism itself. Since Bell thinks this demonstration is unsuccessful,

    I assume he therefore isn't worried about losing this. From his point of view, both the

    hidden variables interpretations and the MWI have to make an additional assumption

    introducing the correct probability measure. Bell's Everett(?) (and Bohm) do indeed add

    such an assumption about the selection of the actual world from an ensemble of possible

    worlds with probability measure on that ensemble given by Ilv211. Moreover for Bell, who sees both the MWI and de Broglie-Bohm as introducing a structure of "worlds" or

    trajectories in addition to the statevector, we can remove the other worlds from this extra

    structure without losing the possibilities of interference present in the statevector; for Everett,

    the statevector is all there is, and we cannot get rid of these other worlds without destroying

    these interference possibilities.

    Another problem is discussed by Bell under (B):

    it could be said that the classical variables x do not appear in Everett and DeWitt. However it is taken for granted there that meaningful reference can be made to experiments having yielded one result rather than another. SO instrument readings, or the numbers on computer output, and things like that,

  • 16

    are the classical variables of the theory. We have argued already against the appearance of such vague quantities at a fundamental level ..... It was for this reason that the hypothesis was made of fundamental variables x, from which instrument readings and so on can be construct ed.... I suspect Everett and DeWitt wrote as if instrument readings were fundamental only in order to be intelligible to specialists in quantum measurement theory. (Bell 198 1).

    This is closely related to another problem: that to specify a probability distribution

    over "worlds" we must choose a preferred operator, so that the components of the statevector

    along its eigenvectors can be taken as the set of "points" on which the measure is defined.

    But for Everett, the different "worlds" are not physically defined "configurations" (Bell's

    Everett(?)) or "trajectories" (de Broglie-Bohm), but are worlds-for-consciousnesses. I stress

    here the fact of consciousness, not the macroscopic nature of instruments. Macroscopic

    superpositions exist; we just cannot, in the nature of things, perceive them. Instrument

    readings are important because they are observed by consciousnesses. Thus while the

    division into worlds is indeed dependent on vague, nonphysical concepts like consciousness,

    these concepts are not imported into the basic physics or the mathematical formalism,

    because the grouping of Hilbert-space components into distinct worlds is not a phenomenon

    at that level (though it could be said to have a basis at that level in the possibility of

    superposition inherent in the QM formalism). Therefore, there is no need in the basic

    physical formalism to choose a preferred observable whose eigenvectors determine the nature

    of the various "worlds."

    (C) is the contention that Everett/de Witt do not succeed in deriving the desired

    probability measure over final configurations from the QM formalism. "Everett has to attach

    weights to the different branches of his multiple universe, and in the same way [as Bohm]

    does so in proportion to the norms of the relevant parts of the wave function. Everett and

    De Witt seem to regard this choice as inevitable. I am unable to see why, although of

    course it is a perfectly reasonable choice with several nice properties." (Bell 1981). This

  • 17

    point is very important, since if we can't get the right probabilities straight from the physical

    formalism then we will have to add something to it, which will probably require mention of

    a particular decomposition of the statevector into worlds and explicit specification of a

    measure over those worlds, thus requiring the extra structure of Bohm and Bell's "classical

    configuration variables x." The validity of Bell's contention, and of various attempted

    derivations of the probability measure by MWI proponents, are considered at length in

    sections 7-9 below.

    (D) is the question of trajectories and branching. I have already indicated that

    branching is not a process represented in the fundamental physics, and Bell is mistaken to

    attribute to Everett the view that it is represented there. Bell also mentions "the [lack of]

    association of a particular present with a particular past". I have already discussed this as

    well: one may suppose such association occurs in the unification of consciousness, rather

    than by explicitly putting trajectories in terms of "configuration variables" into the physics.

    6.2 Wheeler, Wigner, and d'Espagnat. Aside from Bell's, the most influential criticisms

    of the MWI have probably been those of Wheeler, Wigner, and d'Espagnat. The portions

    of their criticisms which are relevant to version (A) of the MWI are quite similar. They

    object to the existence of branches of the statevector in which "we" have experiences

    different from those we actually have. Thus Wheeler:

    ...g reat difficulties would seem to arise in giving any well defined meaning to the term 'state of memory of the observer'. Thus as Bohr always emphasized, any attempt to "push the analysis of the mechanism of living organisms [Le. the consciousness as ultimate observing device] as far as that of atomic phenomena ... would doubtless kill [the] animal" [and thus wipe out that very consciousness]. (Wheeler 1977. Brackets Wheeler's).

    He then cites Wigner and d'Espagnat. Now it is likely that an attempt to view the

    consciousness as part of the quantum-system, and, say, to try to reverse a conscious Stern-

  • 18

    Gerlach measurement would, even theoretically within the MWI, wipe out that observer's

    memory of what went on between the measurement and its reversal (though not necessarily

    the observer-- if one assumes enough finesse to reverse a conscious Stern-Gerlach

    measurement, one might as well assume enough finesse to keep the observer alive in the

    process). But this does not invalidate the theory. And if one arranged to have it done on

    oneself, one might well know after reversal, that one had been in a superposition (statevector

    reduction had not occurred), because of the memory gap. Whereas if reduction had occurred,

    one would be unable to reverse the measurement and might remain conscious of the

    measurement result.

    Wigner shows some awareness of the psychological basis of the MWI, as he argues:

    The epistemology under discussion postulates that I feel to be in only one of the immensely many states in the linear combination of which I actually am. This means, however, that the other states, and hence the total state vector of the world, are meaningless.

    One could postulate, in a similar vein, that the world is homogeneous and isotropic and it is only I who sees differences between different locations and different directions--the real state vector is invariant under all Poincare transformations. Such ideas appear to me--perhaps wrongly--to be detached from reality. (Wigner 1973).

    There is an equivocation on 'I' in the first sentence, between 'I' as whichever consciousness

    I happen to wind up with after measurement, and 'I' as the physical subsystem which gets

    thrown into superposition after measurement. There is no ground for calling the other states

    meaningless except an extreme positivism in which only measurement results are real.

    There are many reasons to reject such a positivism and try to find a realistic interpretation

    of physical theory, and the justification for introducing the "meaningless" other branches into

    the MWI is that they enable a realistic (and non-hidden-variables) interpretation of QM.

    Superpositions are necessary in order to explain interference phenomena; in this regard they

    are unlike the hypothetical supposition of homogeneity and isotropy of the real statevector

  • 19

    to which Wigner compares them in the last paragraph: the latter doesn't help explain

    anything.

    D'Espagnat (1976, Chapter 23) deals with two versions of the MWI, his "solution (a)"

    and "solution (b)." Solution (a) roughly corresponds to a physical multiplicity view, my (B)

    or (C), to which d'Espagnat objects because of the need to choose a preferred observable.

    Solution (b) is one in which "the number of instruments and the number of systems is

    always conserved." It would therefore appear to correspond to my version (A), but

    d'Espagnat does not appear to recognize the need for a psychological interpretation of the

    split.

    Thus we are led to the conclusion that, if the impressions of the observers are just physical properties of these systems--and as such, are described by the state vectors--then these impressions must be blurred in the kind of experiments studied here. This conclusion is, however, in obvious contradiction with our immediate experience, since under the conditions of these experiments every one of us knows with certainty that he always has the definite impression of seeing, or not seeing, a signal. (d'Espagnat 1976, p. 27 3)

    The problem with d'Espagnat's conclusion (and the argument that leads to it) is the

    assumption that there is a single observer consciousness associated with a single physical

    observer-system and represented in the statevector (the plural in the first sentence refers to

    a hypothetical ensemble of identical universes (d'Espagnat likes to couch his quantum theory

    in terms of ensembles), not to the branches of a statevector within a universe). We cannot

    expect the statevector to be in a "one-to-one correspondence'' with my single impression;

    it corresponds to a multiplicity of impressions, which is not the blurred impression of a

    single consciousness, but the distinct impressions of the multiplicity of consciousnesses which

    my version (A) says must exist after measurement. To expect the objective description of

    physical reality to contain the "fact" that I had this particular impression is like expecting

    it to explain why my consciousness is that of being Howard Bamum, and not of being

  • 20

    Bernard d'Espagnat: in both cases the explanation is roughly that various subsystems of

    physical reality with a certain structure exist, some sort of crude psychology tells us that

    each subsystem with such a structure has consciousness, and given that I am going to be a

    consciousness, I have to be one of them and can't be more than one at once, but physics

    has nothing to say about which one3, nor should we expect it to.

    6.3. Thus it would appear that versions (A), (C) or (D) of the MWI remain competitors for

    the de Broglie-Bohm hidden variables theory (a variant of G ) , as do hidden variable

    interpretation (F) and other variants of (G). There might seem little to go on in making the

    choice except for metaphysical prejudice (e.g. against unnecessary multiplication of

    consciousnesses, or against "hidden" variables). But there is also the fact that version (A)

    does not have to choose a preferred set of configuration variables-- indeed, does not have

    to add anything to the Schrodinger equation formalism. This may be viewed as an

    advantage or not, depending on whether one agrees with Bell (1982) that "in physics the

    only observations we must consider are position observations ... It is a great merit of the de Broglie-Bohm picture to force us to consider this fact. If you make axioms, rather than

    definitions and theorems, about the "measurement" of anything else, then you commit

    redundancy and risk inconsistency." Speculating, one might even relate this to the possibility

    (Wigner 1976) that only a few of the mathematically possible Hermitian operators correspond

    to physically measurable quantities like position and momentum. If this is so, the de

    Broglie-Bohm measurement theory, and perhaps version (C) of the MWI as well, might

    explain it, while the standard theory and version (A) of the MWI do not. (Though Bohr's

    'hecessity for using classical variables to describe measurement results" could be considered

    3 B ~ t physics combined with the "stylized psychology" of the MWI may enable us to say something about the probabilities of being various consciousnesses, when your current one splits due to measurement. See Section 8.

  • 21

    a recognition of it). In addition, there is the fact that we have not, as yet, introduced

    probabilities into version (A) of the MWI. If they can be derived from this version which

    does not explicitly mention them, this might be considered an advantage. If they cannot be

    so derived, we must investigate whether they can be coherently introduced by stipulation (as

    they are in the physical multiplicity versions of the MWI). The latter question will be

    investigated in section 7, the former in section 8.

    7. The Status Of Probabilities in Version (A) of the MWI. Let's put aside until the next

    section Everett and DeWitt's contention that the statistical interpretation emerges naturally

    from the formalism, and consider whether we may simply introduce the square-amplitude

    measure as a matter of stipulation. Does it make sense to do so? What does it mean to

    assign probabilities to components of the statevector? If one wants to say it has to do with

    relative frequencies, fine-- but relative frequencies of what?

    Consider several ways probabilities could be included in a physical theory. (1) Under

    certain conditions (unambiguously specified in the theory, one hopes) the theory does not

    predict determinate consequences, but makes a statistical prediction. Le., the equations of

    motion may contain transition probabilities. For example, particles make "random jumps."

    (2) Equations of motion are deterministic, but the initial conditions are probabilistic. This

    could be described by saying the actual physical world is conceived of as chosen from a

    (possibly hypothetical) ensemble of possible worlds, with probabilities given by a certain

    measure. This could be conceived of as (2a)a physically real random process occurring at

    the "beginning of the world" in which initial conditions are "chosen." Or it could perhaps

    be due to (2b)our ignorance of initial conditions. In the latter case one wonders if it is

    proper to call the probabilities part of a genuine physical theory. Perhaps it is, if the

  • 22

    physics of the situation explains why we can't know the values and why we should have the

    subjective probabilities we do. Statistical mechanics is one case in point; Bohm (1953) has

    argued that his hidden variable theory is another.

    The MWI does not fit neatly into any of the above categories. With the MWI, there

    are determinate initial conditions (initial statevector) and a deterministic law of evolution, so

    the probabilities must arise from ignorance. But this is not ignorance of an objective

    physical fact, rather it is ignorance as to which branch of the statevector we are in or will

    go into--ignorance of a "perspectival fact". In Everett's version of the MWI (my version (A))

    the branches "split", rather than being distinct and merely becoming differentiated (section

    5) , so that it is not a mere matter of finding out which branch one is in, but a matter of

    finding out which one of the branches one will end up in after the split. There is a genuine

    stochastic event going on; it is, of course, the splitting of one mind into two, as viewed

    from the perspective of one of the resulting conscious histories. The probabilities are

    probabilities that "my" consciousness will go with one branch versus the other; and their

    introduction can be empirically justified by the fact that if we suppose these probabilities

    obtained in previous, similar, situations where Schrodinger evolution predicts a split (quantum

    superpositions amplified to affect conscious minds), we get relative frequencies very close

    to the ones we've actually observed (at least with very high probability, in the limit as the

    number of observations gets large, which is all any interpretation of quantum mechanics can

    promise). These probabilities may be thought of as "objective" as opposed to

    "epistemological" (or as they are sometimes termed, "subjective") probabilities. But they are

    not the probabilities of objective physical events, but rather of outcomes of a sort of

    subjective, psychological, perspectival event, the splitting of consciousness.

  • If the splitting

    initially similar worlds

    23

    of consciousness were simply a matter of physically distinct but

    becoming differentiated, and the probability meant something like the

    relative numbers of various types of these worlds, the physical basis of the probabilities

    would be relatively clear. In these interpretations, the worlds in the "comparison set of

    possible worlds" differ physically, and the probabilities specify a distribution over these

    different physical possibilities. But in version (A), the probabilities may seem ad hoc,

    necessary for agreement with experiment but a nebulous, hard-to-interpret element in a theory

    which is, after all, attempting to remedy orthodox quantum mechanics' unclear and/or

    idealistic view of the world by providing a clear and precise picture of reality.

    The difficulty is not per se that the probabilities are probabilities of perspectival

    events rather than probabilities describing events occurring in the world as seen from no

    particular point of view. It is that we need a coherent picture of how these probabilities of

    perspectival events (e.g. the probability that "my" consciousness will be the one associated

    with the "pointer-indicating-z-spin up" component of the measuring apparatus) are grounded

    in objective physical reality. After all, for other "perspectival facts," one can generally come

    up with a reasonable explanation of why, given the objective physical situation, things

    viewed from here had to look as they did. One can of course derive the probabilities from

    a coherent mathematical structure. But we need to justify the identification of these numbers

    (norms of Hilbert-space components) with probabilities of perspectival events. Since the

    basic formalism is supposed to be nonprobabilistic, this interpretation of Hilbert-space norms

    as probabilities really should arise from the basic structure and the nature of the perspectives

    we can have on it (the notion of splitting consciousnesses), rather than simply being

    stipulated. Thus, Everett, de Witt, and Graham's claims to have derived the probabilities

    from the Schrodinger equation formalism become crucial.

  • 24

    8. Deriving the Probabilities From the MWI.

    8.1 Everett's derivation. In deriving the square amplitude measure from the formalism

    Everett's main assumption (1957a,b) is the additivity assumption that if ty = Caityi is the component of the wavefunction along the vector w, its measure rn(ty) should equal the sum of the measures associated with each of the components in its expansion, X,m(qvi). This

    additivity requirement is justified by a "conservation of probability" argument: we want the

    probability of being in the "trunk" of a particular tree to equal the sum of the probabilities

    of winding up on each of its branches. But this argument appeals to trajectories, which are

    not part of the physical formalism of version (A). One might object therefore that it should

    be applied to versions of the MWI of type (E) rather than type (A). To this I respond that

    the "trajectories" are to be interpreted as the psychological trajectories discussed in section

    4 above. But what grounds do we have to require the additivity property of these trajectories? Well, we may ask if the apparatus that tells us which branches there are

    (statevector, Schrodinger equation, and psychological conditions for unity of consciousness)

    tells us anything about these probabilities. Let a "memory-sequence" a = &a2, ..., an) be a sequence of observed outcomes of n experiments Note that the sum of probabilities, given

    that I am in the branch corresponding to a memory-sequence a, of going into branches where

    my memory-sequence is a extended by one of the an+,,k where k indexes the possible

    outcomes of the (n+l)th experiment, which is about to be performed, is one. This is a fact

    about the way consciousness unifies through time: physical subsystems (in a nontechnical

    sense) in which one was about to perform a certain experiment unify with later subsystems

    in which that experiment is complete with a certain outcome, to create a consciousness with

    a history (or in this case, a consciousness branching into several consciousnesses with

  • 25

    histories). If your consciousness starts out in one such system which then becomes

    correlated with an amplified quantum phenomenon, you can be sure its history will be

    continued on one of the resulting branches. The reasoning is essentially the same as that

    which justifies assuming that the continued existence of a physical body and brain with the

    right relations to ones body and brain at earlier times ensures ones continued conscious

    existence. And the conclusion is just Everetts additivity assumption.

    But Everetts derivation of a measure also makes the seemingly ad hoc assumption

    that the measure rn of a given component must be a function of its norm ai. (He argues

    that it must be a function of its modulus in fact, since we may simultaneously multiply all

    weights by an arbitrary modulus-one complex phase factor without changing the physical

    system represented). But, we might ask, why not let m be a function from Rk to R, instead of R to R, a function of all the weights in a decomposition, or perhaps even a function of both weights and eigenvectors?

    8.2 An improvement on Everetts derivation. To deal with this objection we may keep

    the additivity assumption and replace the remainder of Everetts derivation with an appeal

    to Gleasons theorem (Gleason 1957). This theorem states that for each additive measure

    on the closed subspaces of a Hilbert space H, there is a density operator of the usual

    quantum-mechanical sort, from which the probability measure can be derived in the usual

    way). Gleasons theorem does not in itself show that we must assign to a system described

    by a statevector w the probabilities described by the corresponding density operator I w)(w I (Le. the square amplitudes of the expansion of that statevector in terms eigenvectors of the

    measured operator). So that if we had a one-to-one mapping R from statevectors to density

    operators, we might generate a different probability measure, by assigning to a system with

    statevector w the probabilities corresponding to some density operator other than I w)(w I ,

  • 26

    like Q(v). But a simple argument shows that in the MWI, we cannot do this. It is only reasonable that if a statevector has a zero projection on the subspace spanned by a certain

    eigenvector, there can be no world corresponding to that subspace in the MWI. (To continue

    our analogy between spatial-region and Hilbert-space subspace localization of consciousness,

    if a certain spacetime region is empty, we can hardly assign consciousness to its contents.

    It seems similarly unreasonable to assign consciousnesses to "empty" subspaces of the Hilbert

    space.) Therefore we must assign probability zero to worlds corresponding to such empty

    subspaces. It follows from the axioms of probability that we must assign probability one to

    a subspace if the statevector lies in that subspace. The only measure satisfying these

    conditions and additivity is the square-amplitude measure corresponding to the statevector.

    (Consider the one-to-one function from H into the space of density operators mentioned

    above. Since density operators are Hermitian, they have real eigenvalues and any density

    operator p can be represented as p = C l p , I ~ l ) ( ~ l I , where the vl are an orthonormal basis for H and the p, are between 0 and 1 and sum to 1. Letting the actual statevector be called

    v0, and letting the Ivk) be normalized states orthogonal to Iv0) and forming an orthonormal basis together with it, we consider measurement of an observable A which has this basis as

    its Set of eigenvectors. Letting oc, be the eigenvalue corresponding to an eigenvector Ivk), we require that PA(& I p), the probability that a measurement of A yields a, if the density matrix is p (calculated according to the usual rules for deriving probabilities from density

    matrices) is 0 for k # 0, and 1 for k = 0. This means that C,p,II(~kI~l)112 = 0 for k # 0.

    For this to be true, since both the pi and the II(vkIyf,)112 are nonnegative, for each i

    either pI or II(yfktvj)l12 must be zero. Since this is true for all i and k, it means that the

    only Iv,) which can enter the representation of the density matrix with nonzero weight p1 are those which are orthogonal to all the Ivk) with nonzero k. The only such (normalized)

  • 27

    vector is Iyfo), so the only vector which can enter the representation of the density matrix

    isIyfo), the actual statevector. The only allowable density matrix is thus lyfo)(yfoI, the

    density matrix corresponding to the statevector.) We now have an acceptable alternative

    derivation of probabilities from the formalism (stressing the psychological nature of the

    trajectories behind Everett's additivity requirement, and adducing Gleason's theorem and the

    0-1 probability constraints imposed by the MWI).

    8.3 The De-Witt Graham derivation. Even later proponents of the MWI, de Witt and

    Graham in particular, felt Everett's arguments for the square-amplitude probabilities to be

    inadequate, and presented arguments they felt were better. For instance, there is an argument

    attributed by De Witt (1971) to Graham (and well presented in d'Espagnat (1976)). (Everett

    states the result, while laying less stress on it than do DeWitt (1971) and Graham (1973)).

    In this argument, one examines relative frequencies of results in ensembles of identical

    experiments, and shows that in the limit as the number of experiments goes to infinity, the

    difference between the observed frequencies and those predicted by standard QM can be

    made as small as desired, except for a "negligible" set of cases which approaches zero

    measure. The difficulty is that the argument that this set is negligible rests on the fact that

    the component of the statevector corresponding to such cases approaches zero norm, and the

    appropriateness of the norm as a measure of relative probability is precisely what we are

    trying to establish, D'Espagnat seems not to view this as a problem, describing the extra

    assumption "that vectors with zero norm correspond to nonexisting branches" as "very

    natural." This is indeed a natural assumption, but it does not necessarily imply that

    statevectors with very small norm have very small probability, unless one makes the

    additional assumption that the relative probability of a branch is a uniformly continuous

    function of its relative norm, This sounds pretty reasonable, but no argument is given for

  • it. A variant of this argument defines a relative frequency operator on infinite tensor

    products of Hilbert spaces, i.e on vectors representing possible outcomes of infinite sequences

    of measurements (and superpositions thereof). Its eigenvalues are shown to be equal to the

    quantum mechanical probabilities. When the formalism is interpreted, this turns out to be

    the same argument as that just given, and the same objection arises when one asks why the

    mathematical idealization of a relative frequency operator on infinite sequences should be

    relevant to actual measurements on finite sequences.

    Graham's objection to Everett is worth quoting at length:

    Everett gives no connection between his measure and the actual operations involved in determining a relative frequency, no way in which the value of his measure can actually influence the reading of, say, a particle counter. Furthermore, it is extremely difficult to see what significance such a measure can have when its implications are completely contradicted by a simple count of the worlds involved, worlds that Everett's own work assures us must all be on the same footing.

    (To be sure Everett argues that the measure ... is unique. But remember that Gleason has shown that the probabilities defined by the Born interpretation, considered as a measure on a Hilbert space, are themselves unique. Nevertheless this (hopefully) does not deter anyone from inquiring into the connection between those probabilities and experiments that measure relative frequency.) (Graham 1973).

    Graham then makes roughly the point I made in the previous paragraph about the

    DeWitt-Graham-Everett demonstration that relative frequencies converge on the quantum

    mechanical probabilities: that it relies on the probability measure it is intended to derive.

    Now Graham's objection that "those probabilities" (in Gleason's theorem) or "[Everett's]

    measure" are not immediately connected with "experiments that measure relative frequency"

    requires some subtlety in its interpretation. If the claim is that the square-amplitude

    probabilities need to be related to relative frequencies, then the DeWitt-Graham-Everett

    argument does as well as can be expected. Any attempt to require an interpretation of

    probabilities in terms of limits of relative frequencies will run up against the problem that

  • 29

    these limits turn out to be plims-- probability limits-- so we are stuck with probabilities as

    primitives. That is no reason to reject a particular use of probability theory such as

    Everett's.

    An alternative interpretation of Graham's objection would be that it is not so much

    the transition from probability to relative frequency as the transition from measure to

    probability that is questionable. The formalism allows one to define this square-amplitude

    measure, but who says it tells us anything about probabilities of events? Maybe these events

    just happen, and there are no probabilities. Although we could assume these particular

    probabilities (and, given the above argument for the uniqueness of the square-amplitude

    measure, no others) we are not forced to assume any probabilities, so their introduction is

    "going beyond the formalism," as surely as in versions (C) or (D) or de Broglie-Bohm. AS

    DeWitt (1971) says: "although reality as a whole is completely deterministic, our own little

    corner of it suffers from indeterminism. The interpretation of the quantum mechanical

    formalism (and hence the proof of Everett's metatheorem) is complete only when we show

    that this indeterminism is nevertheless limited by rigorous statistical laws." By examining

    the way our own little corner fits into the whole, we can apparently derive what those

    statistical laws would have to be, but it is not clear we can derive that such laws must

    apply, unless we are willing to argue that we must assign probabilities when there is a

    unique acceptable distribution .4

    4Graham (1973) has attempted to derive the quantum mechanical probabilities for experiments measuring macroscopic observables by using the quantum statistical-mechanical assumption of equal a priori probabilities and random phases for eigenstates. If we are willing to accept that consciousness is necessarily a macroscopic phenomenon, then this argument, if valid, would allow us to base the probabilities on foundations no less secure than those of statistical mechanics. However, the major justification for the Gibbs principle is that the statistical mechanics constructed from it works, empirically. Perhaps the fact that the quantum mechanical probabilities derived from the mere assumption that we must have some probabilities also work empirically, makes that assumption equally secure, so that there

  • 30

    9. The Option of Refraining From Assigning Probabilities. The option of claiming that

    the MWI formalism still gives us no picture of how these probabilities of perspectival events

    arise, and perhaps even no grounds for assuming such probabilities exist, could correspond

    to "complete ignorance"or "true uncertainty" in the decision-theoretic sense (Luce and Raiffa

    (1957, pp. 12, 275-8)), or as I will call it, "nonprobabilistic indeterminacy".

    There are several possible arguments against this.

    (1) Assuming there are no probabilities makes the theory empirically inapplicable,

    while the mere assumption that there are some probabilities, plus the Schriidinger

    equation/statevector formalism, yields the empirically correct probabilities. If we take this

    approach, we fail to explain what it is about the underlying reality described by the MWI

    that makes us choose the probabilistic, rather than the nonprobabilistic, version of the MWI.

    Furthermore, nonprobabilistic indeterminacy may not be very useful for making predictions,

    but as I shall argue below, it is not empirically inapplicable.

    (2) Nonprobabilistic indeterminacy is necessarily "subjective" in the sense of

    "subjective (i.e. epistemological) probability." It therefore does not apply here, where the

    probabilities, as argued in section 7, are "objective" probabilities (though of "subjective", i.e.

    perspectival, events). This is to claim that nonprobabilistic indeterminacy is always a matter

    of having no clue about the real probability distribution (possibly degenerate), which always

    exists. The only justification for not assigning a single distribution would be suspension of

    judgement between a number of possible distributions. But the uncertainty in the many-

    worlds account of measurement is not due to our ignorance of something now determined.

    There is no "fact of the matter" before a measurement, about which branch I will go into,

    any more than there is a "fact of the matter," (except perhaps in some abstruse metaphysical

    is no need to appeal to statistical mechanics and require consciousness to be macroscopic.

  • 31

    sense) what the outcome of a measurement will be on a statevector-reduction view. The

    probabilities (or the uncertainty, if we refuse to assign probabilities) are as good as our

    knowledge could possibly be, theoretically, and in that sense "objective". (See Section 7.)

    A variant of this argument points out that these events are repeatable, and thus not the kind

    of "unique event" which it is sometimes argued is the proper context for nonprobabilistic

    indeterminacy.

    I believe this argument is simply wrong. One might cite, for example, the existence

    of infinite sequences with no limits of relative frequencies to buttress the possibility that

    "objective" nonprobabilistic indeterminacy could really exist. To counter this, one could

    argue that such sequences may result (though with probability zero-- which does not mean

    impossibility) from probabilistic processes. And one might argue that no finite amount of

    data can convince us we face such an objective nonprobabilistic indeterministic process,

    rather than a probabilistic one. Nonprobabilistic indeterminacy would then be acceptable

    only as a description of our ignorance in situations where we must act without adequate

    data-- never as part of a description of the world which is a candidate for a scientific theory,

    viewed as potentially standing up to indefinite amounts of further data collection. Since the

    MWI is viewed as a candidate for a (possibly final) scientific theory, and since the

    measurements situations which create (perspectival) indeterminacy within it are repeatable,

    we would have to view these measurements as situations of probabilistic indeterminacy.

    The problem with this is that we can in theory have perfectly good evidence that we

    are facing a nonprobabilistic indeterminate process, even on the basis of a finite amount of

    data. With an infinite amount of data, we might of course have a sequence with no limit

    of relative frequency, and since this has zero probability on any probabilistic hypothesis, we

    would be justified in assuming a nonprobabilistic process-- which has nothing to say about

  • 32

    the probability of the data, of course, but at least doesn't assign it probability zero. But

    there are also finite data sets which justify the inference that it is extremely unlikely they

    were produced by a probabilistic process. For instance, divide the data into two sets of

    roughly equal size by some previously chosen, data-independent rule. If (for large amounts

    of data N) the relative frequencies in the two subsets differ too greatly, we may conclude

    the data was probably generated by a nonprobabilistic process. For any probabilistic process

    has a very small probability for this sort of discrepancy-- indeed the probability approaches

    zero for large N.

    (3) We can empirically determine relative frequencies, and perhaps this fact is in

    itself sufficient to justify assuming that there are probabilities. This is not adequate because

    the task of the MWI is precisely to find a theoretical structure which reproduces the

    empirical facts, and this includes reproducing the empirical fact that there are probabilities.

    We want a theoretical argument for this from within the MWI.

    Conclusion. By taking the "multiplicity of worlds" to occur at the level of consciousness,

    Le. of a multiplicity of perspectives on a single reality, I have shown that the MWI is a

    coherent and consistent interpretation of quantum mechanics. Many of the arguments that

    the MWI is inconsistent were shown to result from the erroneous notion that additional

    physical structure was needed to account for the multiplicity of worlds. The notion, put

    forth by Bell, for instance, that the quantum mechanical probabilities were only one of many

    probability distributions which could be imposed on the MWI was also shown to be incorrect

    when applied to the "psychological" version. But an important, possibly fatal, difficulty was

    shown to remain: that of vindicating this unique acceptable probability distribution by

    showing that so far, no adequate argument is apparent which uses the MWI to rule out

  • 33

    nonprobabilistic indeterminacy. Those who take a dubious view of the notion of

    nonprobabilistic indeterminacy (some Bayesians, for instance) may see no difficulty here.

    I view it as a major difficulty which should be a focus of future work on the MWI.

    Even if it is consistent and succeeds in reproducing the experimental facts, there are

    reasons for disliking the MWI, for instance that it implies the view that our minds

    occasionally split into many minds, which we will probably never be able to reestablish

    contact with, in different branches of the "universal wavefunction." While I certainly don't

    consider it a priori impossible that science should lead us to this belief--as proponents of the

    MWI believe it does--1 do consider this belief sufficiently bizarre a priori that it is worth

    investigating the alternatives. However, it may be more scientifically satisfying to adopt the

    splitting-consciousnesses view along with a physical theory that is rigorous, precise, and

    economical, than to adopt the "reduction of the statevector" view which is uneconomical in

    that it postulates two fundamental and radically different modes of change of the statevector,

    and fuzzy in that it gives no clear physical criteria for when one mode rather than the other

    obtains. Therefore interpretations which also reject statevector reduction appear the most

    promising alternatives to the MWI. I argued that the de Broglie-Bohm-Bell type of hidden

    variable theory, Bell's Everett(?) version of the MWI (C), its hidden-variables analog (F),

    and perhaps some many-worlds-with trajectories (D) interpretations remain logically

    acceptable alternatives. Their major differences with version (A) are the need to introduce

    probabilities explicitly as part of the physics, the need to add something to the Schrodinger

    formalism, and the related need to choose a preferred observable. Once it is necessary to

    do this, one might argue, with Bell, that there is little point in retaining the extra worlds;

    if so, the major alternatives are version (A) of the MWI and the de Broglie-Bohm-Bell pilot

  • 34

    wave t h e ~ r y . ~ Future work needs to examine the consequences and justification of the de

    Broglie-Bohm-Bell introduction of preferred observables.

    Despite my defense of the consistency and coherence of the MWI, my own

    sympathies are more with de Broglie-Bohm-Bell: I find the multiplication of consciousnesses

    in the MWI unappealing. This might be termed a mere metaphysical preference. But it is

    possible that the ultimate best choice of interpretation will be determined by its fruitfulness

    as the basis for new physical theories connecting quantum theory with gravitation, and

    "metaphysical" preferences between interpretations in part express different views on their

    fruitfulness in this endeavor. It is perhaps more likely, as Bell often suggests, that some

    wholly new way of viewing quantum theory will emerge out of such a synthesis. The

    currently available realistic interpretations of quantum theory may then be viewed as giving

    us suggestions about the nature of this future perspective on quantum theory, since they give

    us different pictures of reality which are consistent with current quantum theory and the

    experimental facts. The psychological version of the MWI suggests the most conservative

    possibility: that the basic structure of quantum theory may survive intact and without major

    additions-- at the price of a multiplication of consciousnesses. Hidden variable theories like

    de Broglie-Bohm suggest that a more radical revision of the quantum formalism, adding

    additional structure beyond a wavefunction framework, may eventuate.6 But whatever one's

    preferences, if one wants an accurate idea of the various kinds of realities that are

    compatible with quantum theory, it is important to give the psychological version of the

    '(F) is vulnerable to Bell's accusations of solipsism of the present moment and seems to have no compensating advantages over any of the other versions. I omit (E) on the grounds that preferred observables must be chosen on arbitrary, "human-centered'' grounds. See Bell (1981).

    The two types of theory also differ with respect to the nature of "nonlocality" or "nonseparability" they involve, but there is not space to treat this here.

  • 35

    MWI a place among consistent interpretations of that theory, and to understand the true

    nature of the remaining difficulties with it.

  • 36

    REFERENCES

    Aharonov, Y., and Albert, D. (1980) "States and Observables in Relativistic Quantum Field

    Theories", Physical Review D 21: 3316-3324.

    Aharonov, Y., and Albert, D. (1981), "Can We Make Sense out of the Measurement Process

    in Relativistic Quantum Mechanics?", Physical Review D 24: 359-370.

    Bell, J.S. (1975), "On Wave Packet Reduction in the Coleman-Hepp Model", Helvetica Physica

    Acta 48: 93-8. Reprinted in Bell (1987).

    Bell, J.S. (1976), "The Measurement Theory of Everett and de Broglie's Pilot Wave", in

    Quantum Mechanics, Determinism, Causality, and Particles, M. Flato et al. (eds.).

    Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel, pp. 11-17. Reprinted in Bell (1987).

    Bell, J.S. (1981), "Quantum Mechanics for Cosmologists", in C. Isham, R. Penrose, and D.

    Sciama (eds.), Quantum Gravity 2. Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 61 1-37. Reprinted

    in Bell (1987).

    Bell, J.S. (1982), "On the Impossible Pilot Wave", Foundations of Physics 12: 989-99.

    Reprinted in Bell (1987).

    Bell, J.S. (1987), Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics. Cambridge University

    Press, 1987.

    Bell, J.S., and Nauenberg, M. (1966), "The Moral Aspect of Quantum Mechanics", in A. De

    Shalit, H. Feschbach, and L. Van Hove (eds.), Preludes in Theoretical Physics.

    Amsterdam: North Holland, pp. 279-86. Reprinted in Bell (1987).

    Bohm, D. (195 l), Quantum Theory, Chapter 22. Englewood Cliffs NJ: Prentice-Hall. (Dover

    reprint, Mineola NY, 1989).

  • 37

    Bohm, D. (1952), "A Suggested Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics in Terms of 'Hidden

    Variables'", Parts I and 11, Physical Review 85: 160-93. Reprinted in Wheeler and

    Zurek (1983).

    Bohm, D. (1953), "Proof that Probability Density Approaches tf in Causal Interpretation

    of Quantum Theory", Physical Review 89: 458-466.

    Daneri, A., Loinger, D., and Prosperi, G.M. (1962). "Quantum Theory of Measurement and

    Ergodicity Conditions", Nuclear Physics 33: 297-3 19. Reprinted in Wheeler and Zurek

    (1983).

    Davies, P.C.W., and Brown, J.R. (eds.) (1986) The Ghost in the Atom. Cambridge: Cambridge

    University Press.

    d'Espagnat, B. (1976), The Conceptual Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. 2nd ed. Reading,

    MA: Addison-Wesley. (Addison-Wesley reprint 1989).

    De Witt, B.S., and Graham, N. (eds.), The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics.

    Princeton University Press, 1973.

    De Witt, B.S. (1971)., "The Many-Universes Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics", in B.

    d' Espagnat (ed.) Proceedings of the International School of Physics ' Enrico Fermi'

    Course IL: Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. NY: Academic Press. Reprinted

    in De Witt and Graham (1973) and Wheeler and Zurek (1983).

    Everett, H.D. (1957a), "'Relative State' Formulation of Quantum Mechanics", Reviews of

    Modern Physics 29: 454-62. Reprinted in De Witt and Graham (1973) and Wheeler

    and Zurek (1983).

    Everett, H.D. (1957b), The Theory of the Universal Wave Function, Ph.D. thesis, Princeton.

    Reprinted in De Witt and Graham (1973).

  • 38

    Englert, B.-G., Schwinger, J., and Scully, M.O. (1988). "Is Spin Coherence Like Humpty-

    Dumpty? I", Foundations of Physics 18: 1045.

    Fine, A. (1973), British Journal of the Philosophy of Science 24: 33-34.

    Gleason, A.M. (1957), "Measures on the Closed Subspaces of a Hilbert Space", Journal of

    Mathematics and Mechanics 6: 885-893.

    Graham, N. (1973), "The Measurement of Relative Frequency", in De Witt and Graham

    (1973), pp. 229-253.

    Luce, R.D. and Raiffa, H. (1957), Games and Decisions. New York: Wiley. (Dover reprint

    1989).

    Peres, A. (1980), "Can We Undo Quantum Measurements", Physical Review D 22: 879-83.

    Reprinted in Wheeler and Zurek (1983).

    Scully, M.O., Englert, B.-G., and Schwinger, J. (1989), "Is Spin Coherence Like Humpty-

    Dumpty? 111. Effects of Observation and Correlation", preprint.

    Schwinger, J., Scully, M.O., and Englert, B.-G. (1988), "Is Spin Coherence Like Humpty-

    Dumpty? 11", Zeitschrift fur Physik D IO: 135.

    Wheeler, J. (1977), "Include the Observer in the Wave Function?", in J. k i te Lopes and M.

    Paty (eds.), Quantum Mechanics a Half Century Later, Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel,

    pp. 1-18.

    Wigner, E.P. (1961), "Remarks on the Mind-Body Problem", in I.J. Good (ed.), The Scientist

    Speculates, New York: Basic Books. Reprinted in E. Wigner, (1967), Symmetries and

    Reflections, Bloomington: Indiana University Press, and in Wheeler and Zurek (1983).

    Wigner, E.P. (1963), "The Problem of Measurement", American Journal of Physics 31: 6-

    15. Reprinted in E. Wigner (1967), Symmetries and Reflections. Bloomington:

    Indiana University Press, and in Wheeler and Zurek (1983).

  • 39

    Wigner, E.P. (1973), "Epistemological Perspective on Quantum Theory", in C.A. Hooker (ed.),

    Contemporary Research in the Foundations and Philosophy of Quantum Theory.

    Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel, pp. 369-385.

    Wigner, E.P. (1976), "Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics", mimeographed notes, revised

    and reprinted in Wheeler and Zurek (1983), pp. 260-314.

    Zeh, H.D. (1970), "On the Interpretation of Measurement in Quantum Theory", Foundations

    of Physics I: 69-76. Reprinted in Wheeler and Zurek (1983).