Top Banner

of 12

Journal of Philosophy of Education Volume 17 Issue 2 1983 [Doi 10.1111%2Fj.1467-9752.1983.Tb00031.x] David Gordon -- Rules and the Effectiveness of the Hidden Curriculum

Feb 26, 2018

Download

Documents

Andjela Bolta
Welcome message from author
This document is posted to help you gain knowledge. Please leave a comment to let me know what you think about it! Share it to your friends and learn new things together.
Transcript
  • 7/25/2019 Journal of Philosophy of Education Volume 17 Issue 2 1983 [Doi 10.1111%2Fj.1467-9752.1983.Tb00031.x] David

    http:///reader/full/journal-of-philosophy-of-education-volume-17-issue-2-1983-doi-1011112fj1467-97521983tb0003 1/12

    Journal

    of

    Philosophy of Education, Vol.

    17

    No. 2, I983

    207

    David Gordon

    Rules and the Effectiveness of the

    Hidden Curriculum

    Introduction

    Every pupil encounters each day at least three different aspects of hisher school environment:

    (1) the physical environment; (2) the social environment, made up of the people within the

    school, the relationships between them and the social structures they create; (3) the symbolic or

    cognitive environment, made up of the ideas, problems and information the pupil grapples

    with both on his own, in reading, and in discussion with other pupils and with teachers in class

    and other official activities. Each of these three aspects of the school environment has

    associated with it a hidden curriculum (Gordon, 1982). My concern in this paper is with the

    hidden curriculum associated with the social environment. From this point onwards this will

    be referred to as the SHC (social hidden curriculum). The literature on the hidden curriculum

    has been dominated by concern for this SHC. Some writers have even defined the hidden

    curriculum in such a way that the SHC can be the only hidden curriculum (e.g. Dreeben,

    1976). I have argued elsewhere (1982) that this is unacceptable. However, there is no doubt

    that the SHC is a very central part of the hidden curriculum and well worth detailed scrutiny.

    I will be addressing two different but related topics in this paper. First I will examine one

    aspect of the SHC which, although it has been related to implicitly (Dreeben, 1967; Durkheim,

    1961; Jackson, 1968; Kohlberg, 1970), has never been addressed directly,

    as

    far as

    I

    know. This

    consists of the lessons the social environment teaches about the nature of rules by means of

    the SHC. Schools are clearly organisations in which rules are very pervasive. The variety of

    these rules, the insistence of the school staff that rules be obeyed, the range of school activities

    for which rules are relevant, all suggest that pupils may learn in school not on y specific rules

    but also a great deal

    about

    rules

    in

    general. Of course the family is also a social unit in which

    rules (explicit and implicit) are operative. However, these are, in most cases, not impersonal

    rules and thus the school can be regarded as the first important institution in which people

    learn about rules which are, objectively speaking, impersonal ones. This doesnt mean that the

    way these rules are taught need highlight this impersonal aspect. Straughan (1982) has in fact

    argued that very often school rules are taught as if they were personal commands of particular

    teachers. This leads him to the conclusion that the pupils have been, in a sense, mistaught. I

    think Straughan is correct, but this doesnt require us to say that pupils have not been taught

  • 7/25/2019 Journal of Philosophy of Education Volume 17 Issue 2 1983 [Doi 10.1111%2Fj.1467-9752.1983.Tb00031.x] David

    http:///reader/full/journal-of-philosophy-of-education-volume-17-issue-2-1983-doi-1011112fj1467-97521983tb0003 2/12

    208

    D .

    Gordon

    about the nature of rules. All it means is that they have been taught something wrong about

    rules.

    The theoretical perspective which I will use to analyse the hidden curriculum concerning

    rules derives from the philosophy of law. It is a sad comment on the lack of interdisciplinary

    cross-fertilisation that the philosophical literature on legal rules has been so little used in the

    social sciences (and particularly in sociology) in discussions of rules, norms and related

    concepts [l ] . It seems to me that legal philosophy, and particularly the work of Hart (1961)

    and Dworkin (1977) suggests a most fruitful way of looking at rules, even in contexts which,

    strictly speaking, are not legal ones.

    Hart and Dworkin will supply the backdrop for my analysis of the nature of rules, but they

    do not help us with regard to the question of mechanism. How does the SHC teach about

    rules? I will examine a fascinating and problematic mode of functioning of the SHC which can

    be characterised as the ignoring of conceptual distinctions. This mode of functioning is

    particularly relevant to teaching about the nature of rules.

    The second topic of this paper is the effectiveness of the SHC. There is an implicit

    assumption in the literature that hidden curricula are very effective-at any rate more effective

    than the schools manifest curricula.

    As

    a general assumption this is understandable. It

    certainly would be very odd to undertake research on something both hidden from view (and

    therefore difficult to discover) and also ineffective (and thus probably unimportant). Therefore

    it is interesting that there are two very powerful arguments relating particularly to the SHC

    which purport to show that this aspect of the hidden curriculum is ineffective. These

    arguments cannot be used to show that the hidden curriculum in its entirety can have an

    impact on pupils. Thus they do not constitute a radical critique of the notion of a hidden

    curriculum. However, because of the centrality of the SHC in the literature on the hidden

    curriculum, they do seriously limit the claims we can make.

    In the second part of the paper then I will present and discuss the arguments mentioned

    above for the ineffectiveness of the SHC. How is this related to the first part? I will show that

    the SHC concerning rules manages, by and large, to avoid the difficulties raised by these two

    arguments. Since the latter are very powerful arguments, this means that the hidden lessons

    about rules are among the few parts of the SHC that probably are effective.

    The Nature of Rules and the Hidden Curriculum

    Rules and the Philosophy of Law: Hart

    In his classic The Concept of Law, Hart (1961) develops a number of central distinctions

    concerning rules. Of these, three are important for us. First, he distinguishes between habits (or

    convergent behaviour) and rules. A general habit of the members of a society is something

    most people do

    as a rule.

    One example he gives is the habit (at the time of writing of the book,

    at any rate ) of going to the cinema once a week. This is different from obeying a social rule.

    Hart suggests three differences: (1) deviation from a rule always engenders criticism and

    pressure to conform, whereas with habits this need not occur;

    (2)

    deviation from a rule is seen

    as a good reason for criticising behaviour. Criticism is legitimate: this is notso for a habit; 3) a

    rule has what Hart calls an internal aspect which habits need not have. The members of the

    society (or at least some of them) must have a critical, reflective attitude to the patterns of

    behaviour relevant to a rule. Certain such patterns must be seen by them as a common

    standard which guides their conduct.

    A second distinction Hart makes is betweenprimary and secondary rules. Primary or basic

    rules are those that require people to do or abstain from certain actions. They impose duties.

    Secondary rules are rules about rules. They are rules concerning the recognition, changing or

    modifying of primary rules. They confer powers. In Harts view only when a society has

  • 7/25/2019 Journal of Philosophy of Education Volume 17 Issue 2 1983 [Doi 10.1111%2Fj.1467-9752.1983.Tb00031.x] David

    http:///reader/full/journal-of-philosophy-of-education-volume-17-issue-2-1983-doi-1011112fj1467-97521983tb0003 3/12

    Rules and the Effectiveness of the Hidden Curriculum

    209

    developed this distinction between primary and secondary rules can it be considered to have a

    proper legal system.

    This leads us to a third distinction-that between a primitive or pre-legal society and a

    modem society with a developed legal system. In a pre-legal society there only exist primary

    rules. In other words there are no officials who enforce and interpret the laws in the modern

    sense (the creation of officials being one of the by-products of the existence of secondary

    rules). Also these primary rules, which constitute the legal system of the society, are

    conceived internally by most members of the society.

    In the simpler (decentralized pre-legal form of social) structure, since there are no

    officials, the rules must be widely accepted as setting critical standards for the

    behaviour of the group. If, there, the internal point of view is not widely disseminated

    there could not logically be any rules (p. 114)

    In contrast, in a modern society there are secondary rules, and thus there are officials. In

    addition, and this is a fascinating logical consequence of Harts analysis, no members of the

    society except the officials

    need

    regard the rules of the society from the internal point of view.

    Those rules of behaviour which are valid according to the systems ultimate

    criteria of validity must be generally obeyed,. (also the systems) rules of recogni-

    tion specifying the criteria of legal validity and its rules of change and adjudication

    must be effectively accepted as common public standards of official behaviour by its

    officials. (The obeying of valid rules of behaviour) is the only (condition) which

    private citizens need satisfy: they may obey each for his part only and from any

    motive whatever; though in a healthy society they will in fact often accept these rules

    as common standards of behaviour @ 113).

    As we will see, this distinction between a pre-legal society and one with a proper legal

    system becomes central when we consider the hidden curriculum concerning the nature of

    rules. So it is important at the outset to point out certain difficulties with Harts argument.

    First,

    it

    is never quite clear whether he is making an empirical, sociological claim-that

    societies can, as a matter of fact, be differentiated as he suggests-or whether he is only

    suggesting that the differences are logical ones which follow from the concept of a rule itself.

    If his claim is sociological, I think he is clearly wrong. Both in primitive and modern

    societies divergence from general habits of the community is often reacted to as if a proper

    rule had been broken. Also in modern societies most people have never even given a thought

    to the difference between primary and secondary rules, and

    so

    it isnt really clear in what sense

    this distinction could be said to exist within the legal system. To put this in another way: the

    distinction Hart draws between pre-legal and legal societies doesnt seem to express itself in

    the ways Pre-Legal Societys Man in the Street (Village?) and the Legal Societys Man in the

    Street conceive rules.

    If Hart is making a logical claim he is on much safer ground. However even here there is

    one problem. The concept of a primary rule obtains its significance by being compared to a

    secondary rule, in a similar way that the meaning of the word hot derives from the contrast

    between hot and cold. Thus when the same term primary rule is used to describe the rules

    of a pre-legal society in which these are the

    on

    rules, then the concept primary rule has

    changed its meaning. (In a language in which only hot existed, hot could not mean the same

    as it does for us.) It seems to me to be much better to talk of the rules of a pre-legal society as

    conflating primary and secondary rules. The rules of such a society have the content of what

    we call primary rules, but are accorded the importance and absoluteness of secondary rules.

    Continuing this line of thought leads me to suggest the following adaptation of Harts

    thesis. One can distinguish between two prototypical societies. In the first, which in order not

    to complicate matters

    I

    will continue to call a legal society (although I suspect this may be

  • 7/25/2019 Journal of Philosophy of Education Volume 17 Issue 2 1983 [Doi 10.1111%2Fj.1467-9752.1983.Tb00031.x] David

    http:///reader/full/journal-of-philosophy-of-education-volume-17-issue-2-1983-doi-1011112fj1467-97521983tb0003 4/12

    210 D. Gordon

    question begging), members distinguish clearly between habits, primary and secondary rules.

    In the second, which

    I

    will continue calling a pre-legal society, these distinctions are collapsed.

    The members are not aware of the different logical status of habits, primary and secondary

    rules. All rules are one. Of course these two societies are simply abstract ideal cases never in

    fact realised. However what we can say is that modern societies seem to be closer to the legal

    type than to the pre-legal type, whereas for primitive societies the opposite seems to be the case

    (Hayek, 1973; Jenkins, 1980). What we have in fact is a distinction in legal terms that more or

    less parallels classic sociological distinctions like Gemeinschaff/Gesellschaffor mechanical

    solidarity/organic solidarity [2].

    Apart from definitional matters, what further differences between legal and pre-legal

    societies can be stipulated? Perhaps the most important difference is that in legal societies the

    obligatory nature of rules is less insistent than in pre-legal societies. By this I do not mean that

    rules need not be obeyed in legal societies. Rather

    I

    am claiming the following. (1) Only the

    secondary rules of the society are uncontroversially and absolutely obligatory. Habits of course

    are not obligatory at all. The primary rules do require obedience, but they are subject to

    revision and can also be examined and criticised in the light of the secondary rules. It is

    possible to claim that a particular primary rule is invalid. Thus even if today I am obliged to

    obey such a primary rule, I am aware that objections to this rule could lead to its revocation.

    2) Social cohesiveness can be maintained even if a relatively large percentage of societys

    members do not adopt the internal stance towards most rules. In fact we have seen that from

    the logical point of view only the legal officials need necessarily adopt this internal stance. In

    contrast, in pre-legal societies stability would seem to require that most members adopt the

    internal stance towards the rules.

    Rules and the Philosophy

    of Law:

    Dworkin

    Dworkin (1977) suggests a number of further distinctions to those appropriated from Hart. I

    will concentrate on two of these. The first

    is

    the distinction between rules and principles. In

    Dworkins view, rules and principles are two logically distinct kinds of standards which direct

    decisions in different ways. Rules are applicable in an all-or-nothing fashion. As Dworkin puts

    it:

    If the facts a rule stipulates are given, then either the rule is valid, in which case the

    answer it supplies must be accepted, or it is not, in which case it contributes nothing

    to the decision (p. 24).

    Principles guide us differently. They do not set out automatic consequences. They suggest

    reasons that argue in one direction but need not necessitate a particular decision. So when we

    say that a particular principle is a principle of, say, law:

    All that is meant.. . s that the principle is one which officials must take into account,

    if it is relevant, as a consideration inclining in one direction or another (p. 26).

    In Dworkins view it makes perfectly good sense to claim, for example, that our law respects

    the principle that no man profit from his own wrong even if there are cases where the law does

    permit a man to profit from wrongs he commits. All this shows is that in these sorts of cases

    the principle has not been the only one taken into account and other principles have been

    given greater weight.

    Let me add Dworkins distinction between rules and principles to those derived from Hart

    and modify the way I have characterised legal and pre-legal societies. A legal society is one

    whose members distinguish between habits, primary rules, secondary rules and principles. A

    pre-legal society is one whose members collapse these distinctions. The only problem with this

    suggestion is that the notion of collapsing the rules/principles distinction is ambiguous. Does

  • 7/25/2019 Journal of Philosophy of Education Volume 17 Issue 2 1983 [Doi 10.1111%2Fj.1467-9752.1983.Tb00031.x] David

    http:///reader/full/journal-of-philosophy-of-education-volume-17-issue-2-1983-doi-1011112fj1467-97521983tb0003 5/12

    Rules and the Effectiveness of the Hidden Curriculum 21 1

    the resulting hybrid principle-rule retain the all-or-nothing nature of rules or does

    it

    lead to

    the flexibility (with regards to weight) of principles? I will interpret the notion of principle-

    rule in pre-legal societies as retaining the all-or-nothing nature of rules.

    A

    pre-legal society is

    thus one whch, among other things, relates to its basic moral principles as absolute, inflexible

    rules.

    The modifications of the notions pre-legal and legal societies strengthens the claim that

    in

    legal societies obligation is less insistent than in pre-legal societies. This follows from the

    fact that principles do not guide us in an all-or-nothing fashion. Thus applying them requires

    the use of discretion, at least in the weak sense (Dworkin, 1977, p. 31) that application

    demands the use of judgment.

    Let us now turn to a second distinction that Dworkin invokes-that between conventional

    and concurrent m orality.

    A

    community displays a concurrent morality when its members are agreed in

    asserting the same, or much the same, normative rule, but they do not count the fact

    of that agreement as an essential part of their grounds for asserting that rule. It

    displays a conventional morality when they do. If the churchgoers believe that each

    man has a duty to take off his hat in church, but would not have such a duty but for

    some social practice to that general effect, then this is a case of conventional

    morality. If they also believe that each man has a duty not to lie, and would have this

    duty even if most other men did, then this would be a case of concurrent morality

    (P. 53)-

    Three things need to be pointed out about this distinction.

    (1) Dworkins conception of conventional morality is similar to but not identical with

    Kohlbergs (1971) use of the same term. For Kohlberg conventional morality covers his third

    and fourth stages in moral development-the good boy and law and order orientations,

    which stress conformity to rules for its own sake. These two orientations would be included

    under Dworkins notion of conventional morality. However Kohlbergs fifth stage, which in his

    terminology, is post conventional, is a contractual or legalistic view of obligations and this

    would also be regarded as a conventional morality by Dworkin

    [3].

    2) Consider Dworkins churchgoing example. Imagine a churchgoer who, although con-

    tinuing to display a conventional morality (in Dworkins sense), feels that for some reason or

    other he cannot continue taking his hat off in church. It seems to me that this would probably

    result in his discontinuing going to church. In other words, when we have a conventional

    morality then the rules of a community in a sense define the community. Inability to conform to

    the rules will lead to estrangement fr o m the community.

    (3) In pre- leg al societies, social morality will be conventional whereas in legal societies it will

    be concurrent. This follows logically from two considerations: (a) in pre-legal societies habits

    and rules are conflated; (b)

    in

    legal societies, members are aware of the distinction between

    rules and principles, and are guided in part by principles (which must be applied with

    judgment and not simply by conforming to accepted practices).

    Rules and the Hidden Curriculum

    Let us now return to schools and the SHC.

    As I

    have already stressed in the introduction, in

    most cases schools are rule-inundated institutions. There are rules telling kids how to behave,

    where to be at different times of the day, how to answer questions, how to write in their

    exercise books, how to sit, how to dress, how to talk-very little that goes on at school is not

    subsumed under some rule or other. It is surely reasonable to assume that this rule-

    impregnated atmosphere teaches a hidden curriculum about what rules are.

    The question is: what lesson about the rules does the SHC teach? What conception of the

  • 7/25/2019 Journal of Philosophy of Education Volume 17 Issue 2 1983 [Doi 10.1111%2Fj.1467-9752.1983.Tb00031.x] David

    http:///reader/full/journal-of-philosophy-of-education-volume-17-issue-2-1983-doi-1011112fj1467-97521983tb0003 6/12

    212

    D.

    Gordon

    nature of rules is embodied in the way rules are presented? In order to answer this question we

    must first answer the preliminary one:

    how

    are rules presented? The answer I suggest is

    deceptively simple: rules are presented as rules. By this

    I

    mean that, apart from (1) simply

    telling or reminding the pupils at appropriate times what a particular rule is and (2) implying

    the existence of certain rules by virtue of their behaviour, the school staff in most schoolsdo

    not present rules in any special way at all.

    I

    feel a little uncomfortable writing this. After all I

    am making an empirical claim of sorts, and yet I am not producing any direct evidence for it.

    Indirect evidence is available. For instance in the chapters on rules in Hargreaves, Hester

    Mellors Deviance in Classrooms (1975), the authors point out the apparent absence of

    conceptual distinction in members accounts of rules (p. 34) and the fact that in giving

    accounts of (classroom) rules, the members did not possess a coherent framework in which

    they were able to talk about rules (p.

    45).

    This is evidence of a sort, but it is very indirect. The

    point is I dont quite see how

    I

    could produce direct evidence because

    I

    am in effect arguing

    for the existence of a non-event [4]. Over the years I have spent thousands of hours in schools

    and, except for a few rare cases,

    I

    have never come across any real attempt to differentiate

    between rule-types or go beyond the simple stipulation of relevant rules. At best, teachers

    sometimes try to show that a particular rule makes some sort of sense and thus perhaps teach

    the distinction between arbitrary and sensible rules [5] .Over and beyond this-a rule is a rule.

    However,

    as

    the discussion of Hart and Dworkins analyses of rules show, we must not

    conclude from this that the schools do not teach a hidden curriculum about rules. On the

    contrary, what follows is that they teach a very clearly defined hidden lesson. In brief they

    teach the c o n q t i o n of rules appropriate to a pre-legal society. This is my major thesis in this

    article.

    Three conclusions follow immediately if we take into account the previous discussion of

    the distinctions proposed by Hart and Dworkin.

    (1) The schools hidden curriculum presents a conventional morality (in Dworkins sense).

    (2) Recent research findings (which

    I

    will discuss in the next section) may show that the

    hidden curriculum is not very successful in teaching kids to conform to rules. But if the hidden

    curriculum presents a conventional morality, it teaches a very specific lesson about what

    conformity means. What is taught is that disagreement with the rules of a community is

    equivalent to estrangement from that community. In other words, the hidden curriculum

    radicalises non-conformity by equating it with alienation.

    3)

    The pre-legal conception of rules and the associated conventional morality are being

    taught within societies which are far closer to being legal than pre-legal ones. Such societies

    would seem to require a concurrent rather than a conventional morality. What one makes of

    this tension probably depends on ones attitude to functionalist explanations in sociology. All I

    wish to do here is point out that tension.

    So

    if my major thesis is correct and if, in addition, this hidden curriculum about rules is

    not only taught but also learned (i.e. this is an effective part

    of

    the hidden curriculum) then it

    seems we are talking about something with extremely important ramifications. Therefore

    I

    turn now to the question of the effectiveness of the hidden curriculum in general and the

    SHC

    in particular.

    The Hidden Curriculum, Effectiveness and Rules

    Resistance Theories

    When Jackson (1968) coined the term a decade and a half ago, it seemed self-evident to many

    that this hidden curriculum was an effective curriculum. As Bloom (1972) wrote:

    The (hidden) curriculum is in many respects likely to be more effective than the

    manifest curriculum. The lessons it teaches are long remembered because it is so

  • 7/25/2019 Journal of Philosophy of Education Volume 17 Issue 2 1983 [Doi 10.1111%2Fj.1467-9752.1983.Tb00031.x] David

    http:///reader/full/journal-of-philosophy-of-education-volume-17-issue-2-1983-doi-1011112fj1467-97521983tb0003 7/12

    Rules and the Effectiveness of the Hidden Curriculum

    213

    pervasive and consistent over the many years in which our students attend school

    (p. 343).

    However, this effectiveness can be questioned and I wish to discuss two arguments for the

    ineffectiveness of the hidden curriculum: (a) theories of resistance; (b) the school as enclave

    argument. In this sub-section I will relate to the first of these. The structure of my presentation

    will be as follows: first I will briefly characterise resistance theories; secondly, I will point out

    some of the possible criticisms of such theories; thirdly, I will argue that these criticisms are

    inapplicable to the SHC and thus that resistance theories can be interpreted as showing that the

    SHC is ineffective. The following sub-section deals with the school as enclave argument and

    the structure of my presentation is formally identical to that in the present sub-section. In

    other words

    I

    reach the conclusion that this school as enclave argument does apply to the

    SHC and thus supplies a further reason for claiming that the SHC is ineffective. The final sub-

    section brings us back to the teaching of rules. There

    I

    will show how the hidden curriculum

    concerning the nature of rules manages to avoid the charge of being ineffective, despite its

    being part of the SHC.

    Let us now turn to resistance theories. As Apple (1981) puts it:

    For schools are not merely institutions of reproduction, institutions where the overt

    and covert knowledge that is taught inexorably moulds students into passive beings

    who are able to

    fit

    into an unequal society. This account fails in two critical ways.

    First, it views students as passive internalizers of pre-given social messages. Whatever

    the institution teaches in either the formal curriculum or the hidden curriculum

    is

    taken in and is unmodified by class cultures and class (or race or gender) rejection of

    dominant social messages. Anyone who has taught in working-class schools, in

    schools located in our inner city ghettos, knows that this is simply not true. Student

    reinterpretation, at best only partial acceptance, and often outright rejection of the

    planned and unplanned meanings of schools are more likely (p.

    30 .

    A considerable body of literature has appeared over the last few years which purports to

    document the resistance. phenomenon that Apple claims exists (e.g. Anyon, 1981; Giroux,

    1981; Willis, 1977). The evidence is impressive but that does not mean that resistance theories

    are immune from criticism. Hargreaves (1982) points out a number of flaws in this predomi-

    nantly Marxist literature. In his view, an ideological committment to social transformation has

    led the advocates of resistance theories to an oversimplified view of resistance. They have used

    the word as an undifferentiated general concept applying to many different kinds of disaffec-

    tion with schooling, some of which cannot plausibly be regarded as resistance at all. They also

    have not critically analysed their empirical data and other data from other research traditions

    in order to determine the extent to which the phenomena they describe are really prevalent.

    I would add a further criticism. Resistance theorists employ what seems to me to be an

    extremely over simplified and at times loose conception of the hidden curriculum. Take Apple

    for example, and consider the following sentences from a different article of his than that

    quoted above:

    The traditional literature on the hidden curriculum has .

    .

    pictured.

    .

    students.

    .

    as

    passive recipients of the norms and values which are embodied in the curricular and

    social environment of the school Is (this approach) accurate? Do students always

    internalize these norms and dispositions unquestionably? There is evidence to suggest

    that not all students simply take in this hidden curriculum; that students often

    creatively act to control their school environments; and that, at least for certain

    segments of the working class, they in fact expressly reject the norms

    of

    obediance,

    respect f o r authority and so on. . (my emphasis) (Apple 1980/81, p. 7).

    I

    wish to stress that all these sentences appear

    in

    the same paragraph, they are part of one

    sustained idea. However, we see that during this passage Apple moves from seeing the hidden

  • 7/25/2019 Journal of Philosophy of Education Volume 17 Issue 2 1983 [Doi 10.1111%2Fj.1467-9752.1983.Tb00031.x] David

    http:///reader/full/journal-of-philosophy-of-education-volume-17-issue-2-1983-doi-1011112fj1467-97521983tb0003 8/12

    214 D. Gordon

    curriculum as being concerned with norms and values to being concerned with norms and

    dispositions, to being concerned with the specific norms of obedience and respect for authority.

    We also see that a distinction between the curricular and social environments in the first part

    of the passage is collapsed into the school environment later on.

    I do not believe that these are simply examples of a slip of the pen. Rather it seems to me

    that Apple is simply dismissing as irrelevant a number

    of

    distinctions one could make about

    the hidden curricula of the physical, social and cognitive environments, between things the

    teachers did not intend teaching and those they did intend but did not openly acknowledge to

    the students (Martin 1976), between hidden curricula messages directly related to the imposi-

    tion of dominant class hegemony and hidden curricular messages whose relationship to such

    hegemony is at best indirect. Yet surely it is reasonable to suppose that resistances to these

    different facets of the hidden curriculum will vary and, with regards to some of these facets,

    that the resistance will be minimal? Yet if we allow this, we have essentially accepted the

    proposition that some aspects of the hidden curriculum are effective.

    As a general critique of resistance theories this will do nicely. However,

    I

    do not think we

    can use this critique to argue for the effectiveness of the SHC. Let us consider the classic

    ethnographic depiction

    of

    working class resistance-Williss (1977) Learning to Labour. Willis

    shows how a group of working class lads reject the schools culture and how this rejection,

    ironically and tragically, results in their condemning themselves to remaining part of the

    exploited working class labour force. The rejection of the school culture is the rejection of the

    teachers, what they represent, the relationships they try to create, the tasks they set-in short, it

    is a rejection

    of

    the SHC. And so if we are prepared to admit that Willis has captured

    something true and vital about working class reactions

    to

    school (and this we must do-his

    book is simply too good to be ignored), we must accept the fact that with at least a part of the

    school population the SHC is not particularly effective. Resistance and the hidden curricu-

    lum may be terms used loosely by resistance theorists, but their analyses do seem to apply to

    the SHC.

    The School as Enclave Argument

    Resistance theories can be bolstered by an argument which is perhaps even more powerful

    because it encompasses all pupils, including those who do not reject the schools culture. This

    argument is a consequence of Bernsteins (1977) theory of educational codes which, surprisin-

    gly enough, neither Bernstein nor those who have used his conceptual system seem to have

    spotted. Bernstein maintains that the most typical educational codes (collection codes) are

    characterised by strong classijication i.e. contents are insulated from each other by clear-cut

    and strong boundaries. Of these, one boundary pointed out explicitly is that between school

    and everyday knowledge. Now, if this boundary is maintained, the school is transmitting a

    hidden curricular message that school and life are, in some sense separate. The school is a

    special, unique enclave. The point is: i f this message is transmitted effectively then essentially a

    whole class of other hidden curricular messages are rendered ineffective.

    Take as an example the claim that schools, through their hidden curricula, teach pupils

    that they should be docile. In actual fact, the hidden curricular message can only be: in

    schools one should be docile. Those who claim that a more general docility results from this

    are making the (implicit) assumption that some sort of transfer effect occurs. But if we are

    talking about a school system with collection code, the hidden curricular lesson: In schools

    one must be docile, is linked to another hidden curricular lesson: Schools are special

    enclaves, and thus there is no reason to believe that the pupils actually learn: In general one

    must be docile or: In the work place one must be docile. They may learn the skill of acting

    with docility, a skill they can invoke at appropriate times, but they will not have developed a

    predilection to be docile.

  • 7/25/2019 Journal of Philosophy of Education Volume 17 Issue 2 1983 [Doi 10.1111%2Fj.1467-9752.1983.Tb00031.x] David

    http:///reader/full/journal-of-philosophy-of-education-volume-17-issue-2-1983-doi-1011112fj1467-97521983tb0003 9/12

    Rules and the Effectiveness

    of

    the Hidden Curriculum

    215

    At least two types of hidden curricular learning avoid the enclave difficulty. First, the

    hidden curriculum teaches certain thingsabout schools and also matters (mostly cognitive) that

    are conceived in our society as part of the schools legitimate area of authority. In relation to

    this aspect of the hidden curriculum, learning that schools are special places does not act as a

    barrier. For instance, schools project a certain image of science (Cawthron Rowell, 1978).

    Seeing as science is part of school knowledge, in the sense that the school is regarded as the

    institution whose job it is to see to it that societys members are scientifically literate, clearly

    the fact that schools are seen as special enclaves will not result in pupils relating to the image

    of science they have learned in the schools hidden curriculum as only being true in schools.

    This doesnt mean that we can assume that pupils will regard science as something beneficial,

    interesting or important. All I am saying is that they are likely to accept the school image of

    what science is,

    Secondly, the learnings of the hidden curriculum that remain unverbalised are also

    untouched by Bernsteins analysis (and also, by the way, by the analyses of resistance

    theorists). In order to see this, the notion of unverbalised learning must be elaborated. The

    hidden curriculum teaches in such a way that the pupils are usually unaware of having been

    taught anything. This is why we call it a hidden curriculum. However, the results of hidden

    curricular teaching need not remain unconscious. I remember once teaching mathematics to a

    class in a special mathematics track. Many of the pupils were convinced that the humanities

    were nonsense because in the humanities anything you say is acceptable. This extraordinary

    opinion was one they held perfectly consciously and was one they verbalised with great force,

    even though they could not indicate where and how they had picked it up. On the other hand,

    when Schwab (1962, p. 46) claims that one of the meta lessons of science teaching is that all

    entities have the same ontological status, he is not suggesting that this is something pupils

    could or do verbalise explicitly. It is clear that he is referring to a bit of tacit knowledge,

    something that colours the way pupils look at the world, yet is something they are not only

    unaware of having been taught but also

    are unaware they have learnt.

    This second type of hidden curricular learning evades the school as enclave barrier

    because its remaining unverbalised prevents

    it

    from being manipulated in thought in conjunc-

    tion with other beliefs. Specifically, it is never juxtaposed with the belief school is a special

    place in such a way as to result in the limiting of its range (as in the case of the one should be

    docile example).

    The above considerations lead me to the conclusion that, by and large, the hidden

    curriculum of the schools cognitive and physical environments remain unaffected by the

    argument I have derived from Bernstein. The hidden curriculum of the cognitive environment

    is mainly linked to matters considered part of the schools legitimate area of authority, and

    thus the learning associated with it is an important part of the first type of hidden curricular

    learning which avoids the school as enclave difficulty. The hidden curricular learnings

    associated with the physical environment seem likely to remain mainly unverbalised, and thus

    are part of the second type of learning which avoids this difficulty.

    However, when we turn to the SHC, which is our concern here, things are very different.

    Social messages, to use Apples (1981) term, are not those generally considered part of the

    schools legitimate area of authority and the social learnings of the hidden curriculum would

    appear to be precisely those which do become verbalised. Thus the schoolas enclave argument

    would appear to augment resistance theories very convincingly vis-a-vis the ineffectiveness of

    the SHC.

    Resistance Theories, the School as Enclave Argument and Ru les

    Since the hidden curriculum about rules is part of the SHC, must the theoretical structure laid

    out in the first part of this article now simply be dismissed as irrelevant? Must we accept the

  • 7/25/2019 Journal of Philosophy of Education Volume 17 Issue 2 1983 [Doi 10.1111%2Fj.1467-9752.1983.Tb00031.x] David

    http:///reader/full/journal-of-philosophy-of-education-volume-17-issue-2-1983-doi-1011112fj1467-97521983tb000 10/12

    216 D Gordon

    conclusion that the hidden curriculums lessons about rules are not learnt very well if at all,

    despite the pervasiveness of school rules?

    I

    answer in the negative. It seems to me that there

    are good reasons for believing that the hidden curriculum about rules manages to avoid the

    difficulties raised by resistance theories and the school as enclave argument.

    Let us imagine a group of working class lads who reject certain rules or perhaps the very

    notion that school rules need be obeyed. If they are doing this deliberately, they must espouse

    beliefs like This rule is stupid or Nobody here is going to tell

    us

    what to do7.The point is

    that, in order to entertain such beliefs, these lads must have some notion of what a rule is

    Their notion need not be one philosophers of law would be happy with, but it cannot be

    completely amorphous. Without some relatively clear notion of the nature of rules, one cannot

    reject particular rules or question the right of other people to demand ones obediance to them.

    If rejection of rules requires that our imaginary lads have some idea of what rules are,

    then the question arises: how and where did they learn their idea of the nature of rules? Can

    one entertain the idea that they arrived at school as

    six

    year olds with a certain conception

    which remained fixed throughout their school careers? Far more reasonable to assume that

    their conception of rules resulted at least in part from hidden curricular lessons in school

    about rules. Resistance can never be a process of total annihilation of all hegemonic

    impositions.

    A formally equivalent argument can be offered when relating to the relevance of the

    school as enclave argument

    in

    learning abcut rules. Here again, entertaining beliefs like In

    school there are rules like X, but

    I

    will not need to deal with X-like rules outside school

    requires: (1) that

    I

    have some picture of what a rule in general is; (2)

    I

    must have learnt this

    rule at least in part in school.

    As a general conclusion we can say that the pupils rejection or qualification of certain

    SHC lessons relating to rules logically entails that at least one hidden curricular lesson was

    taught effectively-the lesson about the general nature of rules. Seeing as this is such an

    important lesson, with

    so

    many significant consequences, we can conclude that at least one

    central part of the SHC is probably an effective part of the hidden curriculum.

    Unanswered Questions

    Let me conclude by pointing out some of the questions raised by my analysis, questions which

    I hope to address in some future article.

    First, there are certain value issues which follow from Dworkins distinction between

    conventional and concurrent morality. During this article I have maintained, or tried to

    maintain, a neutral stance vis-a-vis the question whether schools should teach the hidden

    curriculum about rules that I claim they actually do teach. Clearly ones reaction to the

    analysis depends on the way one answers this question.

    Let

    us

    assume ones answer is that this hidden curriculum should not be taught because the

    concept of rules it teaches is misleading, unsuited to modern societies, or whatever. This raises

    a second question: how can this hidden curriculum be countered? How can one teach pupils to

    distinguish between habits, primary rules, secondary rules and principles? An obvious sugges-

    tion would be to teach about rules explicitly in the manifest curriculum. But this raises further

    problems. Would the teaching of such a manifest curriculum in a particular school have any

    impact on that schools hidden curriculum? If not, would it be effective enough to counter the

    hidden curriculum (remember, the hidden curriculum is usually considered to be a more

    effective curriculum than the manifest curriculum)?

    A further set of questions arises when we notice that schools do not only teach the sort of

    social rules

    I

    have considered here. They also teach rules related to cognitive matters. For

    instance Ormell (1978) and Gordon, Achiman Melman (1981) have discussed the hidden

  • 7/25/2019 Journal of Philosophy of Education Volume 17 Issue 2 1983 [Doi 10.1111%2Fj.1467-9752.1983.Tb00031.x] David

    http:///reader/full/journal-of-philosophy-of-education-volume-17-issue-2-1983-doi-1011112fj1467-97521983tb000 11/12

    Rules and the Effectiveness of the Hidden Curriculum

    211

    curriculum associated with the learning of rules in mathematics. Do these two different hidden

    curricula about rules interact? If so in what way?

    Attempting to relate to these questions must be postponed for another time but we now

    can say at least that they show the whole issue

    of

    the hidden curriculum and rules to be an

    important one. I also hope that my discussions of Hart and Dworkins work has pointed up a

    source for educational theorising that has been used too little in the past [ 6 ] .

    Correspondence: David Gordon Ben Gurion University of the Neger Beersheba Israel.

    NOTES

    [ ]

    Of course the special sub discipline concerned with sociology of law has used this philosophical literature at

    times. For example: Barkun (1968), Bechtler (1978), Weber (1954).

    [2] In the case of mechanical solidarity/organic solidarity, this is not surprising seeing that legal matters feature so

    strongly in Durkheims (1964) development of this distinction.

    [3] Actually it isnt completely clear that even stage 6 is one of concurrent morality.

    A

    central educational

    development of Kolhbergs approach is the idea of a just community. According to Power (one of Kohlbergs co-

    workers) in such a community there are collective

    norms,

    which he defines as norms which bind members of a

    group qua members of that group to act in certain ways (Power, 1981, p. 11). This seems to me to be a

    conventional morality in Dworkins sense. The point is, however, that Power seems to believe that a truly

    exemplary community will be one whose collective norms will be stage 6

    norms.

    If so, even stage 6 is not a

    concurrent morality.

    [4] I have shown that the notion of a non-event teaching something is problematic (Gordon, 1982). However, the

    example I am developing here avoids the problems I pointed out in the previous paper.

    [ ] However, Straughan (1982) has argued that they do this in such a way as to make the notion of a rule logically

    superfluous.

    [6] I am

    not

    referring here to the use of the philosophical analysis

    of

    distributive justice in discussions

    on

    educational policy. That has been quite prevalent for some time (Strike, 1979).

    REFERENCES

    ANYON,EAN1981) Elementary schooling and distinctions of social class, Interchange, 12 pp. 118-132.

    APPLE,MICHAEL . (1980/81) The other side of the hidden curriculum: correspondence theories and the labor process,

    APPLE,MICHAEL

    W .

    (198

    1)

    Reproduction, contestation and curriculum: an essay in self-criticism,

    Interchange,

    12,

    BARKUN, ICHAEL1968) Law Without Sanctions

    (New Haven, Yale University Press:.

    BECHTLER,HOMAS, . (1978)

    Law in a Social Context

    (Dordrecht, Kluwer).

    BERNSTEIN,ASIL 1971) On the classification and framing of educational knowledge, in: BERNSTEIN,ASILClass,

    Codes and Control, Vol.

    3 pp.

    85-115

    (London, Routledge Kegan Paul).

    CAWTHRON,.R. ROWELL,.A. (1978) Epistemology and science education, Studies in Science Education, 5, 31-59.

    DREEBEN, OBERT1967) The contribution of schooling to the learning of norms, Harvard Educational Review, 32,

    DREEBEN,OBERT 1976) The unwritten curriculum and its relation to values, Journal of Curriculum Studies, 8,

    DURKHEIM,MILE 1961) Moral Education (New York, Free Press).

    DURKHEIM,MILE 1964)

    The Division

    of

    Labor in Society

    (New York, Free Press).

    DWORKIN,ONALD1977) Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Press).

    GIROUX, ENRY . (1981) Hegemony, resistance, and the paradox of educational reform. Interchange, 12, 3-26.

    GORDON, AVID1982) The concept of the hidden curriculum, Journal of Philosophy of Education, 16, 187-198.

    GORDON,AVID, CHIMAN,AS MELMAN, ANIEL1981) Rules

    in

    mathematics, Mathem atics in School,

    10,

    2 4 .

    HARGREAVES,NDY 1982) Resistance and relative autonomy theories: problems of distortion and incoherence in

    Inferchange, 11, 5-23.

    21-47.

    21 1-237.

    1-124.

    recent Marxist analyses of education, British Journal o Sociology

    of

    Education, 3, 107-126.

  • 7/25/2019 Journal of Philosophy of Education Volume 17 Issue 2 1983 [Doi 10.1111%2Fj.1467-9752.1983.Tb00031.x] David

    http:///reader/full/journal-of-philosophy-of-education-volume-17-issue-2-1983-doi-1011112fj1467-97521983tb000 12/12

    218 D. Gordon

    HARGREAVES,AVIDH., HESTOR,STEPHENK.

    MELLOR, RANK . 1975) Deviance in Classrooms London,

    HART,H.L.A.

    1961) The Concept of Law

    Oxford, Oxford University Press).

    HAYEK, RIEDRICH,. VON 1973) Law , Legislation and Liberty, Vol. London, Routledge Kegan Paul).

    JACKSON,HILIPW.

    1968)

    L f e in Classrooms

    New York, Holt, Rinehart Winston).

    JENKINS,REDELL,

    1980) Social Order and the Limits of Law

    Princeton, Princeton University Press).

    KOHLBERG,AWRENCE1970) The moral atmosphere

    of

    the school, in: OVERLY, ORMAN. Ed.) The Unstudied

    Curriculum: Its impact on children,

    pp.

    105-127

    Washington, Association for Supervision and Curriculum

    Development, NEA).

    KOHLBERG,AWRENCE1971) From

    is

    to ought: how to commit the naturalistic fallacy and get away with it in the

    study of moral development,

    in:

    MISCHEL, HEODOREEd.)

    Cognitive Development and Epistemologv,

    pp.

    15 1-235

    New York, Academic Press).

    MARTIN, ANER. 1976) What should we do with a hidden curriculum when we find one? Curriculum Inquiry, 6,

    135-1

    5 1.

    ORMELL,HRISTOPHER

    1978)

    Is there a hidden curriculum in mathematics? in: RICHARDS,OLINEd.)

    Power an d the

    Curriculum: Issues in Curriculum studies, pp. 109-1 16 Nafferton, Driffield, Nafferton Books).

    POWER, LARK

    1981)

    Moral education through the development

    of

    the moral atmosphere

    of

    the school, Journal

    of

    Educational Thought, 15, 4-19.

    SCHWAB,OSEPH .

    1962)

    The teaching of science as enquiry, in: SCHWAB,OSEPH . BRANDWEIN,AUL,

    The

    Teaching

    of

    Science,

    pp.

    2-103

    Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Press).

    STRAUGHAN,OGER

    1982)

    Whats the point of rules?

    Journal of Philosophy

    of

    Education, 16, 63-68.

    STRIKE,KENNETH . 1979) The role of theories of justice in evaluation: why a house is not a home, Educational

    WEBER,MAX

    1954) On Law in Economy and Soc ieq

    Cambridge, Mass, Harvard University Press).

    WILLIS, AUL1977) Learning to La bour London, Saxon House).

    Routledge Kegan Paul).

    Theory,

    29, 1-9.