Top Banner
HAL Id: hal-00478453 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-00478453 Submitted on 30 Apr 2010 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- entific research documents, whether they are pub- lished or not. The documents may come from teaching and research institutions in France or abroad, or from public or private research centers. L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires publics ou privés. Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive mood in Spanish Elisabeth Villalta To cite this version: Elisabeth Villalta. Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive mood in Spanish. Linguistics and Philosophy, Springer Verlag, 2009, 31 (4), pp.467-522. 10.1007/s10988-008-9046-x. hal-00478453
82

Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

Dec 18, 2021

Download

Documents

dariahiddleston
Welcome message from author
This document is posted to help you gain knowledge. Please leave a comment to let me know what you think about it! Share it to your friends and learn new things together.
Transcript
Page 1: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

HAL Id: hal-00478453https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-00478453

Submitted on 30 Apr 2010

HAL is a multi-disciplinary open accessarchive for the deposit and dissemination of sci-entific research documents, whether they are pub-lished or not. The documents may come fromteaching and research institutions in France orabroad, or from public or private research centers.

L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, estdestinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documentsscientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non,émanant des établissements d’enseignement et derecherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoirespublics ou privés.

Mood and gradability: an investigation of thesubjunctive mood in Spanish

Elisabeth Villalta

To cite this version:Elisabeth Villalta. Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive mood in Spanish.Linguistics and Philosophy, Springer Verlag, 2009, 31 (4), pp.467-522. �10.1007/s10988-008-9046-x�.�hal-00478453�

Page 2: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

Mood and Gradability:

An Investigation of the Subjunctive Mood in Spanish

Abstract

In Spanish (and other Romance languages) certain predicates select the subjunctive mood in

the embedded clause, while others select the indicative mood. In this paper, I present a new analysis

for the predicates that select the subjunctive mood in Spanish that is based on a semantics of

comparison. The main generalization proposed here is the following: in Spanish, a predicate selects

the subjunctive mood in its embedded proposition if the proposition is compared to its contextual

alternatives on a scale introduced by the predicate. In this proposal, predicates that select the

subjunctive mood are thus analyzed as gradable predicates. Furthermore, the subjunctive mood

morpheme is claimed to make a semantic contribution, namely to evaluate the contextual alternatives

that are compared by the predicate. In comparing this proposal to other approaches, I show that it can

more straightforwardly account for a number of properties of these predicates (entailment relations,

practical inferences, and contexts with more than two alternatives). New empirical evidence for two

crucial properties of the predicates that select the subjunctive mood is provided: these predicates are

focus sensitive and they are gradable, two properties that follow directly from the proposal developed

here. In the vast literature on mood, the link between the appearance of the subjunctive mood and

these important properties has never been made before.

Page 3: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

2

1. Introduction

In Spanish (and other Romance languages) certain predicates select the subjunctive mood in

the embedded clause, while others select the indicative mood. In this paper, I develop a new analysis

for the predicates that select the subjunctive mood in Spanish. Starting out with Heim=s (1992)

semantics for propositional attitude predicates, I develop an analysis that is based on a semantics of

comparison. The main generalization proposed here is the following: in Spanish, a predicate selects

the subjunctive mood in its embedded proposition if the proposition is compared to its contextual

alternatives on a scale introduced by the predicate. In this proposal, predicates that select the

subjunctive mood are thus analyzed as gradable predicates.

The following important question will also be addressed: what role does the subjunctive mood

play in the semantic composition of the sentence? The investigation of what the subjunctive mood

contributes to the meaning composition provides a first step towards a better understanding of why

subjunctive verb forms require special semantic licensing conditions and why they are obligatory in

certain contexts. I will argue that the licensing conditions of subjunctive clauses can be explained in a

system in which, next to the ordinary semantic value, we also compute an alternative semantic value

of the sentence (cf. Rooth 1985). The view that the semantic component consists of two semantic

values rather than just the ordinary semantic value has proven to be very fruitful in various areas. In

Rooth (1985) it was introduced to account for focus phenomena and focus sensitive operators such as

only, but later also employed by Krifka (1995) for the licensing of negative polarity items. Most

recently, Beck (2006, to appear) argues that this view can successfully be adopted for the analysis of a

whole range of constructions and linguistic phenomena. I show here that this view is also fruitful for

an explanation of the licensing conditions of the subjunctive mood.

Mood selection in Romance is of course too complex to be treated here in an exhaustive

manner. This paper concentrates uniquely on the Spanish data and is limited to a discussion of the

characteristics of the predicates that select the subjunctive mood. There are other semantic and

pragmatic factors that may influence mood selection in Spanish (such as negation, interrogatives or

conditionals) but these will not be discussed here.

The subjunctive mood in Romance languages has received considerable attention in traditional

as well as in recent theoretical linguistic literature. The subjunctive mood has been related to notions

such as Irrealis (Givón 1994), Non-assertion (Bolinger 1968, Terrell & Hooper 1974, Panzeri 2002,

Page 4: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

3

2003, Schlenker 2005), Strong Intensionality (Farkas 1985, 1992), Non-Veridicality (Giannakidou

1997, 1998, 1999), Model Shift (Quer 1998), Modality (Giorgi & Pianesi 1997, Portner 1992,1997),

and many more. Most of these proposals have concentrated on characterizing the common properties

of the contexts that trigger the subjunctive mood rather than spelling out an explicit semantics for the

predicates that select the subjunctive mood. For reasons of space, I will not go into the details of these

approaches here.1 I will limit myself to comparing my proposal to those approaches that present an

explicit proposal for the semantics of these predicates, such as Heim (1992), von Fintel (1999) and

Giorgi and Pianesi (1997). In particular, Giorgi and Piannesi (1997) propose that the licensing

contexts for subjunctive mood can be characterized with Kratzer=s semantics for modality (cf.

Kratzer 1977, 1981, 1999). I will argue that an approach which uses such a semantics for these

predicates cannot account for a number of important properties (entailment relations, practical

inferences, and contexts with more than two alternatives). To the contrary, the proposal developed

here accommodates these properties in a straightforward way.

Finally, in this paper, new empirical evidence for two crucial properties of the predicates that

select the subjunctive mood will be discussed: these predicates are focus sensitive (cf. Dretske 1972)

and they are gradable. These two properties follow directly from the proposal developed here. In the

vast literature on mood, the link between the appearance of the subjunctive mood and these important

properties has never been made before.

The structure of this paper is as follows. In section 2, the relevant data are presented. In

section 3, Heim=s(1992) semantics for desire predicates and emotive factive predicates is presented.

In section 4, a new semantics for these predicates is developed based on the comparison of contextual

alternatives. In section 5, the proposal is extended to all predicate classes that select the subjunctive

mood in Spanish. In section 6, this proposal is compared to previous proposals for the semantics of

these predicates (Giorgi and Pianesi1997, von Fintel1999). In section 7, I investigate the focus

sensitivity of these predicates (cf. Dretske 1972,1975) and make a proposal for the semantic

contribution of the subjunctive mood morpheme. Finally, in section 8, I present empirical evidence for

the gradable nature of these predicates and refine my analysis: predicates that select the subjunctive

mood are analyzed as having an extra degree argument.

Error! Main Document Only. See Portner (1999, 2003), as well as Villalta (2006) for an extensive discussion of traditional and recent approaches to the semantics of mood.

Page 5: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

4

2. The distribution of subjunctive mood in Spanish complement clauses

In Spanish, one important factor that determines whether the verb of an embedded clause is in

the indicative or the subjunctive mood is the matrix predicate. The indicative mood is selected by

epistemic predicates (e.g., saber >know=, pensar >think=, creer >believe=), predicates of

communication (e.g., decir >say=, anunciar >announce= ), predicates of certainty (e.g., estar seguro

>be sure=, estar convencido >be convinced=), commissives (e.g., prometer >promise=), fiction

verbs (e.g., soñar >dream=), predicates of mental judgement (e.g. adivinar >guess=, comprender

>understand=) and predicates of perception (e.g. notar >notice=, ver >see=, escuchar >hear=). A few

examples are presented in (1) through (4).

(1) Victoria cree que hará buen tiempo. TO BELIEVE

Victoria believes that PRO make:FUT.IND.3SG good weather.

>Victoria believes that the weather will be good.=

(2) Sofía sabe que se ha planeado un picnic. TO KNOW

Sofía knows that SE have:PAST.IND.3SG planned a picnic.

>Sofía knows that a picnic has been planned .=

(3) Marcela dice que quiere venir. TO SAY

Marcela says that PRO want:PRES.IND.3SG come.

>Marcela says that she wants to come.=

(4) Sofía ha prometido que traerá el postre. TO PROMISE

Sofía has promised that PRO bring:FUT.IND.3SG the dessert.

>Sofía has promised that she will bring the dessert.=

The subjunctive mood is selected by desire predicates (e.g., querer >want=, preferir

>prefer=, temer >fear=), emotive factive predicates (e.g., lamentarse >regret=, alegrarse >be glad=,

sorprenderse >be surprised=), modals (e.g., es possible >it is possible=, es necesario >es

necesario=), predicates expressing doubt (e.g., dudar >doubt=), directives (e.g., ordenar >order=,

Page 6: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

5

aconsejar >advise=, suggerir >suggest=) and causatives (e.g., hacer >make=, conseguir >achieve=).

A few examples are presented below.

(5) Victoria quiere que Marcela venga al picnic. TO WANT

Victoria wants that Marcela come:PRES.SUBJ.3SG to-the picnic.

>Victoria wants Marcela to come to the picnic.=

(6) Sofía duda que Rafael pueda venir. TO DOUBT

Sofia doubts that Rafael can:PRES.SUBJ.3SG come.

>Sofía doubts that Rafael can come.=

(7) Marcela se alegra de que la hayan invitado. TO BE GLAD

Marcela SE glad of that PRO her have:PAST.SUBJ.3PL invited.

>Marcela is glad that they have invited her.=

(8) Victoria sugiere que salgan temprano. TO SUGGEST

Victoria suggests that PRO leave:PRES.SUBJ.3PL early.

>Victoria suggests that they leave early.=

It can be noted that, in both categories, we find factive as well as non-factive predicates.

Sentences that contain factive predicates have the presupposition that the proposition expressed by the

complement clause is true, contrary to sentences with non-factive predicates. Among the predicates

that select the indicative mood, we find factive predicates such as saber (>know=), acordarse

(>remember=) and olvidarse (>forget=), as well as non-factives such as creer (>believe=), prometer

(>promise=), decir (>say=) and soñar (>dream=). Among the predicates that select the subjunctive

mood, all emotive factive predicates and causative predicates are factive.

A number of predicates allow both the indicative and the subjunctive mood in their

complement clause. Crucially, however, mood alternation then correlates with a meaning change in

the predicate. Depending on the mood of the complement clause, the predicates fall under the

corresponding predicate classes as described above. A few examples are presented below.

Page 7: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

6

The predicate sentir can either be interpreted as an emotive factive predicate (>be sorry=) and

then selects the subjunctive mood, as in (9), or it can be interpreted as a predicate of perception

(>sense=/=have the impression=) and then selects the indicative mood, as in (10).

(9) Siento que te hayan hecho daño.

PRO sorry that PRO you have:PAST.SUBJ.3PL done pain.

>I am sorry that they have hurt you.=

(10) Siento que va a haber un problema.

PRO sense that PRO go:FUT.IND.3SG to there-be a problem.

>I have the impression that there is going to be a problem.=

The predicate decir can either be interpreted as a predicate of communication (>tell=/=say=)

and then selects the indicative mood, as in (11), or it can be interpreted as a directive predicate

(>order=) and then selects the subjunctive mood, as in (12). Most of the predicates of communication

are ambiguous in this sense.

(11) Te digo que acabaré a tiempo.

PRO you tell that PRO finish:FUT.IND.1SG on time.

>I tell you that I will finish on time.=

(12) Te dije que acabaras a tiempo.

PRO you told that PRO finish:PAST.SUBJ.2SG on time.

>I told you to finish on time.=

Thus, when a predicate can select both the indicative and the subjunctive mood, the alternation

correlates with a meaning change of the predicate. Notice, crucially, that the meaning change does not

always correlate with a factive/non-factive distinction.

In the following, I turn to a first attempt at characterizing the semantics of the predicates

that select the subjunctive mood in Spanish.

Page 8: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

7

3. A semantics for the predicates that select the subjunctive mood in Spanish

In this section, the goal is to develop a first proposal for a common semantics of the predicates

that select the subjunctive mood in Spanish. I first present Heim=s (1992) proposal for desire

predicates. Heim=s (1992) analysis of desire predicates builds on Stalnaker=s (1984) insight that

every desire report contains a hidden conditional. AA little more explicitly, the leading intuition is that

John wants you to leave means that John thinks that if you leave he will be in a more desirable world

than if you don=t.@ (Heim 1992, p.193). I then argue that such a conditional semantics should be

extended to all predicates that select the subjunctive mood in Spanish.2

3.1 Heim=s (1992) conditional semantics for desire predicates

We begin with the semantics for propositional attitude predicates first introduced by Hintikka

(1969). The truth conditions for the verb believe are given in (13).

(13) >α believes φ= is true in w iff: � w=0 Doxα(w): φ is true in w=.

(Doxα(w) contains all the worlds that are compatible with what α believes in the world w to be

true, also called doxastic alternatives of α in w.)

The truth conditions in (13) say that >α believes φ= is true in a world w if and only if φ is true

in all worlds w= that are compatible with what α believes in w. Thus, to take an example, John

believes that it is raining is true in w iff it is raining in all the worlds w= that are compatible with

what John believes in w.

Adopting the Hintikka-style analysis for a verb such as want results in the truth conditions

given in (14). Here, the worlds compatible with α=s beliefs in w, the doxastic alternatives, have

simply been replaced with the worlds compatible with α=s desires in w, the so-called >buletic=

alternatives.

Error! Main Document Only. Giannakidou (1998,1999), Portner (1999, 2003) and Quer (1998, 2001) also point out that the conditional semantics proposed by Heim (1992) is relevant for mood selection. But they do not discuss the consequences of adopting such a semantics.

Page 9: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

8

(14) >α wants φ= is true in w iff: � w=0 Bulα(w): φ is true in w=.

(Bulα(w) contains all the worlds that are compatible with what α desires in w, also called

buletic alternatives of α in w.)

These truth conditions, however, cannot appropriately capture all the characteristics of the

verb want. This becomes clear as soon as we look at an example more closely. The example in (15),

from Heim (1992), illustrates that these truth conditions are problematic.

(15) I want to teach Tuesdays and Thursdays next semester.

Heim notes that the sentence in (15) can be true in a situation in which in fact I would rather

prefer not to teach at all. In a situation like this the following holds: in all the worlds that are

compatible with what I desire I do not teach. If we adopt the truth conditions in (14), however, the

sentence comes out as false in this situation: the proposition is only evaluated in worlds that are

compatible with my desires, which do not include worlds in which I teach Tuesdays and Thursdays

next semester.

To remedy this problem, Heim (1992) develops a new proposal for want that captures

Stalnaker=s insight that every desire report employs a hidden conditional: >to want something, is to

prefer something to certain relevant alternatives, the relevant alternatives being those possibilities that

the agent believes will be realizable if he doesn=t get what he wants.= (Stalnaker 1984, p.89). The

sentence (15) can thus be paraphrased as in (16).

(16) If I teach Tuesdays and Thursdays next semester, I will be in a more desirable world than if I

teach on other days next semester.

Heim=s new proposal for the truth conditions of want is based on the semantics adopted for

conditionals. Following Lewis (1973) and Stalnaker (1968), a conditional if φ, ψ is true in a world w

iff ψ is true in all φ-worlds maximally similar to w (where a φ-world is a world in which φ is true).

Thus, in (16), the sentence is true if and only if the consequent is true in all those worlds in which I

teach Tuesday and Thursdays next semester and which are otherwise just like the actual world. By

Page 10: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

9

adopting such a conditional semantics, Heim proposes that the verb want has the truth-conditions in

(17).

(17) >α wants φ= is true in w iff:

For every w=0 Doxα(w): Every φ-world maximally similar to w= is more desirable to α in w

than any non-φ-world maximally similar to w=.

(Heim 1992, p.193)

We now apply this proposal to our previous example repeated here in (18).

(18) I want to teach Tuesdays and Thursdays next semester.

Under the truth conditions presented above, for this sentence to be true, the following has to

hold: for each doxastic alternative w=, if I teach Tuesdays and Thursdays next semester in w=, it is a

more desirable world than maximally similar worlds in which I teach on other days. If I teach on other

days in w=, it is a less desirable world than maximally similar worlds in which I do teach on Tuesdays

and Thursdays.

In Heim (1992), the truth conditions of this verb are stated in a context change semantics.

Since I do not use this framework here, I present the equivalent truth conditions in a non-dynamic

semantics3. Heim encodes the relation of comparative similarity among worlds with a family of

selection functions as in (19): for each world w, there is a selection function Simw from propositions

to propositions which maps each proposition p to the set of worlds maximally similar to w in which p

is true (cf. Heim 1992, p.195).

(19) Simw(p)={w=0 W: w=0 p and w= resembles w no less than any other world in p}

3 By using a dynamic framework, Heim solves a number of presupposition projection facts that will remain unaddressed here.

Page 11: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

10

Additionally, Heim uses an abbreviation for the ranking of possible worlds in terms of

desirability. She introduces >α,w4, a relation between worlds, that can also be employed in an extended

sense as a relation between sets of worlds, as defined in (20) (see Heim 1992, p.197).

(20) (a) For any w, w=, w== 0 W, w= >α,w w== iff w= is more desirable to α in w than w==

(b) For any w 0 W, XφW, YφW, X >α,wY iff w= >α,w w== for all w=0 X, w==0 Y.

The truth conditions of the verb want can now be stated as in (21).

(21) � want� (p)(a)(w) = 1 iff

� w= 0 Doxa(w): Simw=(p) >a,w Simw=(5p)

Heim then suggests that this conditional semantics can be extended to other predicates such as

wish and be glad. She argues, however, that there is an important difference between these predicates:

in the case of the predicate want all the desirability comparisons should be entirely among worlds that

the subject believes possible, contrary to predicates such as wish and be glad.

Heim thus proposes to further restrict the truth conditions of want. The truth conditions in (21)

only require that all p-worlds that are maximally similar to w= be more desirable than all 5 p-worlds

maximally similar to w=. Nothing is said about whether these maximally similar worlds have to be

doxastic alternatives or not. In the new proposal, in (22), all desirability comparisons are entirely

among the subject=s belief worlds, because the argument of the similarity function Sim applies to a

subset of the doxastic alternatives. The function Sim now returns the set of worlds that are an element

of Doxa(w) 1 p and Doxa(w) 1 5p respectively and which resemble w no less than any other world.

(22) Conditional semantics for want

� want� (p)(a)(w) = 1 iff

� w= 0 Doxa(w): Simw=(Doxa(w) 1 p) >a,w Simw=(Doxa(w) 1 5p)

Error! Main Document Only. To express that X is more desirable than Y, I will use X >α,w Y rather than X <α,w Y as is originally done in Heim (1992). The definition is otherwise identical to the one in Heim(1992).

Page 12: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

11

It is exactly in this aspect that the predicate want differs from a predicate such as wish. This is best

illustrated with an example.

(23) John wishes he taught on Tuesdays and Thursdays.

This sentence can only be judged to be true in a situation in which John believes that he

doesn=t teach on Tuesdays and Thursdays. Hence, the worlds compatible with his beliefs only include

worlds in which he doesn=t teach on Tuesdays and Thursdays. Thus, we cannot adopt the same truth

conditions as for want. If all desirability comparisons are entirely among the subject=s belief worlds,

the set on the left hand side of the comparison relation will always be empty. Heim proposes that, for

the verb wish, the proposition p is evaluated with respect to a revision of the worlds compatible with

his beliefs, a set that will also include some p-worlds. Heim proposes that this revised set of worlds

results from Doxa(w) by suspending some of the assumptions in Doxa(w), as in the revision of a

context necessary for the interpretation of counterfactuals. The definition proposed in Heim (1992) is

stated in a context change semantics and is not suitable for the semantics adopted here. I will assume

here that the revision of the doxastic alternatives with respect to a proposition p, which I call

revp(Doxa(w)), contains all the worlds in Doxa(w) as well as all the p-worlds most similar to w.

We can now adopt the truth conditions of the predicate wish given in (24). Here, in the first

argument of the ordering relation >a,w, the function Sim applies to worlds that are included in the

revision of the doxastic alternatives.

(24) Conditional semantics for wish

� wish� (p)(a)(w) = 1 iff

� w= 0 Doxa(w): Simw=(revp(Doxa(w)) 1 p) >a,w Simw=(Doxa(w) 1 5p)

Heim (1992) furthermore extends her proposal to the predicate be glad.

(25) John is glad that he teaches on Tuesdays and Thursdays.

The sentence in (25) has the presupposition that John believes in the truth of the complement,

i.e. John believes that he teaches on Tuesdays and Thursdays. In this case, John=s doxastic

Page 13: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

12

alternatives do not include worlds in which he doesn=t teach on Tuesdays and Thursdays. Hence, for

the predicate be glad, it is in the second argument of the ordering relation >a,w , that the function Sim

applies to worlds that are included in a revision of the doxastic alternatives. The truth conditions of

the predicate be glad are given in (26).

(26) Conditional semantics for be glad

� be glad� (p)(a)(w) = 1

� w= 0 Doxa(w): Simw=(Doxa(w) 1 p) >a,w Simw=(rev5p(Doxa(w)) 1 5p)

To summarize, in Heim (1992), predicates such as wish, want and be glad share their core

semantics, a conditional semantics. They have the common feature that for each doxastic alternative,

two sets of worlds are compared. The only difference between these predicates lies in whether the

relevant sets of worlds are included in the doxastic alternatives of the subject or rather in a revision of

the doxastic alternatives of the subject.

3.2 A conditional semantics for predicates that select the subjunctive mood

After this brief presentation of Heim=s semantics for desire predicates, we now return to the

class of predicates that select the subjunctive mood in Spanish. The predicates discussed by Heim

(1992) all select the subjunctive mood in Spanish. My hypothesis will be that the conditional

semantics adopted so far can also be extended to all other predicate classes that select the subjunctive

mood in Spanish, such as modals, predicates of doubt, directives and causatives. This hypothesis

naturally accommodates the fact that among the predicates that select the subjunctive mood we find

factive as well as non-factive predicates. The semantic property shared by these predicates is that they

establish a comparison. Whether this comparison is between worlds that are among the doxastic

alternatives of the subject or not is irrelevant for mood selection.

Under this hypothesis, the predicates that select the subjunctive mood in Spanish share the

following common property: they introduce an ordering relation or scale. It is important to observe

that the ordering relation expressed by the predicate is not a relation of desirability for all predicates.

For instance, predicates such as sorprenderse >be surprised= and dudar >doubt= rather require an

ordering relation of likelihood. Also, a number of emotive factive predicates cannot be based on the

Page 14: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

13

notion of desirability, such as es interesante (>it is interesting=), es divertido (>it is amusing=), etc. I

will assume that the ordering relation is contributed by the lexical meaning of each predicate. This is

reminiscent of what has been said about the meaning of gradable adjectives in the literature. The

scalar approaches to the semantics of gradable adjectives argue that the meaning of a gradable

adjective such as tall directly contributes the dimension of the scale involved (in the case of tall the

dimension is height).5

Below, I present a first attempt at a characterization of the predicates that select the

subjunctive mood in Spanish, as stated in (27).

(27) Preliminary hypothesis for the subjunctive mood in Spanish

A proposition p that is the complement of the matrix predicate requires the subjunctive mood

iff the matrix predicate introduces an ordering relation and compares p to non-p.

To conclude, I have proposed to adopt Heim=s (1992) conditional semantics to characterize

the predicates that select the subjunctive mood in Spanish. In the following, I present two arguments

that call for a revision of this semantics.

4. A new proposal: comparison of contextual alternatives

In this section, I propose to revise the semantics for the predicates that select the subjunctive

mood in Spanish. First, I argue that their semantics involves comparison of the embedded proposition

p with contextually available alternatives, rather than simply with 5p. Second, I argue that, in the truth

conditions, reference to the subject=s beliefs can be replaced with the set of contextually available

alternatives. I then develop a new analysis for these predicates.

Error! Main Document Only. For approaches that adopt a scalar semantics for gradable adjectives see Bartsch and Venneman 1973, Bierwisch 1989, Cresswell 1976, Kamp 1975, Kennedy 1999, Klein E. 1980, 1991, Rullmann 1995, Schwarzschild & Wilkinson 1999, Seuren 1973, von Stechow 1984a,1984b, and many others.

Page 15: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

14

4.1 When more than two contextual alternatives are available

The central point to be made in this section is that the semantics of the predicates selecting the

subjunctive mood requires comparison of contextual alternative propositions. In fact, the semantics

adopted so far is based on a special case where the context only provides the alternatives p and 5p.

Contexts providing more than two alternatives illustrate this issue quite clearly. Consider the scenario

in (28).

(28) Sofía has promised to bring a dessert to the picnic. Victoria believes that there are three

possibilities for what she may actually do. She could prepare a chocolate cake, even though

Victoria considers that extremely unlikely because it represents far too much work. She might

bring an apple pie, which Victoria considers very likely since she can just buy it at the bakery

nearby. Or Sofía might bring ice-cream, which seems most likely to Victoria, since she

usually has some in her freezer. Victoria prefers the chocolate cake over the apple pie and the

apple pie over the ice-cream.

The schematic figure in (29) represents the two scales involved in this scenario, desirability

according to Victoria and likelihood according to Victoria. That Sofía will bring the chocolate cake is

the most desirable and most unlikely alternative; that she will bring the ice cream is the least desirable

and most likely alternative.

(29) + desirable ┬ chocolate cake ┬ - likely (according to Victoria) │ │ │ │ │ │ │ apple pie │ │ │

! desirable ┴ ice cream ┴ + likely

In this situation, the sentence in (30) is intuitively judged to be false.

(30) Victoria wishes Sofía would bring an apple pie.

Page 16: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

15

Contrary to intuitions, Heim=s conditional semantics for the verb wish predicts that this

sentence should come out as true in this scenario. Under Heim=s proposal, the sentence (30) is true iff

for all worlds w= that are compatible with Victoria=s beliefs, the worlds in which Sofía brings the

apple pie are more desirable to Victoria than all the minimally different worlds in which she doesn=t.

This is true, since, in the given scenario, the closest worlds in which Sofía doesn=t bring an apple pie

are worlds in which she brings ice-cream. This set does not contain worlds in which she brings

chocolate cake (these are not minimally different for Victoria since she considers them as extremely

unlikely). A conditional semantics thus does not make the correct predictions for this scenario.

Other predicates give rise to similar effects in contexts that make more than two alternatives

available. Imagine that, in the continuation of the previous scenario, Sofía does in fact bring the apple

pie to the picnic. The sentence in (31) can then be true in that situation.

(31) Victoria is disappointed that Sofía brought an apple pie.

A conditional semantics for the predicate be disappointed, however, predicts (31) to be false

in this scenario. Simplifying somewhat, I will assume that the only difference between the semantics

of be disappointed and be glad is that the ordering relation of desirability is reversed. The truth

conditions of be disappointed then predict that the worlds in which Sofía brought the apple pie are

less desirable to Victoria than all the minimally different worlds in which she doesn=t. This is false,

since the closest worlds are all worlds in which she brings ice-cream. She considers these worlds as

less desirable. Again, a conditional semantics does not make the correct predictions for a scenario as

described above.

I conclude that the semantics of the predicates under discussion involves comparison of p with

the set of its contextual alternatives rather than with just 5p. I propose to adopt a new lexical entry for

want as in (32). The difference with the previous lexical entry for want is that, here 5p is replaced by

the contextually given alternatives q.

(32) Semantics of want based on comparison of alternatives

� wantC� g(p)(a)(w) = 1 iff

� q: q � p & q 0 g(C): Simw=(Doxa(w) 1 p) >a,w Simw=(Doxa(w) 1 q)

Page 17: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

16

In the lexical entry in (32), the verb want carries an index C that stands for a variable

anaphoric to a contextually determined set of propositions (it is an index of type <<s,t>,t>>). This

variable receives its content from the variable assignment g. Variables of this kind have also been

used before for similar purposes, such as for the domain of quantification of only in Rooth (1985,

1992) and the resource domain of adverbs of quantification in von Fintel (1994), as well as the

contextual restriction of determiners in Westerståhl (1985), and others.

To conclude, in this section, I have argued that comparison between p and 5 p is a special case

of comparison of p with its contextual alternatives. I now turn to one further revision of the semantics

of these predicates.

4.2 Reference to the doxastic alternatives

In what follows, I argue that, in Heim=s semantics for desire predicates, the desires of the

subject are too tightly connected to his/her beliefs. In fact, Heim=s semantics predicts that for

sentences containing desire predicates certain inferences should be possible, contrary to our intuitions.

Imagine a situation in which my choices for my teaching schedule of the next semester depend on

how much work I get done this semester. The conclusion in (33c), nevertheless cannot be inferred.

(33) a) I want to teach Tuesdays and Thursdays next semester.

b) I believe that I will teach Tuesdays and Thursdays next semester if and only if I work hard

now.

____________________________________

c) Invalid inference:

� I want to work hard now.

The conditional semantics for the predicate want, however, predicts that this inference should

be valid. For clarification, I repeat Heim=s conditional semantics for the predicate want.

(34) Conditional semantics for want

� want� (p)(a)(w) = 1 iff

� w= 0 Doxa(w): Simw=(Doxa(w) 1 p) >a,w Simw=(Doxa(w) 1 5p)

Page 18: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

17

According to (34), from the truth of (33a) it follows that in DoxI(w) all the worlds in which I

teach Tuesdays and Thursdays next semester are more desirable than maximally similar worlds in

which I don=t teach on Tuesdays and Thursdays next semester. From the truth of (33b) it follows that

in DoxI(w) the worlds in which I teach Tuesdays and Thursdays next semester correspond exactly to

those worlds in which I work hard this semester. Hence, from (33a) and (33b) it follows that in

DoxI(w) all worlds in which I work hard this semester are more desirable than maximally similar

worlds in which I don=t work hard this semester. As a result, the inference is expected to be valid,

and (33c) is expected to be true, contrary to what we observe.

The invalid inference illustrates that someone may believe that two propositions p and q are

true in the exact same set of worlds, and at the same time want p without wanting q. Heim=s

semantics cannot capture this fact. As a consequence, I propose to eliminate the reference to the

doxastic alternatives and simply replace it with the set of contextually relevant alternatives.

The proposal made in (32) can then be simplified accordingly, as in (35) along with a slight

modification of the definition of >α,w6:

(35) Semantics of want based on comparison of alternatives

� wantC� g(p)(a)(w) = 1 iff

� q: q � p & q 0 g(C): p >DESα,w q

where >DESα,w is defined as follows

a) For any w, w=, w== 0 W, w= > α,w w== iff w= is more desirable to α in w than w==.

b) For any pφW, qφW, p >DES α,w q iff � w== 0 q � w=0 p such that w=>α,w w==, and it is

not the case that � w= 0 p � w==0 q such that w==>α,w w=.

Error! Main Document Only. In (35), I propose to use a new definition of >DESα,w, adapted from the definition of >better possibility= in Kratzer(1991), since the ordering relation defined in Heim (1992) is not suitable for comparative desirability among propositions. This is so, since Heim=s definition makes a requirement that is too strong. If we were to apply it to propositions we would run into the following problem: if p is more desirable than q, the definition requires that all worlds in p be more desirable than all worlds in q. However, some worlds in p may be really bad worlds for other reasons, and may still not necessarily affect the desirability relation between p and q. Kratzer=s definition of >better possibility= solves this problem.

Page 19: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

18

With the semantics proposed in (35), no inference is expected. The new semantics predicts

that >I teach Tuesdays and Thursdays= is more desirable than its contextually relevant alternatives

(for example >I teach Mondays, Wednesdays and Fridays=). However, from the fact that >I teach

Tuesdays and Thursdays next semester= and >I work hard this semester= are true in the exact same

set of worlds it does not follow that >I want to work hard this semester=. This is so, since in both

cases we are comparing a different set of alternatives. For example, the set of alternatives for >I work

had this semester= may be {>I don=t work this semester=, >I work a little this semester=}. As a

consequence, no inference is expected.

With the semantics proposed here, however, two new problems arise. First, we cannot account

anymore for the fact that the subject=s beliefs do sometimes play a role in determining the truth

conditions of a want-sentence. Take the example in (36).

(36) John doesn=t have to teach at all next semester but he thinks he does and he wants to teach

Tuesdays and Thursdays.

In this sentence, the alternative AJohn doesn=t teach at all next semester@ is provided in the context,

however, it cannot be part of the set of alternatives that is relevant for the comparison. If this were so,

we would not predict the correct truth conditions. Hence, the subject=s beliefs do play a role in

determining which alternatives enter the comparison.

A second problem is that we cannot express the difference between want, wish and be glad

anymore. As we saw before, these predicates precisely differ in terms of whether the subject believes

that the proposition expressed by the complement clause is true or not. As a consequence, I propose to

distinguish these predicates in terms of their definedness conditions.

Below, I adopt a semantics in which the predicate want has a definedness condition which

requires that all contextual alternatives be included in the doxastic alternatives7.

(37) Semantics of want based on comparison of alternatives

� wantC� g(p)(a)(w) is defined iff � q 0 g(C): Doxa(w)1q � ι

7 Further refinements may be necessary. As an anonymous reviewer points out, the predicate want requires that p be a desirable alternative, unlike the predicate prefer. That is, in a context in which Victoria considers all alternatives as highly undesirable it is still possible to say that Victoria prefers p, but not that Victoria wants p.

Page 20: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

19

if defined � wantC� g(p)(a)(w) = 1 iff

� q: q � p & q 0 g(C): p >DESα,w q

I will show that this new proposal still does not predict the practical inference discussed earlier

to be valid. The practical inference is repeated here.

(38) a) I want to teach Tuesdays and Thursdays next semester.

b) I believe that I will teach Tuesdays and Thursdays next semester if and only if I work hard

now.

____________________________________

c) Invalid inference:

� I want to work hard now.

According to (37), from the truth of (38a) it follows that >I teach Tuesdays and Thursdays

next semester= is more desirable to me than its contextual alternatives, for example >I teach

Mondays, Wednesdays and Fridays next semester=. From the truth of (38b) it follows that in DoxI(w)

the worlds in which I teach Tuesdays and Thursdays next semester correspond exactly to those worlds

in which I work hard this semester. From this, however, it does not follow that (38c) is true. (38c)

says that >I work hard now= is more desirable than its contextual alternatives, for instance {>I don=t

work at all=, >I work a little=}. Even if the propositions >I teach Tuesdays and Thursdays next

semester= and >I work hard now= are true in the same set of worlds, their contextual alternatives are

not necessarily the same.

I propose that the predicates wish and be glad will then have slightly different definedness

conditions. The fact that the predicate wish requires that the proposition p should not be included in

the subject=s doxastic alternatives, whereas the predicate be glad requires that the proposition p

necessarily be true in the subject=s doxastic alternatives can now be expressed in their definedness

conditions.

(39) Semantics of wish based on comparison of alternatives

� wishC� g(p)(a)(w) is defined iff p 1 Doxa(w) = ι

If defined � wishC� g(p)(a)(w) = 1 iff

� q: q� p & q 0 g(C): p >DESα,w q

Page 21: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

20

(40) Semantics of be glad based on comparison of alternatives

� be gladC� g(p)(a)(w) is defined iff Doxa(w) φ p

If defined � be gladC� g(p)(a)(w) = 1 iff

� q: q� p & q 0 g(C): p >DESα,w q

The lexical entries provided here are certainly a simplification, given that the precise

definedness conditions of these predicates are a rather complex matter (cf. von Fintel 1992). Since my

main aim is to show that these different predicates share a core semantics, I will not go into further

discussion of the details of these definedness conditions here, but adopt a simplified semantics that is

sufficient for the argumentation developed here.

I will now propose that the semantics based on comparison of contextual alternatives can be

extended to all predicates that select the subjunctive mood in Spanish:

(41) New hypothesis for the subjunctive mood in Spanish

A proposition p that is the complement of the matrix predicate requires the subjunctive mood

iff the matrix predicate introduces an ordering relation between propositions and compares p

to its contextually available alternatives.

To conclude, in this section, I have developed a new hypothesis for the semantics of the

predicates that select the subjunctive mood in Spanish. By revising Heim=s (1992) proposal, I have

developed a semantics of comparison for predicates such as want, be glad and wish. The new

semantics involves comparison of contextual alternatives to the proposition expressed by the

complement clause. In the next section, I discuss how the presented analysis can be extended to all

predicate classes that select the subjunctive mood.

5. The predicate classes that select the subjunctive mood in Spanish

In this section, I will go over all predicate classes that select the subjunctive mood in Spanish

to show how their semantics can be captured by the generalization. While it is impossible to present a

Page 22: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

21

full fledged analysis for every single predicate class here, I will briefly sketch possible ways of

analyzing the different classes under the presented proposal. The exact semantics of causative

predicates will however be left for future research.

5.1. Desire predicates and Emotive Factive Predicates

In the previous section, I have discussed the desire predicates want and wish and emotive

factive predicates such as be glad and be disappointed. The analysis can in principle be extended to

all other predicates in these two classes, but there are two important factors that may vary.

The first factor of variation is the dimension of the scale which may differ from predicate to

predicate. This scale should be contributed directly by the lexical meaning of the predicate. Desire

predicates such as querer (>want=) and esperar (>hope=) contribute an ordering relation of

desirability. For the class of emotive factive predicates there is more variation in terms of what

dimension is contributed. Many emotive factive predicates contribute a relation of desirability, such

as alegrarse (>be glad=) and estar contento (>be happy=), or a reverse relation of desirability, such

as lamentarse (>regret=), or enfadarse (>be upset=). However, a number of other emotive factive

predicates cannot be based on the notion of desirability such as es interesante (>it is interesting=), es

divertido (>it is amusing=), es útil (>it is useful=), es fascinante (>it is fascinating=), etc. I will

assume that the ordering relation is contributed by the lexical meaning of each predicate. Parallel to

the scalar approaches to the semantics of gradable adjectives, I will propose that gradable predicates

directly contribute the dimension of the scale involved.

The second factor of variation is the ranking of p among the alternatives. The proposal

developed here leaves room for expressing that p may be the best, the worst or just a good alternative.

While I have argued here that these predicates require p to be the best (or highest ranked) among the

contextual alternatives, we will see in section 6.2.3 that not all predicates require that p be the best

alternative, but rather that p be a good alternative (such as, for example, alegrarse >be glad= or

lamentarse >be disappointed=).

5.2 Modals and predicates expressing likelihood and doubt

Page 23: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

22

Modal predicates, which select the subjunctive mood in Spanish, can be captured by the

generalization quite straightforwardly. I will illustrate this here with the predicate es necesario >be

necessary=. Krasikova (2007) argues that have to-like modals such as have to, need, be required, be

necessary etc. are associated with the likelihood scale/scale of comparative possibility when they

express teleological modality.8 Parallel to Krasikova=s (2007) analysis, I will define the lexical entry

for the predicate be necessary as follows:

(42) Semantics of be necessary based on comparison of alternatives

� be necessaryC� g(p)(w) = 1 iff � q: q� p & q 0 g(C): p >LIKELYw q

where >LIKELYw is defined as follows:

a) For any w, w=, w== 0 W, w= > w w== iff w= is closer to w than w==.

b) For any pφW, qφW, p >LIKELYw q iff � w== 0 q � w=0 p such that w=>αw w==, and it

is not the case that � w= 0 p � w==0 q such that w==>,w w=.

The likelihood scale as defined here is based on comparative similarity (closeness to the actual world,

cf. Lewis1986). Other predicates from this class such as es probable (>it is likely=), es posible (>it is

possible=) and dudar (>doubt=) can also be analyzed as contributing the scale of likelihood. There

may again be variation concerning the ranking of p among the contextual alternatives. For example, in

the case of es posible (>it is possible=), the requirement will be that p is not the best alternative.

Here as well, there will be variation in the kind of scale contributed by the predicate: when

modals express other kinds of modalities (such as deontic or bouletic modalities), the scale

contributed is a different one (such as ranking based on the closeness to the ideal or law, cf. Lewis

1986).

8 She argues this on the basis of the fact that their ability to induce the more than minimum reading in comparatives correlates to their ability to appear in sufficiency modal constructions (cf. Von Fintel & Iatridou 2007).

Page 24: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

23

Sloman (1970) in fact already proposes an analysis equivalent to the one presented here for

sentences containing the predicate ought.9 In order to capture their various possible interpretations

(modal can, must and directive interpretation), he develops an analysis in which alternatives are

compared with respect to a contextually determined ordering relation. He proposes that the

interpretation of It ought to be the case that p should be >p is, or is a necessary condition for the best,

relative to the basis B, of the possibilities in the class Z.= (Sloman 1970, p. 389). B here stands for

basis of comparison (dimension of the ordering relation), which is contextually given when not

specified explicitly. Z stands for the comparison class. Sloman claims that possible different meanings

of ought fall out of differences in basis of comparison as well as differences in comparison class.

5.3. Directive predicates

Portner(2004,2007) proposes that imperative sentences are used to contribute to the discourse

component that he labels the To-do List, more precisely the addressee=s To-do List. A To-do List is a

set of propositions that the participant intends to make true. In short, imperative sentences are used to

make requirements, where the essential function of a requirement is to add a proposition to

someone=s To-Do List. Just as declarative sentences are used to make assertions and contribute to the

common ground, in Portner (2004,2007), imperatives are used to make requirements and contribute to

the addressee=s To-Do List. Another important feature of his analysis is that the To-Do List is

considered to be a subset of the ordering source (cf. Kratzer 1981) and thus contributes to imposing an

ordering on the common ground.

Turning now to directive predicates such as mandar (>order=), ordenar (>order=), pedir

(>ask=), we can show that, by adopting Portner=s main ideas, these can be accommodated in the

proposal developed here. I propose that they make reference to the To-Do List and that the relevant

set of propositions are those propositions that are part of (or a subset of) the set of contextual

alternatives. The ordering relation is introduced by the predicate. For deontic predicates, such as to

order, I propose the following semantic definition:

(43) Semantics of to order based on comparison of alternatives

9 I thank Kai von Fintel for pointing this out to me.

Page 25: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

24

� orderC� g(p)(x)(w) = 1 iff x requires that

� q: q� p & q 0 g(C) & q 0 T(α) : p >DEONTICw q

where T(α) is the set of propositions (>To-Do List=) assigned to a

participant α in the conversation

The ordering relation contributed by the predicate may vary. In Portner(2007), the ordering imposed

may vary depending on what is expressed by the imperative: when the imperative expresses an order,

it will be a deontic ordering source, when it expresses an invitation, it will express a bouletic ordering

source, when it expresses a suggestion, it will express a teleological ordering source.

Notice that under this proposal the semantics of directives is slightly different from the other

predicate classes that select the subjunctive mood: the comparative meaning component is embedded

more deeply within the meaning of the predicate.

5.4 Causative predicates

In the case of causatives such as hacer (>make=) and lograr (>achieve=), I propose that the

relevant comparison relation is one of comparative similarity. Causatives are usually analyzed with

the semantics of counterfactual conditionals. In Lewis (1973), it is proposed that, in a counterfactual,

all worlds in which the antecedent is true are ordered with respect to their similarity to the actual

world. For a causative predicate this means that, all worlds in which the embedded proposition is true

will be compared to the actual world with respect to their similarity. This ordering relation may also

be defined for propositions (cf Lewis 1986) as was done for modal predicates in section 5.2. Hence,

the predicate cause can be defined as expressing that p is the closest to the actual world among the set

of contextual alternatives.

I suggest that predicates such as hacer (>make=) and lograr (>achieve=) contain the

predicate cause as part of their meaning. Hence, similarly to directive predicates, the relevant

comparison will be embedded more deeply within the meaning of the predicate. Even though I will

not go into the details of a semantics of causatives here, we can assume that they share with the other

predicates classes the fact that they contribute an ordering relation and compare p its contextual

alternatives.

Page 26: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

25

6. Comparing the proposal to other approaches

In this section, I compare my proposal to other existing proposals on the semantics of

propositional attitude predicates.

Propositional attitude predicates have received a lot of interest in the semantic and

philosophical literature independently of the issues of mood selection. Since Hintikka (1962, 1969),

predicates such as believe, know and want have commonly been analyzed with a semantics of possible

worlds, more specifically with a semantics of modal necessity: α believes/knows/wants φ is true in w

iff φ is true in all the worlds that are compatible with α=s beliefs/knowledge/desires in w. The

question then is to what extent a Hintikka-style semantics could be extended to all kinds of

propositional attitudes. In a similar vein, recent approaches have proposed that propositional attitudes

should be modeled after the semantics of modal expressions involving a semantics of necessity and

possibility (cf., for example Kiefer 1987, von Fintel 1999, Giorgi and Piannesi 1997).

In this section, I explicitly compare my proposal to these approaches. As we have already seen

before, a Hintikka-style semantics has its problems when extended to desire predicates. I will show

here that there are a number of characteristics of the predicates that select the subjunctive mood that

are difficult to account for in this type of approach. We will see that, on the contrary, these

characteristics follow straightforwardly from the proposal that I have adopted here.

I now turn to making explicit how the meaning common to the predicates that select the

subjunctive mood can be expressed with a semantics of modal necessity or modal possibility,

following von Fintel(1999). Since he makes use of the semantics proposed in Kratzer (1997, 1981,

1999) to capture the meaning properties of predicates such as want, wish, be glad and be sorry, I first

present a brief overview of Kratzer=s theory of modality.

6.1 A semantics of modal necessity/possibility

Kratzer (1977, 1981, 1991) develops a semantics in which modal expressions receive

meanings that are dependent on two contextual parameters, a modal base and an ordering source.

These two parameters are determined by two conversational backgrounds.

Page 27: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

26

Kratzer points out that there are many different kinds of conversational backgrounds. A

conversational background is the kind of entity denoted by expressions such as what the law provides,

what we know, what is normal, what is rational, what is desirable, etc. What the law provides in a

world is a set of propositions p such that the law provides that p in that world. The denotation of what

the law provides is then the function that assigns to every possible world this set of propositions p.

More generally, a conversational background is a function f which assigns sets of propositions to

possible worlds.

The modal base is defined as a set of worlds determined by a conversational background f.

The set of worlds in which all propositions of f(w) are true constitutes the modal base in w. The

modal base thus determines the set of worlds accessible from each world.

The ordering source is a second conversational background g which assigns to every possible

world a set of propositions. Ordering sources represent ideals, given that they can induce an ordering

on the modal base (the worlds in the modal base may be closer or further away from what the law

provides, what is desirable, what is normal, etc.).

More generally, a set of propositions A can induce an ordering #A on a set of worlds W in the

following way (following Lewis 1981).

(44) The ordering #A:

� w , w= 0 W: w #A w= iff {p: p0 A and w=0 p} φ {p: p0 A and w0 p}

>A world w is at least as close to the ideal represented by A as a world w= iff all propositions

of A which are true in w= are true in w as well.=

Thus, in (44), worlds are ordered with the help of an unordered set of propositions. A world w is at

least as close to the ideal represented by A as a world w= iff it makes at least as many propositions

true as w= does.

Sentences containing modals are then evaluated with respect to an ordered set of worlds. The

ordering source is usually not expressed explicitly in the sentence but has to be recovered from the

context. Consider the following example in (45).

(45) Sofía should bring a chocolate cake.

Page 28: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

27

In the context of the scenario discussed previously, in section 4.1, the modal base of this sentence is

formed by the set of worlds that constitute Victoria=s beliefs. The ordering source is bouletic and

corresponds to the set of propositions determined by Victoria=s desires. This set of propositions

induces an ordering on the set of the modal base. The modal force of the modal should is necessity.

The meaning of (45) can then be paraphrased as in (46).

(46) In view of what Victoria desires, it is necessary for Sofía to bring a chocolate cake.

We now turn to the implementation of a semantics based on modal necessity for predicates

that select the subjunctive mood.

Giorgi and Pianesi (1997) propose that the contexts in which the subjunctive mood appear can

be characterized with the semantics that Kratzer proposes for modal expressions. The generalization

they propose is that in certain Romance languages such as Spanish and French, the subjunctive mood

is selected when the context requires the interaction between a modal base and a non-null ordering

source. This generalization still does not tell us what exactly the semantics should be for the

predicates that select the subjunctive mood. Giorgi and Pianesi do not explicitly formalize a proposal

for the semantics of these predicates, but only illustrate the kind of semantics they want to use with

the modal must. I will thus follow here instead von Fintel (1999), who proposes to adopt a semantics

of modal necessity for propositional attitude predicates such as want, wish, be glad and be sorry. He

defines the following concepts.

(47) (i) The >modal base function= f is a function from pairs of an individual and a world to a set

of worlds.

(ii) The >ordering source function= is a function from pairs of an individual and a world to a

set of propositions (in the case of want to a set of propositions forming the subject=s

preferences).

(von Fintel 1999, p.115)

Here, the subject=s preferences form an unordered set of propositions that induce an ordering on the

modal base. The best worlds are those that make most propositions true. This is stated in the

following definition.

Page 29: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

28

(48) For any set of propositions P, we define a strict partial order <P:

� w=,w==: (w= <P w== iff � p0 P (w== 0 p 6 w=0p) & � p 0 P (w=0 p & w==⌠p))

(Von Fintel 1999, p. 115)

Von Fintel proposes to use the selection function maxP that selects the best worlds in any set X with

respect to a partial order <P, as defined in (49).

(49) For a given strict partial order <P on worlds, define the selection function maxP that selects the

set of <P-best worlds from any set X:

� x φ W: maxP(X) = {w 0 X: 5� w=0 X : w= <P w}

(von Fintel 1999, p.116)

The semantics of the verb want can then be stated as in (50), as proposed in von Fintel (1999).

The proposition is here evaluated in those worlds in the modal base f(α,w) that maximally satisfy the

preferences given by the ordering source g(α,w). Thus, the ordering source is used to induce an

ordering on the worlds in the modal base.

(50) Semantics of modal necessity for want

� want� f,g (p)(α)(w) = true iff � w= 0 maxg(α,w) (f(α,w)) : w= 0 p.

>Among the worlds f(α,w), the ones that maximally correspond to α=s preferences in w are

all p-worlds= (von Fintel 1999, p.115)

Von Fintel proposes that the verb want requires the modal base f to be formed by the worlds

that are compatible with the subject=s beliefs. The ordering source g is formed by the set of the

subject=s desires. In other words, in (50), α wants φ is true in w iff among the worlds compatible

with α=s beliefs, the ones that maximally correspond to α=s desires in w are all φ-worlds.

Thus, this semantics is identical to the semantics of the predicate should. The only difference

is that, in the case of the modal should the ordering source is contextually determined, while in the

lexical entry provided here for want the ordering source is explicitly introduced by the verb.

Page 30: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

29

Such a semantics can easily be extended to the other propositional attitude predicates that

select the subjunctive mood in Spanish. There are two types of parameters of variation that we expect.

First, the modal base should differ from predicate to predicate: predicates such as wish and be glad

require a modal base formed by the set of revised doxastic alternatives. Second, the ordering source

also varies from predicate to predicate. For example, for predicates such as want and wish the

ordering is determined by the desires of the subject, while for predicates such as be surprised and

doubt the ordering is determined by what the subject considers likely.

Von Fintel=s proposal is modeled after the semantics of modals that express necessity, such as

must and should. In (50), it is required that the proposition expressed by the complement clause be

necessarily true in all the worlds that maximally correspond to α=s desires (the worlds selected by the

function maxP). Let us now consider the option that some of the predicates under discussion may also

be modeled after the semantics of modals that express possibility, such as may and could.

Kiefer (1987) proposes that the semantics of different kinds of propositional attitudes involves

both modal necessity and modal possibility. One may then adopt the view that different propositional

attitude predicates may encode different kinds of modal strength.

To adopt modal possibility for the semantics of a predicate, only a few simple modifications

from the previous proposal are necessary. Following Kratzer (1991), a proposition p is a possibility in

a world w with respect to a modal base f and an ordering source g iff 5p is not a necessity in w with

respect to f and g. (Kratzer 1991, p. 644). Hence, instead of requiring that the proposition p be true in

all worlds selected by the max-function (the worlds that maximally correspond to the subject=s

preferences), we require that there is a world among those selected by the max-function such that p is

true in that world.

Page 31: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

30

I propose to illustrate this kind of semantics with the predicate be disappointed. For a

predicate such as be disappointed, there are indeed situations in which α is disappointed that p in w is

true even if p is not true in all worlds that maximally correspond to what α considers undesirable in w,

as illustrated previously with example (31). A semantics of necessity is thus not appropriate for this

predicate: AVictoria is disappointed that Sofía brought an apple pie@ can be considered true in a

scenario where ASofia brought an apple pie@ is not true in all worlds that maximally correspond to

what Victoria considers undesirable. One may then consider to adopt a semantics of possibility, as

presented in the lexical entry below.

(51) Semantics of modal possibility for be disappointed

� be disappointed� f,g (p)(α)(w) = True iff � w= 0 maxg(α,w) (f(α,w)) : w= 0 p.

In the case of the predicate be disappointed, the ordering source g is determined by what is

considered undesirable by α in w. The modal base f is the set of worlds compatible with α=s revised

beliefs. (51) then says that α is disappointed that p in w is true iff among the worlds f(α,w) compatible

with α=s revised beliefs, there is a world w= in the set of worlds that maximally correspond to what α

considers undesirable in w such that p is true in that world w=.

To conclude, in this section I have presented a semantics for the predicates that select the

subjunctive mood based on modal necessity and modal possibility that is identical to the semantics

commonly adopted for the modals must and can. In the following, I investigate a few characteristics

of the predicates that select the subjunctive mood in Spanish that present difficulties to such an

approach. I will argue that my proposal based on comparison of contextual alternative propositions

can accommodate these characteristics in a more straightforward way.

Page 32: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

31

6.2 Comparing the predictions

In this section, I argue that there are some empirical differences between a semantics for the

predicates selecting the subjunctive mood that is modeled after modal necessity/possibility and the

semantics of comparison that I developed in section 4. In the following, I present several facts related

to practical inferences, possible rankings of the alternatives, lack of entailment relations, and

association with focus phenomena. I discuss the predictions of the different proposals concerning

these phenomena. We will see that these phenomena can be straightforwardly accommodated within

the semantics of comparison developed here.

6.2.1 Practical Inferences

With the help of practical inferences (Von Wright (1963)), I will argue that a semantics of

modal necessity or possibility cannot straightforwardly capture an important property of the predicates

that select the subjunctive mood.

Below, I present an example that shows that, in the conclusion of certain practical

inferences, we cannot replace the modal verb (which expresses necessity) with the predicate want.

Under the assumption that both predicates are analyzed with a semantics of modal necessity (i.e. that

they essentially have the same semantics), we however expect that this should be possible. From the

two premisses a) and b) we can infer c). Yet, we cannot infer d).

(52) a) Marcela wants to go to the picnic.

b) Marcela believes that she can only go to the picnic if she works extra hours.

_________________________________

c) � Marcela should work extra hours.

d) Invalid inference:

� Marcela wants to work extra hours.

I now show that under the assumption that want receives a semantics of modal necessity, we

predict that d) should be a valid inference, just like c). I repeat here von Fintel=s proposal for the

semantics of want discussed earlier.

Page 33: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

32

(53) Semantics of modal necessity for want

� want� f,g (p)(α)(w) = True iff � w= 0 maxg(α,w) (f(α,w)) : w= 0 p.

By using the semantics for want as stated in (53), we predict the following for the example

(52). From a) it follows that among the worlds compatible with Marcela=s beliefs, the ones that

maximally correspond to her desires in w are all worlds in which she goes to the picnic. From b) it

follows that Marcela believes that all worlds in which she goes to the picnic are worlds in which she

works extra hours. We can thus infer that among the worlds compatible with Marcela=s beliefs the

ones that maximally correspond to her desires in w are all worlds in which she works extra hours, and

we expect d) to be true. (53) thus predicts that d) should be a possible inference from a) and b),

contrary to what is observed.

Among the predicates that select the subjunctive mood, there are a number of predicates that

do not allow for such practical inferences, such are preferir (prefer), temer (>fear=), esperar

(>hope=), alegrarse (>be glad=), lamentarse (>regret=), sugerir (>suggest=), recomendar

(>advise=), sorprenderse (>be surprised=) and dudar (>doubt=).

To conclude, practical inferences provide an argument against a semantics of modal necessity.

To the contrary, a semantics based on comparison of contextual alternatives captures the phenomenon

in a straightforward way: in my proposal there is no expectation that the inference should also hold for

the predicate want.

6.2.2 Lack of entailment relations

An interesting characteristic of the predicates under discussion is that entailment relations

between propositions do not survive when these propositions are embedded under the predicates, as

has been previously observed in Katz (1991), Kadmon and Landman (1993), Lee & Horn (1994),

Linebarger (1987) von Fintel (1999), and others. Thus, when a proposition p entails a proposition q,

this does not necessarily have the consequences that α is glad that p entails that α is glad that q.

The fact that entailment relations between propositions do not survive in this context is

problematic for a semantics based on modal necessity. This can be shown with an example discussed

in Kadmon & Landman (1993) and von Fintel (1999).

Page 34: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

33

(54) He bought a Honda.

(55) He bought a car.

(56) I am glad he bought a Honda.

(57) I am glad he bought a car.

The proposition in (54) entails the proposition in (55), given that all the worlds in which he

bought a Honda are worlds in which he bought a car. Nevertheless, when these propositions are

embedded under the predicate be glad, we do not find an entailment relation: the proposition in (56)

does not entail the proposition in (57). This is so, since all the worlds in which I am glad that he

bought a Honda are not necessarily worlds in which I am glad that he bought a car. The sentence in

(56) can very well be true in a situation in which I am not glad at all that he bought a car. I may in

fact be upset about it and think that for environmental reasons it would have been much better for him

to buy a bike. But given that he has bought a car, I am glad that he bought a Honda rather than another

car. Maybe the Honda is not as polluting a choice as the other options would have been.

To show that a semantics of modal necessity cannot capture this lack of entailment relations, I

repeat here the corresponding lexical entry for the predicate be glad.

(58) Semantics of modal necessity for be glad

� be glad� f,g (p)(α)(w) = True iff � w= 0 maxg(α,w) (f(α,w)) : w= 0 p.

In the lexical entry for be glad, f stands for a modal base that contains all the worlds that are

compatible with the subject=s revised beliefs and g stands for an ordering source that is determined

by the subject=s desires. For the sentence pair in (56) and (57) then the following holds. If the

sentence in (56) is true, we predict that among the worlds compatible with my revised beliefs, the

ones that maximally correspond to my preferences in w are all worlds in which he bought a Honda.

All the worlds in which he bought a Honda are also worlds in which he bought a car. Hence, we can

conclude that among the worlds compatible with my revised beliefs, the ones that maximally

correspond to my preferences in w are all worlds in which he bought a car. Thus, with the semantics

in (58), whenever the sentence in (56) is true, the sentence in (57) is true as well. As a consequence, a

semantics of modal necessity cannot capture the lack of entailment relations.

Page 35: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

34

The problematic aspect of a semantics based on modal necessity is that it requires to verify

whether p is true in all the worlds that best fit α=s desires. If in all those worlds it is true that he

bought a Honda, automatically it is also true that in all those worlds he bought a car. However, we

have seen that the entailment does not necessarily hold: if I am glad that he bought a Honda it does

not necessarily hold that I am also glad that he bought a car.

To remedy this problem, Kadmon and Landman (1993) suggest that for predicates such as be

glad there is another contextually interpreted modal parameter involved, a so-called perspective. The

perspective enters into the semantics of these predicates and affects the truth conditions of sentences

containing it. This would explain why it is possible for me to be glad that he bought a Honda (because

a Honda is a better choice than other cars), and at the same time not be glad that he bought a Honda

(because I have something against buying cars), without contradicting myself. Kadmon and Landman

(1993) claim that entailment relations are maintained unless the perspective changes. However, they

do not present an explicit proposal as to how this perspective is to be incorporated into a semantics of

predicates such as be glad. We will see that the proposal that I have developed here provides us with

the means to make this notion more explicit. Under my proposal, a change in perspective simply

corresponds to a change in the set of alternative propositions.

Von Fintel (1999) suggests that a semantics of modal necessity can still be maintained. He

proposes that, for the two examples (56) and (57), there is a shift in which worlds are being

considered, because they assume different contexts. For the example (56), only worlds in which he

bought a car are compared. For different sentences, the modal base then would not always be the

same, rather it would be contextually determined. Under this assumption, we do not expect there to be

an entailment relation between the two sentences. He thus proposes that the phenomenon under

discussion is explained by the fact that there may be a contextually signaled narrowing of the modal

base relevant for the interpretation of the predicate. A semantics of modal necessity can thus be

amended to capture the fact if we allow the modal base to change with the context.

One of my main goals has exactly been to show this last point, namely, that for different

examples, different contextual alternatives are relevant. At the core of my proposal is the idea that

contextual alternatives are an important ingredient of the semantics of these predicates. By employing

a semantics of comparison of contextual alternatives for the predicate be glad we do not expect that

an entailment relation should hold between the two examples (59) and (60), repeated from before.

Page 36: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

35

(59) I am glad he bought a Honda.

(60) I am glad he bought a car.

In my proposal, no entailment relation is expected, since the set of contextual alternatives

differs for both examples. In the example in (59), the set of alternatives could be {He bought a Honda,

He bought a Toyota, He bought a Mercedes}, while in the example in (60), this set could be {He

bought a car, He bought a bike, He didn=t buy anything}. Thus, we do not expect that (59) entails

(60).

Kadmon and Landman=s notion of perspective can then be characterized with the help of the

set of alternatives. A change in perspective corresponds to a change of the set of alternatives.

Similarly, a change in the modal base in von Fintel=s account, corresponds to a change in the set of

alternatives.

6.2.3 Possible rankings of the alternatives

Predicates such as be glad, be disappointed and regret illustrate that p is not always

necessarily the best/worst alternative. In certain contexts, α is glad that p is true in w even if p is not

true in the worlds that best match α=s desires. We can illustrate this again with the previous scenario

that has more than two alternatives. I repeat the schematic figure below.

(61) + desirable ┬ chocolate cake ┬ - likely (according to Victoria)

│ │ │ │ │ │ │ apple pie │ │ │

! desirable ┴ ice cream ┴ + likely (according to Victoria)

Imagine, that Sofía in the end brought an apple pie. Then, the sentence in (62) can be true in this

scenario:

(62) Victoria is glad that Sofía brought an apple pie.

Page 37: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

36

Victoria may be glad that Sofia at least didn=t bring ice cream, which she would have hated. Thus, the

sentence in (62) is true in a scenario in which p is not the best alternative. It would have been much

better for Victoria if Sofía had brought a chocolate cake.

By employing a semantics of modal necessity, we however predict that this sentence should be

false in this scenario. A semantics of modal necessity for the predicate be glad is given in (63).

(63) Semantics of modal necessity for be glad

� be glad� f,g (p)(α)(w) = true iff � w= 0 maxg(α,w) (f(α,w)) : w= 0 p.

The lexical entry of be glad in (63) predicts that the example (62) should be false in this

scenario. It requires that among the worlds compatible with Victoria=s revised beliefs (the modal base

f), the ones that maximally correspond to Victoria=s preferences in w are all worlds in which Sofía

brings an apple pie. But, in fact, Victoria would have preferred it if Sofía had brought a chocolate

cake. Thus, in none of the worlds that best match Victoria=s preferences it is the case that she brings

an apple pie. Hence, a semantics of modal necessity makes the wrong prediction for predicates such as

be glad.

Let us now see whether a semantics of modal possibility could better capture the truth

conditions of the predicate be glad. The lexical entry of the predicate be glad is then as in (64).

(64) Semantics of modal possibility for be glad

� be glad� f,g (p)(α)(w) = true iff � w= 0 maxg(α,w) (f(α,w) : w= 0 p).

This semantics of the predicate be glad does not make the correct predictions for the above

scenario either. The meaning of be glad expressed in (64) predicts that the example (62) should be

false in the given scenario. The lexical entry requires that there is a world among the worlds that best

match Victoria=s desires such that Sofía brings an apple pie in that world. Nevertheless, we already

saw before that this is false: since Victoria prefers the chocolate cake, all worlds that maximally

correspond to her preferences are worlds in which Sofía doesn=t bring an apple pie, but rather a

chocolate cake.

Hence, we have seen that neither modal necessity nor modal possibility can capture the fact

that, for certain predicates, p may not necessarily be the best alternative. The problem with this kind

Page 38: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

37

of semantics is that we only consider worlds that best match the subject=s desires. But these may

sometimes in fact be irrelevant.

To the contrary, the proposal that I have developed so far can capture the truth conditions of a

predicate such as be glad, because it allows to express that p is not necessarily the best alternative.

The predicates under discussion seem to vary with respect to this issue. Some predicates, such as

prefer, for example, require p to be ranked highest among the alternatives, whereas other predicates

such as be glad and regret don=t. This information should then be encoded in the lexical entry of

these predicates. The lexical entry for be glad could be formalized as in (65).

(65) Semantics based on comparison of alternatives for be glad

� be gladC� g(p)(a)(w) = 1 iff � q: q � p & q 0 g(C): p > Desa,w q

This lexical entry for the predicate be glad does not require that p be the best alternative, but rather

that there be an alternative q such that p is more desirable than q. In this scenario, we predict the

sentence Victoria is glad that Sofía brought the apple pie to come out as true: there is an alternative

(>Sofía brings ice cream=) such that the alternative >Sofía brings an apple pie= is more desirable.

To conclude, we have seen that a semantics based on necessity or possibility cannot capture

the fact that certain predicates such as be glad do not require the proposition expressed by the

complement clause to be ranked highest. A semantics based on comparison of contextual alternatives

leaves room for variation in this domain. Different kinds of constraints on how the proposition p

stands with respect to the other alternatives can be implemented.

In Kratzer (1991), next to modal possibility and necessity, other modal strengths are also

defined, among which the modal strength of at least as good a possibility and better possibility. Let

me now show in what respect my proposal differs from Kratzer=s proposal on comparative

possibility, which is based on the interaction of a modal base with an ordering source:

(66) Definition 9 (Kratzer 1991:p644)

A proposition p is at least as good a possibility as a proposition q in a world w with respect

to a modal base f and an ordering source g iff for all u such that u 0 1 f(w) and u 0 q there is a

v 0 1 f(w) such that v#g(w) u and v 0 p.

Page 39: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

38

(67) Definition 10 (Kratzer 1991: p.644)

A proposition p is a better possibility than a proposition q in a world w with respect to a

modal base f and an ordering source g iff p is at least as good a possibility as q and q is not at

least as good a possibility as p in w with respect to f and g.

The notion of better possibility is defined here for propositions p and q with respect to a modal base f

and an ordering source g. The ordering source corresponds to an unordered set of propositions that

induces an ordering on the relevant set of worlds in the modal base. Crucially, in this definition, the

propositions p and q to be compared are not part of the set of propositions that forms the ordering

source. Hence, we could not assume, as was previously done in von Fintel=s proposal for the

predicate want, that the ordering source contains those propositions that correspond to the subject=s

preferences (since, at least in the case of the predicate want, the proposition p and q to be compared

are presumably propositions that express the subject=s desires).

In my proposal, the set of contextual alternative propositions is not used to induce the

ordering. Rather, the different propositions expressing the desires of Victoria are ranked with respect

to an ordering relation or scale. Thus, the crucial difference between the two approaches is that in one

case the propositions that express the desires are unordered while they are ranked with respect to a

scale in the other.

As pointed out to me by Barbara Partee, in the approach that uses ordering sources, one may

express ranked desires by using a set of disjunctions as the relevant ordering source. For our scenario,

we would need the set {>Sofía brings a chocolate cake=, >Sofía brings a chocolate cake or apple

pie=, >Sofía brings a chocolate cake or apple pie or ice cream=}. Given such an ordering source, the

best worlds are then the worlds in which Sofía brings the chocolate cake: these are the only worlds

that make all three propositions true. If it seems plausible to use ordering sources of this kind, these

two approaches may turn out to be equivalent.

In the following section, however, I will show that the proposal developed here has two

advantages. Given that predicates are analyzed parallel to focus sensitive operators such as only, we

predict these predicates to be focus sensitive. In section 7.1, I show that this prediction is born out.

The Kratzer-style approach, which is based on the interaction of a modal base with an ordering

source, however, does not make this prediction. In section 7.2.1, I argue that the subjunctive mood

morpheme makes a particular semantic contribution, namely that it evaluates the contextual

Page 40: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

39

alternatives for the matrix predicate. In the Kratzer-style semantics, there does not seem to be room

for such a semantic contribution: the subjunctive mood morpheme would simply have to make a

vacuous semantic contribution. Hence, the proposal developed here has the advantage of providing a

first step towards a better understanding of the question why subjunctive verb forms are obligatory

under the predicate classes discussed here.

7. Mood and Focus

In this section, I turn to investigating an important consequence of my proposal. Given the

analysis presented here, we expect the predicates that select the subjunctive mood to be focus

sensitive. The focus sensitivity of these predicates follows directly from the fact that they are analyzed

analogous to other focus sensitive operators such as only. We thus expect the meaning of these

predicates to be affected by a focused constituent in the embedded clause.

7.1. Focus sensitive predicates

As already pointed out in Dretske (1972,1975), focused phrases embedded under certain

propositional attitude predicates give rise to meaning differences. In the context of the previous picnic

scenario, the sentence in (68) is felicitous, while the sentence in (69) is not (words in capital are

focused).

(68) Victoria wants Sofia to bring A CHOCOLATE CAKE.

(69) Victoria wants SOFIA to bring a chocolate cake.

The proposal developed here can provide a rather straightforward analysis of the meaning

difference between examples (68) and (69). This theory makes explicit that for predicates such as

want an analogy to focus sensitive operators such as only is expected. Both want and only make

reference to a domain of quantification C of contextually determined alternatives, which following.

Rooth (1992) is constrained by focus.

In fact, Rooth (1985,1992) shows that focus has a truth conditional effect in the context of the

adverb only. He presents the following example: in a context in which Mary introduced Bill and Tom

Page 41: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

40

to Sue and there were no other introductions, (70) is true, but (71) is false. These two sentences only

differ in terms of what constituent is focused (marked in capital letters).

(70) Mary only introduced Bill to SUE.

(71) Mary only introduced BILL to Sue.

For the predicates discussed here, we thus also predict differences in focus structure in the

embedded clause to have a truth conditional effect. In this section, my goal is to show that, while

predicates that select the subjunctive mood do show this effect, predicates that select the indicative

mood do not.

We begin with the class of desire predicates. I illustrate their behavior with the predicate want

and use some examples similar to the one discussed in Heim(1992). Consider the following context:

(72) In the linguistics department, at the faculty meeting, the teaching schedules of the different

faculty members for the upcoming semester are discussed. There is only one syntactician in

the department (John), one phonologist (Lisa), and two semanticists (Lara and Frank). John

can only teach syntax. Lara can teach syntax and semantics. There is some controversy on

which days John should teach his syntax classes. There are two options: he may teach syntax

on Tuesdays and Thursdays, or he may teach syntax on Mo, We & Fri. Lisa=s preferences are

the following: she would prefer it if Lara would teach syntax rather than John. But given that

John has to teach syntax, she prefers it if he teaches on Tuesdays and Thursdays rather than on

Mo, We & Fri (because she wants the teaching slot on Mo, We & Fri for her own phonology

class, which cannot conflict with the syntax class).

In this scenario, consider the following utterances:

(73) Lisa wants John to teach syntax ON TUESDAYS AND THURSDAYS.

(74) Lisa wants JOHN to teach syntax on Tuesdays and Thursdays.

Page 42: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

41

In the described scenario, the utterance in (73) is true. However, the utterance in (74) cannot

be true (since Lisa would in fact prefer it if Lara would teach syntax, not John). The only difference

between these two utterances is that a different constituent is focused in the embedded clause.

We can thus conclude that, in the presence of the predicate want, the focus structure of the

embedded clause has a truth conditional effect. The same can be shown to hold for other predicates

that select the subjunctive mood in Spanish. For the class of emotive factive predicates, I illustrate

this with the predicate be glad.

In the context described above, assume that, at the end of the faculty meeting, it is decided that

John is indeed going to teach syntax on Tuesdays and Thursdays. Consider now the following

utterances.

(75) Lisa is glad that John teaches syntax ON TUESDAYS AND THURSDAYS.

(76) Lisa is glad that JOHN teaches syntax on Tuesdays and Thursdays.

Here again, (75) can be true in the described scenario, but not (76) (for the same reasons as before).

The predicate be glad can thus be considered to be focus sensitive.

Boer(1978) illustrates that this same kind of focus sensitivity also appears in conditional

sentences. He presents an example introduced by Dretske(1972) with the following scenario: Ted=s

father left a clause in his will stipulating that Ted can only receive his inheritance if he is married by a

certain date. In this context (77) is true, but (78) is false:

(77) If Ted hadn=t MARRIED Alice, he would have lost his inheritance.

(78) If Ted hadn=t married ALICE, he would have lost his inheritance.

Similarly, the causative predicate cause and the directive predicate demand10, which in Spanish select

the subjunctive mood, show focus sensitivity. Modeling our examples after the conditional sentences,

in the same context, the examples (79) and (81) are true, while (80) and (82) are false:

(79) His father caused Ted to MARRY Alice.

(80) His father caused Ted to marry ALICE.

10 See also Dretske(1975), p.415, for an example which illustrates that directive predicates such as >advise= are focus sensitive.

Page 43: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

42

(81) His father demanded that Ted MARRY Alice.

(82) His father demanded that Ted marry ALICE.

Notice that a modal predicate such as be necessary also displays this pattern: in the same context, (83)

is true while (84) is false :

(83) In order to receive his inheritance, it was necessary that Ted MARRY Alice.

(84) In order to receive his inheritance, it was necessary that Ted marry ALICE.

We have thus seen examples for each predicate class that selects the subjunctive mood (desire

predicates, emotive factives, modals, directives and causatives) that show that the matrix predicate is

sensitive to the focus-structure of the embedded clause.

In contrast, consider now some examples containing predicates that select the indicative mood

in Spanish. The following examples contain the epistemic predicate know.

(85) Lisa knows that John teaches syntax ON TUESDAYS AND THURSDAYS.

(86) Lisa knows that JOHN teaches syntax on Tuesdays and Thursdays.

Contrary to the previous examples, here the matrix predicate does not seem to be sensitive to the

focus structure of the embedded clause. These examples are both true under the same circumstances:

all contexts that make one of them true make the other one true as well. The fact that the predicate

know is not focus sensitive can best be illustrated with a dialogue. If speaker A says: ALisa knows that

John teaches syntax ON TUESDAYS AND THURSDAYS.@, speaker B cannot reply ANo, that=s not

true. Lisa knows that JOHN teaches syntax on Tuesdays and Thursdays.@ without contradicting

himself. Notice that this is different for the predicate want. If speaker A says: ALisa wants John to

teach syntax ON TUESDAYS AND THURSDAYS.@, speaker B can than naturally reply ANo ,

that=s not true. Lisa wants JOHN to teach syntax on Tuesdays and Thursdays.@ without uttering a

contradiction11.

11 For some speakers, a more explicit context is necessary to make this a natural dialogue. For example speaker B could naturally reply: "well, that's not really true, as she doesn't mind which day these classes take place, as long as

Page 44: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

43

Other predicates that select the indicative mood, such as predicates of communication are not

focus sensitive either, as can be illustrated with the predicate say:

(87) Lisa said that John teaches syntax ON TUESDAYS AND THURSDAYS.

(88) Lisa said that JOHN teaches syntax on Tuesdays and Thursdays.

In these examples, focus on a constituent in the embedded sentence creates alternatives that are not

evaluated by the predicate of the matrix clause: the alternatives that are available for an example such

as (87) are the alternatives to the whole clause, not the embedded clause: >Lisa said that John teaches

syntax on Tuesdays and Thursdays= and >Lisa said that John teaches syntax on Mondays,

Wednesdays and Fridays=. Similarly, in (88), the available alternatives are >Lisa said that John

teaches syntax on Tuesdays & Thursdays= and >Lisa said that Lara teaches syntax on Tuesdays and

Thursdays=.

It can easily be shown that the same holds for other predicate classes that select the indicative

mood in Spanish: predicates of certainty (e.g. estar convencido >be convinced=, estar seguro >be

certain=), commissives (prometer >promise=), and fiction predicates (e.g. soñar >dream=) have this

same property.

John is the one who does the teaching, so one should rather say that Lisa wants JOHN to teach syntax on tuesdays and thursdays." (personal communication, Jenny Doetjes).

In fact, in the literature, some examples have already been provided to show that focus does

not always have the same effect in the context of all propositional attitude predicates. The following

examples are from Boër (1979). He suggests that with predicates such as know and believe the

meaning differences induced by focused constituents in the complement clause are much less

perceptible.

(89) Tom knows/believes that Bob HIT Alice.

(90) Tom knows/believes that Bob hit ALICE.

Similarly, Dretske (1972) points out that predicates such as believe and say are not sensitive to

the contrastive differences of the embedded clause (see footnote 16, p.435).

Page 45: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

44

Finally, let me illustrate with the example of the predicate sentir which can select both the

subjunctive and indicative mood, that such predicates are only focus sensitive when they select the

subjunctive mood. The predicate sentir, when it selects the subjunctive mood, has the meaning of the

emotive factive predicate >be sorry=. In the scenario above, (91) turns out to be false, while (92) is

true:

(91) Lisa siente que Juan de clases de sintaxis los MARTES Y JUEVES

>Lisa is sorry that Juan teaches syntax on TUE&THUR=

(92) Lisa siente que JUAN de clases de sintaxis los martes y jueves

>Lisa is sorry that JUAN teaches syntax on Tue&Thur=

To the contrary, when the predicate has the meaning of >sense=/=have the impression=, and selects

the indicative mood, the two examples (93) and (94) are truthconditionally equivalent:

(93) Lisa siente que Juan dará clases de sintaxis los MARTES Y JUEVES

>Lisa has the impression that Juan will teach syntax on TUE&THUR=

(94) Lisa siente que JUAN dará clases de sintaxis los martes y jueves

>Lisa has the impression that JUAN will teach syntax on Tue&Thur=

To conclude, the purpose of this section has been to argue that predicates that select the

subjunctive mood are sensitive to the presence of a focused constituent in the embedded clause: when

different constituents are focused, there is a truth conditional meaning difference. We thus have

evidence for the claim that the predicates that select the subjunctive mood are focus sensitive

operators.

In the following section, I turn to making precise what the semantic contribution of the

subjunctive mood morpheme is.

7.2 The semantic contribution of the subjunctive mood

Page 46: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

45

In this section, I address the following question: what role does the subjunctive mood

morpheme play in the semantic composition of the sentence? The literature on the semantics of mood

rarely addresses this question. The main focus of the majority of previous studies has rather been to

provide a characterization of the contexts in which the subjunctive mood appears. The investigation of

what the subjunctive mood contributes to the meaning composition provides a first step towards a

better understanding of why subjunctive verb forms require special semantic licensing conditions and

why they are obligatory in certain contexts.

To begin, I introduce Rooth=s (1985,1992) terminology for the semantics of sentences

containing focused constituents and present his semantics for focus sensitive operators such as only.

7.2.1 Focus according to Rooth (1985,1992)

As mentioned before, Rooth (1985,1992) shows that focus has a truth conditional effect in the

context of the adverb only. I now present Rooth=s proposal for the meaning of sentences of the

following kind:

(95) Mary only introduced Bill to SUE.

(96) Mary only introduced BILL to Sue.

In Rooth (1985,1992), next to the ordinary semantic value, an additional semantic value is

used to express the contribution that focus makes to the meaning of a sentence. The focus semantic

value of a constituent α is represented as � α� ALT , its ordinary semantic value as � α� o. The focus

semantic value of a sentence is the set of propositions obtainable from the ordinary semantic value by

making a substitution in the position corresponding to the focused phrase. I present here the ordinary

and alternative semantic values for the sentences above without only.

(97) � Mary introduced Bill to [Sue]F� o = λw.Mary introduced Bill to Sue in w

(98) � Mary introduced Bill to [Sue]F� ALT ={λw.Mary introduced Bill to x in w/x 0 D}

(99) � Mary introduced [Bill]F to Sue� o = λw.Mary introduced Bill to Sue in w

(100) � Mary introduced [Bill]F to Sue� ALT ={λw.Mary introduced x to Sue/x 0 D}

Page 47: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

46

The denotation of only carries an index C which (through the variable assignment g) refers to a

contextually determined set of propositions:

(101) � onlyC� go = λp.λw.� q: q 0 g(C) & q(w) 6 p = q

For a focus sensitive operator such as only, Rooth proposes that its domain of quantification

C is constrained by the focus semantic value. Focus introduces a variable C which anaphorically

constrains the domain of quantification of the focus sensitive operator. Rooth defines the ~-operator

which is adjoined to the variable C and evaluates the alternatives introduced by the focused

constituent. The sentence in (102) can be assumed to have the underlying representation in (103):

(102) Mary only introduced Bill to SUE.

(103) IP1 ri

onlyC IP2 ri

IP3 ~ C 6

Mary introduced Bill to [Sue]F

There are two constraints on the variable C introduced by focus interpretation. The first is that φ ~ C

presupposes that C is a subset of the focus semantic value for φ (and contains both the ordinary

semantic value of φ and an element distinct from the ordinary semantic value of φ). The choice of

antecedent for the variable C is free, but it is guided by the presuppositional constraint introduced by

the ~-operator:

ty (104) 4 φ ~ C 4o is defined only if � C� o φ � φ� ALT

ty If defined, 4 φ ~ C 4o = � φ� o

Page 48: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

47

The second constraint is that, in the expression [φ ~ C], focus has been interpreted, so the semantic

effect of the foci in φ has to be neutralized:

ty

(105) 4 φ ~ C 4ALT = {� φ� o}

Rooth=s semantics can also be adopted for predicates such as want. Parallel to only, the

predicate want has been defined here as carrying an index C that refers to a contextually available set

of propositions. For convenience, I repeat my proposal for predicates such as want here:

(106) � wantC� g = λp.λx.λw.� q: q � p & q 0 g(C): p >DES x,w q

Just like in the case of only, the index C of the predicate want should be constrained by the

focus semantic value of the embedded clause. The ~-operator, if placed in the appropriate position in

the tree, evaluates the alternatives for the predicate. I illustrate this here with an example from the

previous section, with a focused constituent in the embedded clause:

(107) Lisa wants John to teach syntax ON TUESDAYS AND THURSDAYS.

The appropriate tree structure for the sentence in (107) is the one below, where ~C is attached at the

level of the CP of the embedded clause.

Page 49: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

48

(108) IP ep

NP VP g eo

Lisa V CP1 g ri wantsC CP2 ~ C

5 John to teach syntax [on Tuesdays and Thursdays ]F

We can thus conclude that Rooth=s proposal for focus sensitive adverbs such as only can

straightforwardly be carried over to the predicate want. Notice, however, that we have to ensure that

the ~-operator is adjoined to the CP-level of the embedded clause. Other structures, in which the ~-

operator is adjoined to other positions, have to be excluded. The following structure, for example, is

uninterpretable because the elements in C are not of the right type (since ~C is adjoined at the VP

level, the elements in C are of type <e,<s,t>>):

(109) * IP ep

NP VP g eo

Lisa V CP g ri wantsC NP VP

g tu John 5 ~C to teach syntax [on Tuesdays and Thursdays ]F

A structure in which the index C is attached at the IP-level of the higher clause, such as in

(110), leads to a nonsensical interpretation: even though the elements in C are of the right type, C

does not correspond to a set of alternative propositions of the embedded clause. Here, C corresponds

to the following set of alternative propositions: {>Lisa wants John to teach syntax on Tuesdays and

Thursdays=, >Lisa wants John to teach syntax on Mondays, Wednesdays and Fridays}. These are not

the appropriate alternatives that the predicate want requires.

(110)* IP ep

Page 50: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

49

IP ~C ep

NP VP g eo

Lisa V CP g ri wantsC NP VP

g 5 John to teach syntax [on Tuesdays & Thursdays ]F

In the following section, I turn to the semantic contribution of the subjunctive mood

morpheme. I propose that the role of the subjunctive mood is to ensure that C contains the appropriate

set of alternatives, or in other words, that the evaluation of contextual alternatives happens in the right

place of the tree, namely at the level of the embedded clause.

7.2.2 The subjunctive mood: evaluation of contextual alternatives

In this section, I return to the Spanish data. I will assume that the subjunctive mood is realized

in a projection above IP, presumably in MoodP12. I will argue that subjunctive mood is an operator

that has the role of the ~-operator, namely to evaluate the alternatives for the matrix predicate. As a

consequence, the evaluation of alternatives necessarily happens in MoodP. Subjunctive mood thus

ensures that the evaluation of alternatives happens at the right place in the tree. Indicative mood, to

the contrary, will be argued to prevent evaluation of alternatives at the level of the embedded clause. I

define the SUBJC-operator as follows:

12 See Bhatt & Yoon (1991) for arguments for the existence of the functional projection MoodP. In proposing that MoodP is between CP and IP, I follow Kempchinsky (1998) and references therein.

Page 51: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

50

(111) Definition of SUBJC:

ty g a. 4 SUBJC IP 4o is only defined if g(C ) φ � IP� g

ALT & Card(g(C)) > 1

ty g when defined 4 SUBJC IP 4o = � IP� g

o

ty g b. 4 SUBJC IP 4ALT = {� IP� g

o}

The semantic contribution of the subjunctive mood can best be illustrated with an example

that contains a focused constituent in the embedded clause:

(112) Victoria quiere que Sofía traiga UNA TORTA DE CHOCOLATE.

Victoria wants that Sofía bring:PRES.SUBJ.3SG a cake of chocolate.

>Victoria wants Sofía to bring A CHOCOLATE CAKE.=

I will assume again that the relevant contextual alternatives are the following: >Sofia bring a

chocolate cake=, >Sofia brings ice cream=, or >Sofia brings an apple pie=. The relevant tree structure

corresponding to (112) is given below.

(113) IP2 ri NP VP g ri

Victoria V CP g ri

quiereC C MoodP g ri que SUBJC IP1 5

Sofía traiga [una torta de chocolate]F

Given the definition of the SUBJC-operator, the semantic derivation of (113) is as follows:

(114) � IP1� go = λw. Sofia brings a chocolate cake in w.

Page 52: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

51

� IP1� gALT = {λw. Sofia brings a chocolate cake in w, λw. Sofia brings ice cream in w, λw.

Sofia brings an apple pie in w}

� MoodP� go = � SUBJC IP1� g

o is only defined if g(C ) φ � IP1� gALT = {λw. Sofia brings a

chocolate cake in w, λw. Sofia brings an apple pie in w, λw. Sofia brings ice cream in

w}

when defined

� MoodP� go = λw. Sofia brings a chocolate cake in w

� MoodP� gALT = {λw. Sofia brings a chocolate cake in w}

� CP� go = � MoodP� g

o = λw. Sofia brings a chocolate cake in w

� CP� gALT = � MoodP� g

ALT = {λw. Sofia brings a chocolate cake in w}

� wantC� go = λp.λx.λw=.� q: q � p & q 0 g(C ): p >DES x,w= q

� VP� go = � wantC � g

o (� CP2� go) =

= λx.λw=.� q: q � [λw. Sofia brings a chocolate cake in w] & q 0 {λw. Sofia brings a

chocolate cake in w, λw. Sofia brings an apple pie in w, λw. Sofia brings ice cream in

w}: [ λw. Sofia brings a chocolate cake in w] >DES x,w= q

� IP2� go = � VP� g

o ( � NP� go) =

=λw=.� q: q � [λw. Sofia brings a chocolate cake in w] & q 0 {λw. Sofia brings a

chocolate cake in w, λw. Sofia brings an apple pie in w, λw. Sofia brings ice cream in

w}: [ λw. Sofia brings a chocolate cake in w] >DES Victoria,w= q

The resulting meaning can be paraphrased as follows: among the relevant alternatives {>Sofia brings

chocolate cake=, >Sofia brings an apple pie=, >Sofia brings ice cream=} >Sofia brings a chocolate

cake= is the most desirable alternative to Victoria.

I thus propose that MoodP is responsible for the evaluation of contextual alternatives for the

class of predicates that select the subjunctive mood. These predicates require the subjunctive mood in

the embedded clause because they require the presence of a set of contextual alternatives to the

embedded proposition. The SUBJC-operator evaluates this set of contextual alternatives for the matrix

predicate. At the level of the embedded clause, subjunctive mood is thus the morphological

realization of Rooth=s ~-operator.13

13 According to this theory of the subjunctive mood, we expect interaction with other possible focus-sensitive

Page 53: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

52

operators in the sentence. For instance, we expect that only should not be able to associate with a chocolate cake in the following example (since we predict that want associates with a chocolate cake): (i) Victoria only wants Sofia to bring A CHOCOLATE CAKE However, as pointed out to me by an anonymous reviewer, in English only can associate with the Focus in the embedded sentence. This may potentially be a problem for the theory. Interaction with other focus-sensititive operators will be left for future research.

Page 54: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

53

Let us now examine what would happen if the embedded clause was in the indicative mood. I

will propose that when the SUBJC-operator is replaced by the IND-operator, no evaluation of

contextual alternatives takes place in MoodP. Rather, the ordinary and alternative semantic values of

the IP are simply inherited. In other words, the IND-operator is essentially an identity function.

Is such a definition of the IND-operator sufficient to exclude indicative clauses to appear

under predicates such as want? The IND-operator does not evaluate alternatives that may be

introduced by a focused constituent in the embedded clause, hence the combination of want with an

indicative clause is, in principle, not interpretable (under the assumption that, just like in the case of

only, C has to be constrained by focus and cannot be purely provided by context). However, we still

have to exclude the possibility that the ~-operator could appear in an appropriate position in the

structure and do the work that otherwise would be done by the SUBJC-operator. In other words, we

have to exclude structures of the following kind:

(115)* IP ri NP VP g ri

Victoria V CP g ri

quiereC C MoodP g ri que MoodP ~C

ri IND IP 5

Sofía trae [una torta de chocolate]F

Hence, the IND-operator has to introduce some kind of constraint that prevents evaluation of

alternatives at the level of the embedded clause. Notice that the ~-operator should still be able to

appear in other positions in the tree. This is so since predicates that select the indicative mood also

allow for focused constituents in the embedded clause:

(116) Victoria sabe que SOFIA trajo una torta de chocolate.

Victoria know that Sofía bring:PAST.IND.3SG a cake of chocolate.

>Victoria knows that SOFIA brought a chocolate cake.=

Page 55: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

54

In this example, evaluation of contextual alternatives happens at the level of the whole clause. This is

seen from the fact that (116) is felicitous in a context that provides alternatives such as >Victoria

knows that Marcel brought a chocolate cake=, >Victoria knows that Rafael brought a chocolate

cake=. The corresponding tree structure is given in (117).

(117) IP1 ri IP2 ~C ri NP VP g ri

Victoria V CP g ri

sabe C MoodP g ri que IND IP

5 [Sofía]F trajo una torta de chocolate

The following example illustrates that evaluation of contextual alternatives may also happen below

the level of MoodP, for example in the presence of another focus sensitive operator such as only:

(118) Victoria sabe que solo SOFIA trajo una torta de chocolate.

Victoria knows that only Sofía bring:PAST.IND.3SG a cake of chocolate.

>Victoria knows that only SOFIA brought a chocolate cake.=

Page 56: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

55

(119) IP1 ri NP VP g ri

Victoria V CP g ri

sabe C MoodP g ri que IND IP2

ri soloC IP3

ri IP4 ~C

5 [Sofía]F trajo una torta de chocolate

We can conclude that for predicates that select the indicative mood the following holds:

evaluation of contextual alternatives is possible but not at the level of the embedded MoodP. In order

to block evaluation of alternatives at the level of MoodP, I thus propose the following definition of

the IND-operator

(120) Definition of INDC:

ty g a. 4 INDC IP 4o is only defined if

If there is a g(C ) φ � IP� gALT then g(C)= {� IP� g

o}

when defined ty g

4 INDC IP 4o = � IP� go

ty g b. 4 INDC IP 4ALT = � IP� g

ALT

This definition of the INDC-operator introduces the presupposition that if there is a contextually

available set of alternatives included in the alternative semantic value of the IP immediately below

MoodP, it only contains one single element, namely the ordinary semantic value of that IP. This

constraint prevents a predicate such as want to combine with an indicative clause: a contextually

available singleton-set is not sufficient for the interpretation of want.

Page 57: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

56

The definitions of SUBJC and INDC capture the fact that predicates that select the subjunctive

mood necessarily require the subjunctive mood in the embedded clause: SUBJC evaluates the

contextual alternatives for the matrix predicate, INDC prevents evaluation of the contextual

alternatives for the matrix predicate. Finally, we need to ensure that the predicates that select the

indicative mood also disallow the subjunctive mood in their complement clause. For the moment,

nothing would prevent SUBJC to appear under a predicate that selects the indicative mood. To remedy

for this, I propose that the following constraint holds for the operator SUBJC:

(121) Constraint on SUBJc:

SUBJC can only be licensed if it appears in the scope of a focus sensitive operator.

SUBJC is thus different from the ~-operator: ~C may appear in a sentence even in the absence of a

focus sensitive operator. As it stands, this constraint on SUBJC is a stipulation. However, it captures

well the fact that subjunctive mood is essentially a phenomenon in embedded contexts. Furthermore,

under certain circumstances, predicates that select the indicative mood do in fact allow for the

subjunctive mood in the embedded clause as long as they are embedded under another operator such

as negation or the question operator, as illustrated in the examples below14.

(122) Lucho no dijo que la comida estuviera lista.

Lucho not said that the food be:PAST.SUBJ.3SG ready.

>Lucho didn=t say that the food was ready.=

(123) Dijo Lucho que la comida estuviera lista?

Said Lucho that the food be:PAST.SUBJ.3S ready?

>Did Lucho say that the food was ready?=

14 As pointed out by an anonymous reviewer, the constraint on SUBJC is not precise enough. As it stands, it predicts that SUBJC can be licensed under any focus sensitive operator. Future research will address the question of how the relevant set of focus sensitive operators can be characterized.

Page 58: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

57

SUBJC thus can appear under predicates that select the indicative mood, as long as it is licensed by the

presence of negation or the question operator. These are operators that are also known to be focus

sensitive.

To conclude, in this section, I have proposed that the semantic contribution of the subjunctive

mood is to evaluate the contextual alternatives introduced in the embedded clause. To the contrary,

the indicative mood blocks evaluation of contextual alternatives at the level of the embedded clause.

8. Empirical evidence for a semantics of comparison

The proposal defended here makes the following important claim: predicates that select the

subjunctive mood introduce a gradable property (or ordering relation) with respect to which the

contextual alternatives are compared. The ordering relation is contributed by the lexical meaning of

each predicate. Under this assumption, we expect predicates that select the subjunctive mood, just like

gradable adjectives, to appear in certain types of degree constructions. There are only very few

predicates for which this expectation does not hold, namely some of the causative predicates (such as

hacer >make= and lograr >achieve=) and some of the directive predicates (such as ordenar

>order=)15. I proposed earlier, in section 5, that in these cases the comparative meaning component is

more deeply embedded within the meaning of the predicate. These predicates are thus not gradable

predicates as a whole but rather contain a gradable meaning part. As a consequence, we do not expect

them to allow for degree modification on the surface.

In the following, I discuss the distribution of various degree modifiers such as mucho

(>much=), bastante (>quite=), demasiado (>too much=), enormemente (>enormously=), and the

comparative construction with predicates that select the subjunctive/indicative mood. The distribution

of these degree modifiers provides further evidence for the proposal defended here.

8.1 Gradability in the adjectival versus verbal domain

15 See the appendix for more examples.

Gradable predicates such as tall express properties that are ordering inducing: we can compare

individuals according to whether they have the property of being tall to a greater or lesser extent. The

Page 59: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

58

crucial difference between gradable and non gradable predicates is that the domains of gradable

predicates can be partially ordered according to some gradient property, whereas the domains of non-

gradable predicates cannot.

For adjectives, modifiers such as >very= are an indicator of their gradable/non gradable

nature: while gradable adjectives can combine with >very=, non gradable ones cannot. The sentence

in (124) expresses that the victim is tall to a high degree, while the sentence in (125) cannot express

that the victim is dead to a high degree:

(124) The victim is very tall.

(125) *The victim is very dead.

Another good test for the gradable/non gradable nature of an adjective is the comparative

construction. Only gradable expressions can appear in comparative constructions:

(126) The victim is taller than his neighbor.

(127) *The victim is more dead than his neighbor.

When we turn to the verbal domain, the tests for gradability are less straightforward. Bolinger

(1972) suggests that we can distinguish degree verbs from non degree verbs by their acceptance of

lexical intensifiers such as quite, rather, so, etc. Thus, in the example (128), the acceptability of the

modifier quite indicates that the predicate exasperate is a degree verb. The modifier quite expresses

that there is a quite high degree of exasperation.

(128) He quite exasperates me. (Bolinger 1972)

However, Bolinger points out that such modifiers do not always signal degree modification. In

fact, a number of these degree modifiers are ambiguous and do not necessarily modify the degree of

the intensity of the property denoted by the predicate. For example, a modifier such as much as in

(129) can also be used to modify the extensibility of a predicate. Here, the modifier indicates that the

quantity of talking was high, not the intensity of talking.

Page 60: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

59

(129) He talks too much. (Bolinger 1972)

Doetjes (1997) points out that there is one class of modifiers that is not ambiguous in this way,

but has a much more restricted distribution: high degree adverbs such as >enormously= exclusively

modify the degree of the intensity of a property. The examples below illustrate that enormously can be

used to express a very high degree of appreciation, but not to express a very high quantity of movie-

going.

(130) John appreciated the movie enormously

(131) *Anne goes enormously to the movies. (Doetjes 1997, p.122)

The modifier >enormously= thus seems to be the best test for distinguishing gradable from non-

gradable predicates. I now turn to the distribution of degree modifiers with the predicates under

discussion.

8.2 Degree modification for predicates that select the subjunctive/indicative mood

In this section, I show that predicates that select the subjunctive mood differ from predicates

that select the indicative mood in what type of degree modification they allow.

A wide range of the predicates that select the subjunctive mood in Spanish allow for

modification with enormemente (>enormously=). This holds for all desire predicates, most emotive

factive predicates, all predicates of doubt, all predicates of probability and possibility and some of the

directive and causative predicates, as illustrated in the examples below16.

(132) Marcela desea enormemente que Rafael venga.

Marcela desires enormously that Rafael come:SUBJ.PRES.3SG.

>Marcela enormously wants Rafael to come.=

16 See the appendix for more examples.

Page 61: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

60

(133) Sofía se alegra enormemente de que la vengan a visitar.

Sofía SE glad enormously of that PRO her come:PRES.SUBJ.3PL to visit.

>Sofía is enormously glad that they will visit her.=

(134) Te sugiero enormemente que no salgas.

PRO you suggest enormously that PRO not leave:PRES.SUBJ.2SG.

>I suggest enormously that you don=t leave=

However, among the emotive factive predicates, there are some predicates that cannot

combine with high degree modifiers: certain predicates that express high extremes of scales such as es

estupendo (>it is great=) and es extraordinario (>it is extraordinary=), as well as predicates that

express a lower bound of a scale such as aceptar (>accept=), and es suficiente (>it is sufficient=). For

predicates that express such extremes of scales it is not unexpected that they disallow high degree

adverbs. High degree adverbs simply contribute redundant information in this case. Notice that all of

these predicates allow for other degree modifiers such as muy (>very=). Furthermore, as we will see

below, they can also appear in comparative constructions.

There are also a few other emotive factive predicates that do not allow for high degree

modifiers, such as es lógico (>it is logic=), es natural (>it is natural=), es normal (>it is normal=), es

mejor (>it is better=) and es peor (>it is worse=). For some reason, these predicates resist high

degree modification. They do however allow for degree modifiers such as muy (>very=) and mucho

(>much=). Since all the above mentioned examples are adjectives, I will assume that the possibility of

the modifier muy (>very=) is sufficient a test to show that they denote gradable properties. Again, all

of these predicates can also appear in comparative constructions.

To the contrary, none of the predicate classes that select the indicative mood allow for

modification with high degree adverbs such as enormemente (>enormously=) (with the exception of

the class of predicates of certainty). The incompatibility with high degree adverbs is illustrated in the

examples below with an epistemic predicate saber (>know=), and a predicate of communication decir

(>say=).

Page 62: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

61

(135) *Sofia sabe enormemente que no puede venir.

Sofia knows enormously that PRO not can:PRES.IND.3SG come.

*=Sofia knows enormously that she cannot come.=

(136) *Alberto dijo enormemente que tenía hambre.

Alberto said enormously that PRO have:PAST.IND.3SG h u n g r y .

* >Alberto said enormously that he was hungry.=

As expected under the proposal, all predicates that select the subjunctive mood (with the

exception of certain directive and causative predicates) allow for modification with a whole range of

other degree modifiers such as mucho (>much=), bastante (>quite=), tanto (>so much=), demasiado

(>too much=):

(137) Marcela teme mucho que Rafael venga.

Marcela fears much that Rafael come:SUBJ.PRES.3SG.

>Marcela very much fears that Rafael will come.=

(138) Sofía se alegra tanto de que la vengan a visitar.

Sofía SE glad so of that PRO her come:PRES.SUBJ.3PL to visit.

>Sofía is so glad that they will come to visit her.=

To the contrary, with predicates that select the indicative mood these modifiers are inacceptable

(when they express modification of the intensity of the property):

(139) *Rafael sabe mucho que no tiene razón.

Rafael knows much that PRO not have:IND.PRES.3SG right.

>Rafael much knows that he is not right.=

(140) *Rafael promete mucho que podrá venir.

Rafael promises much that PRO can:FUT.IND.3SG come.

>*Rafael promises much that he will be able to come.=

Page 63: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

62

For predicates that select the indicative mood, when modification with such degree modifiers

is possible, t h e y c a n o n l y e x p r e s s m o d i f i c a t i o n o f t h e

>e x t e n s i b i l i t y

= o f t h e p r e d i c a t e o r

r e p e t i t i o n . T h u s , i n t h e e x a m p l e b e l o w , w i t h t h e p r e d i c a t e o f c o m m u n i c a t i o n d e c i r

(>s a y= )

, d e m a s i a d o c a n o n l y m e a n >

t o o o f t e n=

a n d n o t >

t o o i n t e n s e l y=.

(141) Alberto dijo demasiado que tenía hambre.

Alberto said too-much that PRO h a v e :P A S T . I N D . 3 S G

hunger

>A l b e r t o s a i d t o o o f t e n t h a t h e w a s h u n g r y .

Importantly, for those predicates that can select both the indicative and the subjunctive mood,

degree modification is only possible when the subjunctive mood is selected. This is illustrated here

with the predicate sentir:

(142) Siento enormemente que te hayan hecho daño.

PRO sorry enormously that PRO you have:PAST.SUBJ.3PL done pain.

>I am enormously sorry about the fact that they have hurt you.=

(143) * Siento enormemente que va a haber un problema.

PRO sense enormously that PRO go:FUT.IND.3SG to there-be a problem.

*>I sense enormously that there is going to be a problem.=

The predicate esperar has also been claimed to allow for mood alternation (cf. Ridruejo 1999)17.

When this predicate selects the subjunctive mood it has the meaning of the factive emotive predicate

17 However, the indicative mood is only possible when the embedded clause is about a future event (as pointed out in Ridruejo(1999): (Error! Main Document Only.) Espero que venga /vendrá mi hermano

PRO hope that come:PRES.SUBJ.3SG/come:: FUT.IND.3SG my brother (Error! Main Document Only.) Espero que mi hermano viniera/*ha venido ayer

PRO hope that my brother come:PAST.SUBJ.3SG/*PAST.IND.3SG

Page 64: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

63

>to hope=, whereas when it selects the indicative mood it has the meaning >to anticipate=/=to

expect=. Crucially, modification with >enormemente= is possible only when the predicate selects the

subjunctive mood:

(144) Espero enormemente que venga mi hermano

PRO hope enormously that come:PRES.SUBJ.3SG my brother

>I enormously hope that my brother will come=

(145) * Espero enormemente que vendrá mi hermano.

PRO hope enormously that come:FUT.IND.3SG my brother

*>I enormously anticipate that my brother will come.=

Among the predicates that select the indicative mood, an exception is formed by the class of

predicates of certainty such as estar seguro (>be certain=). For these predicates, degree modification

is in fact possible. We will see, however, that the semantics of these predicates does not involve

comparison of contextual alternatives.

Imagine again a context in which there are the following three possibilities: Sofia may bring a

chocolate cake, she may bring an apple pie or she may bring ice cream. In this scenario, the

interpretation of a sentence containing the predicate be certain does not involve ranking the possible

alternatives on a scale of certainty. For example, the sentence in (146) does not imply (147). Rather it

implies (148):

(146) Victoria is certain that Sofia will bring chocolate cake.

(147) Victoria is less certain that Sofia will bring ice cream.

(148) Victoria is certain that Sofia will not bring ice cream.

We have seen previously that for predicates such as want the contextual alternatives are

ranked on a scale of desirability. Thus, if Victoria wants Sofia to bring chocolate cake, this implies

that the other alternatives are ranked lower on the scale of Victorias desirability. As we have seen

here, this is not the case for a predicate such as be certain. If Victoria is certain that Sofia will bring a

chocolate cake, this does not imply that she is less certain about the other alternatives.18

18 The predicate creer >believe= also allows for modification with enormemente and mucho (the only predicate in

Page 65: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

64

the class of epistemic predicates).Parallel to predicates of certainty, if Victoria believes that Sofia will bring a chocolate cake, this does not imply that she believes less in the other alternatives. Rather it implies that Victoria believes that Sofia will NOT bring ice cream.

Page 66: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

65

Finally, there is one further type of empirical evidence for gradability, namely the kind of

comparative construction illustrated in the example (149).

(149) It is more likely that Sofia will bring a chocolate cake than that she will bring an apple pie.

Notice that, in this example, overt comparison is established between two of the possible alternatives,

namely >that Sofia will bring a chocolate cake= and >that Sofia will bring an apple pie=. This kind of

comparative construction is thus a very straightforward test for the proposal developed here. As

expected, apart from the class of directives and causatives, all predicate classes that select the

subjunctive mood can appear in such comparative constructions. To the contrary, predicates that

select the indicative mood cannot appear in comparative constructions of this kind. This is illustrated

in the examples below.

(150) Sofia teme más que pueda perder su trabajo que no que tenga que trabajar demasiado.

>Sofia fears more that she could loose her job than that she may have to work too much.=

(151) Es más probable que Rafael venga a la fiesta que no que Lucia venga.

>It is more likely that Rafael will come to the party than that Lucia will come.=

(152) *Sofia sabe más que Lucia vendrá a la fiesta que no que Rafael vendrá.

*>Sofia knows more that Lucia will come to the party than that Rafael will come.=

(153) *Sofia comprendio más que tenía que trabajar demasiado que no que podía cambiar de

trabajo.

>*Sofia understood more that she had to work too much than that she could change her job.=

To conclude, in this section I have provided empirical evidence for the claim that predicates

that select the subjunctive mood are gradable predicates. These predicates can combine with degree

modifiers and can appear in a certain type of comparative construction, contrary to the predicates that

select the indicative mood.

Page 67: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

66

8.3 Refining the proposal: predicates that select the subjunctive mood have an extra degree

argument

In this section, I will refine the proposal in order to accommodate the empirical facts presented

above. In doing so, I will follow recent semantic literature that has adopted a scalar analysis19 for the

semantics of gradable adjectives. In the scalar approach, gradable adjectives are analyzed as relations

between individuals and degrees. In the literature, there are different variants as to what exactly the

denotation of a gradable adjective should be. I will assume here that a predicate such as tall is a

function of type <d,<e,<s,t>>> :

(154) � tall� = λdd.λxe.λws. x is tall to a degree d in w.

Similarly, I will assume that the predicate want is a function of type <d,<<s,t>,<e,<s,t>>>:

(155) � want� = λd.λp.λx.λw. x wants p to a degree d in w.

The degree morphology then applies to this function and imposes some requirement on the degree.

This requirement is different for each type of degree construction (absolute, comparative, superlative

and equative constructions). For each different construction in which the predicate may appear, this

degree morpheme introduces a different ordering relation. In absolute constructions, the ordering

relation is contributed by an abstract ι-morpheme. In comparative, superlative and equative

constructions the overt morphemes more, less, most or as take the place of this abstract ι-morpheme.

19 See for example Bartsch & Venneman (1973), Bierwisch (1989), Cresswell (1976), Heim (1985, 2000), Kennedy (1999,2001), Kennedy & McNally (2005), Klein (1991), von Stechow (1984a,b). See Kennedy (1999) for an overview of scalar analyses of gradable adjectives.

I will thus propose that, for predicates such as want, the comparison relation is introduced by

an abstract ι-morpheme. Notice that, in such an analysis, the ι-morpheme has the meaning of a

superlative morpheme, rather than an absolute morpheme (as is the case for adjectives). I will not

make any commitments as to what exactly the syntax of the verbal projection should be (see, for

example, Kennedy 1999 who proposes that adjectives have an extended projection DegP that hosts

Page 68: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

67

their degree morphology). For the sake of simplicity, I will assume that the degree morpheme is

attached at the V=-level, in the same position in which we find other verbal modifiers. For the

predicate want, this abstract ι-morpheme carries the variable C (which refers to the set of contextual

alternatives to p):

(156) VP ri

V= CP ri p

DegP V ιC want

The denotation of the whole VP should be the following:

(157) � VP� g = λx.λw. � q: q � p & q 0 g(C):

max(λd. x wants p to a degree d in w) > max(λd=. x wants q to a degree d= in w)

where max(S) = ιx:x 0 S & � y[y 0 S Ψ y� x]

We obtain this meaning from the two following parts:

(158) � want� g = λd.λp.λx.λw. x wants p to a degree d in w.

(159) � ιC� g = λP<d,<st,<e,st>>>.λp.λx.λw. � q: q � p & q 0 g(C): max(λd.P(d)(p)(x)(w)) >

max(λd=.P(d=)(q=)(x)(w))

In fact, some clarification is in order to explain how this proposal for the meaning of the

predicate want is related to the definition developed previously in section 4. Before, the comparison

relation >DESα,w was used to compare propositions, here > is used to compare degrees. Based on the

definition of the relation >DESα,w, we can express the meaning of a degree by defining an equivalence

relation (following Cresswell1976):

(160) Definition of an Equivalence Relation .:

p .q iff � z: (p >DESα,w z iff q >DESα,w z) & (z >DESα,w p iff z >DESα,w q)

Page 69: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

68

We can now define a relation � >DESα,w between degrees based on the relation >DESα,w. (� >DESα,w) is the set

of all >DESα,w -equivalence classes ( stands for field of a relation: Athe set of all things that are related

in one direction or another to something else@ Cresswell1976, p. 266, and p stands for the degree to

which p is desirable):

(161) p 0(� >DESα,w) iff � p 0 (>DESα,w): p = {z: z .p}

(162) p � >DESα,w q iff p >DESα,w q

The meaning of the predicate want should thus be as follows.

(163) � want� g = λd.λp.λx.λw. x wants p to a degree d in w.

where d 0 (� >DESx,w)

(164) � ιC� g = λP<d,<st,<e,st>>>.λp.λx.λw. � q: q � p & q 0 g(C):

max(λd.P(d)(p)(x)(w)) � >DESx,w max(λd=.P(d=)(q=)(x)(w))

where d 0 (� >DESx,w)

and max(S) = ιx:x 0 S & � y[y 0 S Ψ y� x]

(165) � VP� g = λx.λw. � q: q � p & q 0 g(C): max(λd. x wants p to a degree d in w)

� >DESx,w max(λd=. x wants q to a degree d= in w)

where d 0 (� >DESx,w)

and max(S) = ιx:x 0 S & � y[y 0 S Ψ y� x]

The definition in (165) thus replaces the previous definition of the meaning of the predicate want

from section 4. Notice that this proposal amounts to analyzing the comparative as a phrasal

comparative, as in Heim(1985).

To conclude, in this section, I have refined my proposal for the semantics of the predicates that

select the subjunctive mood. Following the recent literature on the semantics of gradable predicates, I

have proposed that these predicates have an additional degree argument. Furthermore, the meaning of

the predicate is decomposed into two parts. The predicate introduces the dimension of comparison

(for the predicate want the dimension is desirability), and the ι-morpheme introduces the comparative

Page 70: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

69

meaning component, as well as the variable C. When these predicates are modified by some degree

modifier such as mucho (>much=) or enormemente (>enormously=), or appear in a comparative

construction, the ι-morpheme in DegP is replaced by the corresponding degree morpheme.

9. Conclusion

In this paper, I have argued for a new semantics of the predicates that select the subjunctive

mood in Spanish, a semantics based on the comparison of contextually relevant alternatives.

I have proposed the following generalization for the subjunctive mood in Spanish complement

clauses: a proposition p that is the complement of the matrix predicate requires the subjunctive mood

iff the matrix predicate introduces an ordering relation (or scale) and compares p to its contextually

available alternatives. This generalization captures the fact that whether these alternatives are possible

or counterfactual alternatives is irrelevant for the distribution of the subjunctive mood.

Furthermore, I have addressed the following important question: what role does the

subjunctive mood morpheme play in the semantic composition of the sentence? The literature on the

semantics of mood rarely addresses this question. The main focus of the great majority of these

studies has rather been to provide a characterization of the contexts in which the subjunctive mood

appears. The investigation of what the subjunctive mood contributes to the meaning composition

provides a first step towards a better understanding of why subjunctive verb forms require special

semantic licensing conditions and why they are obligatory in certain contexts.

In the analysis presented here, the predicates that select the subjunctive mood are treated as

focus sensitive operators, and the subjunctive mood morpheme is given the role of evaluating the

alternatives for the focus sensitive operator. Subjunctive mood is then licensed by the presence of a

focus sensitive operator. This analysis has the advantage that it may be extended to other contexts in

which the subjunctive mood appears. It is well known that the subjunctive mood in complement

clauses may also be triggered under negation and in questions. As has been widely assumed in the

literature (cf. for example Büring 1999, Borgonovo 2003, Erteshik-Shir 1997, Jakobs 1983,1991,

Partee 1991,1993) negation can be analyzed as a focus sensitive operator. Parallel to what I have

proposed here, in the context of negation, the subjunctive mood morpheme can then have the same

role of evaluating the alternatives for the negation operator (see Villalta 2006). Similarly, Beck (to

appear) proposes that the question operator Q accesses the alternative semantic value of the

Page 71: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

70

proposition to turn the sentence into a question denotation, namely the alternative semantic value of

the sentence. Assuming that this question operator is a focus sensitive operator, the subjunctive mood

morpheme could, in the context of a question, have the same role as in the other contexts: namely to

evaluate the contextual alternatives for the focus sensitive operator.

Finally, I have shown that two important properties of the predicates that select the subjunctive

mood follow directly from the proposal developed here. These predicates are focus sensitive and they

are gradable. The focus sensitivity of these predicates follows directly from the fact that they are

analyzed analogous to focus sensitive operators such as only. Their gradability follows from the fact

that they are analyzed as introducing an ordering relation or scale. After presenting the empirical

evidence for a comparative semantics, I have revised the analysis accordingly: in the final proposal,

predicates that select the subjunctive mood carry an extra degree argument. This final proposal points

to a parallelism between the semantics of predicates that select the subjunctive mood and what has

been proposed for the semantics of gradable adjectives in the literature.

Page 72: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

71

References

Bartsch, R. and T. Venneman (1973). Semantic Structures: A Study in the Relation between Syntax

and Semantics. Frankfurt: Athenäum Verlag.

Beck, S. (2006). >Intervention Effects follow from Focus Interpretation=.Natural Language

Semantics 14.1-56.

Beck, S. (to appear). >The Grammar of Focus Interpretation=. Proceedings of the Berlin Symposium

>Interfaces + Recursion = Language=.

Bhatt, R. & J. Yoon (1991). >On the composition of COMP and parameters of V2'. In D. Bates (ed.)

Proceedings of the West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics 10. 41-52.

Bierwisch, M. (1989). >The Semantics of Gradation=. In M. Bierwisch and E. Lang (eds.)

Dimensional Adjectives. Berlin: Springer-Verlag. 71-261.

Boër, S. (1979). >Meaning and Contrastive Stress=. The Philosophical Review 2. 263-298.

Bolinger, D. (1968). >Postposed Main Phrases: An English rule for the Romance subjunctive=.

Canadian Journal of Linguistics 10. 125-197.

Bolinger, D. (1972). Degree Words. De Hague: Mouton.

Borgonovo, C.(2003). >Mood and Focus=. In J. Quer et al. (eds.). Romance Languages and

Linguistic Theory 2001. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins. 17-30.

Büring, D. (1999). >Drinking, Accents, And Negation=. In E. Benedicto & al. (eds.) Proceedings of

the Focus Workshop. University of Massachusetts Working Papers 21. Amherst, MA: GLSA-

publications. 37-50.

Cresswell, M. J. (1976). >The semantics of degree=. In B.H. Partee (ed.) Montague Grammar. New

York: Academic Press. 261-292.

Doetjes, J. (1997). Quantifiers and Selection: On the Distribution of Quantifying Expressions in

French, Dutch and English. PhD dissertation. Leiden University.

Dretske, F. (1972). >Contrastive Statements=. Philosophical Review 81. 411-437.

Dretske, F. (1975). >The Content of Knowledge=. In B. Freed et al. (eds.) Forms of Representation.

Amsterdam: North Holland Publishing Company.77-93. E g e a , E .

(

1 9 7 9

)

. L o s a d v e r b i o s t e r m i n a d o s e n B

m e n t e e n e l e s p añ

o l c o n t e m p o rá

n e o .

B o g o tá

: Publicaciones del Instituto Caro y Cuervo XLIX.

Page 73: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

72

Erteschik-Shir, N. (1997). The dynamics of focus structure. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Farkas, D. (1985). Intensional Descriptions and the Romance Subjunctive Mood. New York: Garland.

Farkas, D. (1992). >On the Semantics of Subjunctive Complements=. In P. Hirschbuehler & K.

Koerner (eds.) Romance Languages and Modern Linguistic Theory. Amsterdam/Philadelphia:

John Benjamins. 69-103.

Farkas, D. (2003). >Assertion, Belief and Mood Choice=. Ms. University of Santa Cruz.

von Fintel, K.(1994). Restrictions on Quantifier Domains. PhD Dissertation. University of

Massachusetts at Amherst.

von Fintel, K. (1999). >NPI-Licensing, Strawson-Entailment, and Context-Dependency=. Journal of

Semantics 16. 97-148.

von Fintel, K. & S. Iatridou (2007). AAnatomy of Modal Construction@, Linguistic Inquiry 38.445-

483.

Giannakidou, A. (1997). The Landscape of Polarity Items. PhD dissertation. University of Groningen,

the Netherlands.

Giannakidou, A. (1998). Polarity Sensitivity as (Non) Veridical Dependency. Amsterdam/

Philadelphia: John Benjamins.

Giannakidou, A. (1999). >Affective Dependencies=. Linguistics and Philosophy 22. 367-421.

Giorgi A. & F. Pianesi (1997). Tense and Aspect, From Semantics to Morphosyntax. Oxford: Oxford

University Press.

Givón, T. (1994). >Irrealis and the Subjunctive=. Studies in Language 18-2. 265-337.

Heim, I. (1985). Notes on Comparatives and Related Matters. Ms, University of Texas, Austin.

Heim, I. (1992). >Presupposition Projection and the Semantics of Attitude Verbs=. Journal of

Semantics 9. 183-221.

Heim, I. (2000). >Degree Operators and Scope=. In B. Jackson and T. Matthews (eds.) Semantics and

Linguistic Theory 10. 40-64.

Hintikka, J. (1962). Knowledge and Belief. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

Hintikka, J. (1969). >Semantics for propositional attitudes=. In J.W. Davis et al. (eds.) Philosophical

Logic. Dordrecht: Reidel. 21-45.

Hooper, J. (1975). >On Assertive Predicates=. In J. Kimball (ed.). Syntax and Semantics 4. New

York/London: Academic Press. 91-124.

Page 74: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

73

Hooper, J. & Thompson S.A. (1973). >On the applicability of root transformations=. Linguistic

Inquiry 4. 465-497.

Jakobs, J. (1983). Fokus und Skalen. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer Verlag.

Jakobs,J. (1991). >Negation=. In Arnim von Stechow & Dieter Wunderlich (eds.)

Semantik/Semantics: An International Handbook of Contemporary Research. Berlin: de

Gruyter.

Kadmon N. & F. Landman (1993). >Any=. Linguistics and Philosophy 16. 353-422.

Kamp, H. (1975). >Two Theories of Adjectives=. In E. Keenan (ed.) Formal Semantics of Natural

Language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 123-155.

Katz, E. G. (1991). >The Downward Entailingness of Conditionals and Adversatives.= In FLSM II:

Papers from the 2nd Annual Meeting of the Formal Linguistics Society of Midamerica.

Bloomington: IULC Publications. 217-243.

Kempchinsky, P. (1998). >Mood Phrase, Case Checking and Obviation=. In T. Schwegler & M.

Uribe-Etxebarría (eds). Selected Proceedings of the 27th Linguistic Symposium on Romance

Languages. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. 143-154.

Kennedy, C. (1999). Projecting the Adjective. The Syntax and Semantics of Gradability and

Comparison. New York: Garland.

Kennedy, C. (2001). >Polar Opposition and the Ontology of >Degrees== Linguistics and Philosophy

24. 33-70.

Kennedy, C. and L. McNally (2005). >Scale Structure and the Semantic Typology of Gradable

Predicates=. Language 81(2).1-37.

Kiefer, F. (1987). >On Defining Modality=. Folia Linguistica 21. 67-94.

Klein, E. (1980). >A Semantics for Positive and Comparative Adjectives=. Linguistics and

Philosophy 4.1-45.

Klein, E. (1991). >Comparatives=. In Arnim von Stechow & Dieter Wunderlich (eds.)

Semantik/Semantics, An International Handbook of Contemporary Research. Berlin: de

Gruyter. 673-691.

Krasikova, S. (2007). >Universal modals in comparative clauses=. In Grønn, Atle (ed.). Proceedings

of SUB12, Oslo.

Kratzer, A. (1977). >What >must= and >can= must and can mean=. Linguistics and Philosophy 1.

337-355.

Page 75: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

74

Kratzer, A. (1981). >The Notional Category of Modality=. In H.-J. Eikmeyer & H. Rieser (eds.).

Words, Worlds, and Contexts: New Approaches in Word Semantics. de Gruyter. 38-74.

Kratzer, A. (1991). >Modality=. In A. von Stechow & D. Wunderlich (eds.) Semantik/Semantics: An

International Handbook of Contemporary Research. Berlin: de Gruyter. 639-650.

Krifka, M. (1995). >The Semantics and Pragmatics of Polarity Items=. Linguistic Analysis 25. 209-

257.

Lee, Y. & L. Horn (1994). >Any as Indefinite plus Even=. Manuscript. Yale University.

Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Lewis, D. (1981). >Ordering Semantics and Premise Semantics for Counterfactuals=. Journal of

Philosophical Logic 10. 317-234.

Lewis, D. (1986). Philosophical Papers. Vol. II. Oxford University Press.

Linebarger, M. (1987). >Negative Polarity and Grammatical Representation=. Linguistic and

Philosophy 10. 325-387.

Panzeri, F. (2002). Mood and Assertion. PhD dissertation. Universita degli Studi di Milano.

Panzeri, F. (2003). In the (Indicative or Subjunctive) Mood. In M. Weisgerber (ed.) Proceedings of

the Conference Asub7- Sinn und Bedeutung@. Arbeitspapier Nr. 114, FB

Sprachwissenschaften, Universität Konstanz, Germany. 216-227.

Partee, B. (1991). >Topic, Focus and Quantification=. In S. Moore & A. Z. Wyner (eds.) Proceedings

of Semantic and Linguistic Theory I. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. 159-189.

Partee, B.(1993). >On the >Scope of Negation= and Polarity Sensitivity=. In Eva Haji�ová (ed.)

Functional Description of

Language. Prague: Faculty of

Mathematics and Physics,

Charles University. 179-196.

Portner, P. (1992). Situation Theory and the Semantics of Propositional Expressions. PhD

dissertation. University of Massachusetts at Amherst.

Portner, P. (1997). >The Semantics of Mood, Complementation, and Conversational Force=. Natural

Language Semantics 5.167-212

Portner, P. (1999). >The Semantics of Mood=. Glot International 4. 3-9

Page 76: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

75

Portner, P. (2003). >The Semantics of Mood=. In L. Cheng & R. Sybesman (eds.) The Second Glot

International State-of-the-Article Book. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.47-77.

Portner, P. (2004). >The semantics of imperatives within a theory of clause types.= In K.Watanabe &

R. Young (eds.). Proceedings of semantics and linguistic theory 14. CLC publications,

Cornell University.

Portner, P. (2007). >Imperatives and Modals=. Natural Language Semantics 15,4. 351-383.

Quer, J. (1998). Mood at the Interface. Ph.D. dissertation. Universiteit Utrecht, the Netherlands.

Quer, J. (2001). >Interpreting Mood=. Probus 13.81-111.

Ridruejo, E. (1999). >Modo y Modalidad. El modo en las subordinadas sustantivas=. In Ignacio

Bosque & Violeta Demonte (eds.) Gramática descriptiva de la lengua española. Madrid:

Espasa. 3207-3251.

Rooth, M. (1985). Association with Focus. PhD Dissertation. University of Massachusetts at Amherst.

Rooth, M. (1992). >A Theory of Focus Interpretation=. Natural Language Semantics 1. 75-116.

Schlenker, P. (2005). >The Lazy Frenchman=s Approach to the Subjunctive: Speculations on

reference to Worlds and Semantic Defaults in the Analysis of Mood=. In T. Geerts, I. van

Gynneken & H. Jakobs (eds.) Romance Languages and Linguistic Theory 2003.

Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins.269-309.

Seuren, P. (1973). >The comparative=. In F. Kiefer and N. Ruwet (eds.) Generative Grammar in

Europe. Dordrecht: Reidel. 528-564.

Sloman, A. (1970). >Ought and Better=. Mind 79. 385-394.

Stalnaker, R. (1968). >A Theory of Conditionals=. In N. Rescher (ed.) Studies in Logical Theory,

American Philosophical Quarterly. Monograph: 2. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. 98-112.

Stalnaker, R. (1984). Inquiry. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Stechow, A. von (1984a). >Comparing Semantic Theories of Comparison=. Journal of Semantics 3.

1-77.

Stechow, A. von (1984b).=My reaction to Cresswell=s, Hellan=s, Hoeksema=s and Seuren=s

comments=. Journal of Semantics 3. 183-199.

Stechow, A. von (2007). >Times as Degrees=.

Terrell, T. D. & J. Hooper (1974). >A semantically based analysis of Mood in Spanish=. Hispania

57. 484-494.

Page 77: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

76

Villalta, E. (2006). Context Dependence in the Interpretation of Questions and Subjunctives. PhD

dissertation. Universität Tübingen.

Westerståhl, D. (1985). >Determiners and Context sets=. In G. Van Benthem & A. Ter Meulen (eds.)

Generalized Quantifiers in Natural Language. 45-72.

Wright, G.H. von (1963). >Practical Inference=. The Philosophical Review 72.159-179.

APPENDIX

In this appendix, a few examples for each predicate class are provided and their behavior with

respect to focus sensitivity and degree modification (of intensity) is summarized

A. PREDICATES THAT SELECT THE INDICATIVE MOOD

Focus-sensitivity Modification with Modification with overt comparative enormemente mucho(intensity) construction possible

(intensity) EPISTEMIC PREDICATES

saber (>know=) * * * * pensar (>think=) * * * * creer (>believe=) * Υ Υ * PREDICATES OF CERTAINTY estar convencido * Υ Υ * (>be convinced=) estar seguro * Υ Υ * (>be certain=) es cierto * * Υ * (>it is a matter of fact=) es claro (>it is clear=) * * Υ * es obvio (>it is obvious=) * * Υ * PREDICATES OF COMMUNICATION

Page 78: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

77

aclarar (>clarify=) * * * * anunciar (>announce=) * * * * confesar (confess=) * * * * confirmar (>confirm=) * * * * contar (>tell=) * * * * decir (>say=) * * * * explicar (>explain=) * * * * indicar (>indicate=) * * * * mencionar (>mention=) * * * *

Focus-sensitivity Modification with Modification with overt comparative enormemente mucho(intensity) construction possible

(intensity) COMMISSIVES prometer (>promise=) * * * * ofrecer (>offer=) * * * * proponer (>propose=) * * * * FICTION VERBS soñar (>dream=) * * * * imaginar (>imagine=) * * * * PREDICATES OF MENTAL JUDGEMENT acordarse (>remember=) * * * * adivinar (>guess=) * * * * anticipar (>anticipate=) * * * * comprender (>understand=) * * * * darse cuenta (>realize=) * * * * descubrir (>discover=) * * * * estar de acuerdo (>agree=) * * * * sospechar (>suspect=) * * * * suponer (>suppose=) * * * * PREDICATES OF PERCEPTION notar (>notice=) * * * * sentir (>feel=) * * * * ver (>see=) * * * *

Page 79: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

78

entender (>hear=) * * * *

Page 80: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

79

B. PREDICATES THAT SELECT THE SUBJUNCTIVE MOOD

Focus-sensitivity Modification with Modification with overt comparative enormemente mucho/muy construction possible

(intensity) (intensity) DESIRE PREDICATES esperar (>hope=) Υ Υ Υ Υ desear (>desire=) Υ Υ Υ Υ preferir (>prefer=) Υ Υ Υ Υ temer (>fear=) Υ Υ Υ Υ EMOTIVE FACTIVE PREDICATES admirar (>admire=) Υ Υ Υ Υ aburrir (>be bored=) Υ Υ Υ Υ alegrar (>be glad=) Υ Υ Υ Υ aceptar (>accept=) Υ Υ fascinar (>fascinate=) Υ Υ Υ Υ gustar (>like=) Υ Υ Υ Υ importar (>care=) Υ Υ Υ Υ interesar (>interest=) Υ Υ Υ Υ es estupendo Υ (>it is great=) * Υ Υ es extraordinario Υ (>it is extraordinary=) * Υ Υ es fabuloso (>it is fabulous=) Υ * Υ ? es fantastico (>it is fantastic=) Υ * Υ ? es justo (>it is fair) Υ Υ Υ Υ lamentar (>regret=) Υ Υ Υ Υ es lógico (>it is logic=) Υ * Υ Υ es natural (>it is natural=) Υ * Υ Υ es normal (>it is normal=) Υ * Υ Υ es peligroso (>it is dangerous=) Υ Υ Υ Υ

Page 81: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

80

Focus-sensitivity Modification with Modification with overt comparative

enormemente mucho/muy construction possible (intensity) (intensity)

preocupar (>be worried=) Υ Υ Υ Υ es raro (>it is strange=) Υ Υ Υ Υ quejar (>complain=) Υ Υ Υ Υ sentir (>be sorry=) Υ Υ Υ Υ sorprender (>be surprised=) Υ Υ Υ Υ es útil (>it is useful=) Υ Υ Υ Υ es urgente (>it is urgent=) Υ Υ Υ Υ MODAL PREDICATES

es posible Υ Υ Υ Υ (>it is possible=) es necesario Υ Υ Υ Υ (>it is necessary=) es probable Υ Υ Υ Υ (>it is likely=) necesitar Υ Υ Υ Υ (>need=)

DIRECTIVE PREDICATES autorizar (>authorize=) Υ * * * aconsejar (>advise=) Υ Υ Υ Υ animar (>encourage=) Υ Υ Υ Υ exigir (>request=) Υ ? * Υ invitar a (>invite=) Υ * * * impedir (>hinder=) Υ * * Υ mandar (>order=) Υ * * * obligar (>oblige=) Υ * * *

Page 82: Mood and gradability: an investigation of the subjunctive ...

81

pedir (>ask=) Υ * * * prohibir (>forbid=) Υ * * *

Focus-sensitivity Modification with Modification with overt comparative enormemente mucho/muy construction possible

(intensity) (intensity) recomendar (>recommend=) Υ Υ Υ Υ sugerir (>suggest=) Υ Υ Υ Υ CAUSATIVE PREDICATES hacer (>make=) Υ * * * conseguir (>achieve=) Υ * * * lograr (>accomplish=) Υ * * * evitar (>avoid=) Υ Υ * Υ contribuir (>contribute=) Υ Υ Υ Υ ayudar a (>help=) Υ Υ Υ Υ causar (>cause=) Υ * * * Acknowledgments Over the years, this paper has benefitted from the help and comments of many, many people . I=m especially indebted to Sigrid Beck, Roger Higgins, Angelika Kratzer, Claudia Maienborn, Lisa Matthewson, Barbara Partee, Arnim von Stechow, and Wolfgang Sternefeld, and two anonymous reviewers. I would also like to thank Ana Arregui, Rajesh Bhatt, Nicholas Asher, Jenny Doetjes, Kai von Fintel, Irene Heim, Chris Kennedy, Sveta Krasikova, Doris Penka, Paul Portner, Yael Sharvit, and Philippe Schlenker for many comments and suggestions, as well as the audiences at the SALT X conference at Cornell University, the 30th Symposium of Romance Linguistics at the University of Florida, and the audiences at talks given at the University of Connecticut, at the University of Texas at Austin, at the Université Paris 7, and at the Universität Tübingen. All errors are mine. This paper was written under the support of the SFB 441/B17 project at the Universität Tübingen.