Top Banner
Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economics Roger E. Backhouse and Tamotsu Nisizawa Version 17, December 2006 1. Placing welfare economics in context The standard history of welfare economics in the early decades of the twentieth century needs to be rewritten. It runs in terms of a conflict between two traditions, one associated with Pigou, the other with Pareto. 1 Until the 1930s, so the story goes, welfare economics was dominated by A. C. Pigou, whose two books, Wealth and Welfare (1914) and The Economics of Welfare (1920, 1932) effectively defined the subject. It was aggregative and based on utilitarianism, its ancestry going back, through Marshall and Sidgwick, to Bentham and the English utilitarians of the mid-nineteenth century. This “Cambridge” approach to welfare economics was based on the assumption that different individuals utilities could be measured and compared with each other. Against this was set what remained, till the 1930s, a continental European tradition, associated primarily with Pareto, but with its origins in Walras. In this tradition, there was no need to compare utilities, 1 For examples of such accounts see Blaug (1997), Backhouse (1985).
26

Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economicskomine/hope/backnishi0612.pdf · Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economics Roger E. Backhouse and

Jul 02, 2018

Download

Documents

dangkhanh
Welcome message from author
This document is posted to help you gain knowledge. Please leave a comment to let me know what you think about it! Share it to your friends and learn new things together.
Transcript
Page 1: Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economicskomine/hope/backnishi0612.pdf · Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economics Roger E. Backhouse and

Introduction: reinterpreting the

history of welfare economics

Roger E. Backhouse

and

Tamotsu Nisizawa

Version 17, December 2006

1. Placing welfare economics in context

The standard history of welfare economics in the early decades of the twentieth century needs to be

rewritten. It runs in terms of a conflict between two traditions, one associated with Pigou, the other

with Pareto.1 Until the 1930s, so the story goes, welfare economics was dominated by A. C. Pigou,

whose two books, Wealth and Welfare (1914) and The Economics of Welfare (1920, 1932)

effectively defined the subject. It was aggregative and based on utilitarianism, its ancestry going

back, through Marshall and Sidgwick, to Bentham and the English utilitarians of the mid-nineteenth

century. This “Cambridge” approach to welfare economics was based on the assumption that

different individuals utilities could be measured and compared with each other. Against this was set

what remained, till the 1930s, a continental European tradition, associated primarily with Pareto,

but with its origins in Walras. In this tradition, there was no need to compare utilities,

1 For examples of such accounts see Blaug (1997), Backhouse (1985).

Page 2: Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economicskomine/hope/backnishi0612.pdf · Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economics Roger E. Backhouse and

differentiating it sharply from the Pigovian approach. Around 1930, English-speaking economists

took up the Paretian approach, showing that not only was there no scientific basis for interpersonal

comparisons of utility, there was no need for such comparisons. All the significant results of

welfare economics could be derived, using techniques such as indifference curves and revealed

preference. The key figure in this change, at least in Britain, was Lionel Robbins, whose Essay on

the Nature and Significance of Economic Science (1932, 1935) effectively served as a death notice

for Pigovian welfare economics, ushering in the so-called New Welfare economics, from which the

route into modern welfare economics can be traced.

We argue that welfare economics needs to be placed in a much broader context because doing so

not only helps explain the way it arose but also offers a very different perspective on the changes in

the subject that took place during this period. The most important elements in this context were the

following. Firstly, welfare economics arose at a time when academic disciplines were becoming

professionalized, as disciplines pursued by specialists within universities. Secondly, this was the

time when the foundations of the British welfare state were being laid. Finally, welfare economics

was not yet completely separated from religion. Our claim is that the history of welfare economics

is significantly distorted if it is told apart from this context. Welfare economics was a broader, more

pluralistic, endeavour than the conventional story implies, in which economists on the fringes of

academia played a role that, according to contemporaries, was as important as that played by

academics; and it was based on a much broader range of philosophical positions. This broader

history leads to a radically different viewpoint, in which the similarities between Cambridge

welfare economics, in particular Pigou’s welfare economics, and the approach inspired by Pareto

and endorsed by Robbins appear much more significant than the differences. They both sought to

render the study of economics scientific, through excluding ethical judgements that many of their

contemporaries were prepared to make. Furthermore, Pigou distanced himself considerably from

utilitarianism and even welfarism: paradoxically his main critic, Hobson used utilitarian arguments

in his critique of Pigou.

Page 3: Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economicskomine/hope/backnishi0612.pdf · Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economics Roger E. Backhouse and

We start by outlining, in Section 2, the economists who were involved in discussions of welfare

during this period, and their position in relation to, on the one side, professional academic

economics and, on the other side, to providing the intellectual case for the welfare state. We then

turn, in Section 3, to the philosophical views that inspired them. From there we paint a broader

picture of welfare economics as a field, to which academics and various types of practitioner

contributed, that we describe as pluralism in welfare economics. That pluralism is then analysed

through discussing first Cambridge welfare economics (section 4) and second Oxford welfare

economics and the welfare state (section 5). The asymmetry in the headings of these two sections

arises because Oxford economists, in addition to contributing to welfare economics as the term was

understood at the time, also became involved, to a greater extent than Cambridge economists, in

the movement towards the welfare state . The effect of Robbins’s Essay on welfare economics is

discussed in section 7. The final section draws more wide ranging conclusions, relating to both

welfare economics and the welfare state.

2. Economists, the academy and politics

The story of welfare economics from the 1870s to the First World War centres on two figures:

Henry Sidgwick (at Cambridge) and Thomas Hill Green (at Oxford). They were friends from an

early age, whose careers had much in common. Both contributed to establishing ethics as an

academic discipline, Sidgwick through his Methods of Ethics (1874), Green through his teaching at

Balliol and, to a lesser extent, through his posthumous Prolegomena to Ethics (1883),2 and both

were members of the group of “academic liberals” who entered politics in the 1860s. In their

different ways, both were inspirational figures for their generation.3 However, their careers also

diverged in ways that, quite apart from their philosophical differences, considered in detail in

Section 3, help explain the difference between the welfare economics that came out of Cambridge

and Oxford.

2 See Richter (1964: **). 3 Richter on Green; check Schultz on Sidgwick. Also Leavis on Sidgwick?

Page 4: Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economicskomine/hope/backnishi0612.pdf · Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economics Roger E. Backhouse and

Sidgwick and Green were both members of the group of “academic Liberals” who sought to

enter politics in the 1860s. Faced with the extension of the franchise to the working class, a process

started with the 1867 Reform Act, they believed that academics had an obligation both to help

educate the new electorate and to provide enlightened leadership. Education for newly-enfranchised

adults was provided by the university extension movement. Leadership was to be provided by

academics standing for Parliament. They were radicals, successors to the earlier Philosophic

Radicals, wanting reform of society, in particular to reduce the role of the Church and the

aristocracy. In 1868, nineteen of their number were elected and they were full of hope that

Gladstone’s administration would fulfil this aim of reforming society on a rational basis. However,

these hopes were rapidly dashed when it became clear that religious interests were still sufficiently

strong to prevent the educational reforms that were needed. An Education Act was passed in 1870,

but the radicals felt let down because it left the Churches in a strong position in providing education.

Gladstone regrouped the Liberal Party, it was on the basis of foreign policy. The new electorate was

revealed as conservative, and a barrier to reform. It was necessary to find a new way forward.

Another of the academic Liberals, Leslie Stephen, assessed the problem in the following terms:

For a solid reform therefore we must look to the gradual infiltration of sound beliefs

through the whole social organism, which must end by bearing the fruit of an intelligent

loyalty to trustworthy leaders. The change must be inward before it can be outward: no

shuffling of the cards can make them all turn up trumps; it is a new force that is required,

not a new machinery; and all constitution-mongering is thrown away till a new spirit

has been breathed into the dead bones. (Stephen [1875], quoted in Harvie 1976: 198)

The relation between academia and politics needed to be re-assessed. In order to bring about this

“inward” change, many Liberals retreated from Parliament, and resorted to single issue politics –

the temperance movement, public health, public education and poor relief.

Sidgwick’s response was to explore the foundations of ethics, political economy and politics in a

series of thorough tomes, each offering a meticulous analysis of the problem in hand. In response to

Page 5: Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economicskomine/hope/backnishi0612.pdf · Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economics Roger E. Backhouse and

Marshall’s comment that his lectures failed to attract more than a handful of students (in contrast to

the hundreds who were inspired by Green) Sidgwick responded [*** get quote from Harvie]. He

laid the foundations for the Cambridge School of economics. Not only can Cambridge welfare

economics be traced from Sidgwick through Marshall to Pigou, Sidgwick began the process

whereby economists became academic experts, distancing themselves from direct political

involvement. Sidgwick’s Principles of Political Economy (1883[1901]) used utilitarian arguments

to make a case for government intervention that went beyond what his predecessors, such as Mill,

had advocated, but he remained conservative in his outlook. Though briefly entertaining socialism

in the ****, he soon to more traditional Liberal views. Thus he was involved in the Charity

Organisation Society (COS) an organisation established in 1869 to tackle the problem of poverty by

ensuring that poor relief was not handed out inappropriately, undermining its recipients’ ability to

help themselves through harming their moral character.

Green also “retreated” to academia, and shared many of Sidgwick’s classical Liberal views.

However, his teaching in Balliol had a very different effect. Unlike Sidgwick, Green remained

within the Church of England, seeking to reinterpret Christianity as an ethical creed. Students came

might come away from his lectures without having understood a word, but inspired by the call of

duty. This consciously moral outlook on social problems was reinforced by John Ruskin, who

became Professor of Fine Arts in 1869, offering a denunciation of the life-threatening values of

commercial society and political economy. Perhaps their most influential student was Arnold

Tonybee whose lectures on the industrial revolution used history to reinforce the the moral critique

of capitalist society, though, like his teacher, Green, he resisted socialism: reform was to come

about through improvement of character. He threw himself into the university settlement movement,

and after his death, in 1883, at the age of 30, he was lionised as if a martyr. The combination of

Green, Ruskin and Toynbee inspired a generation of students, including many historically-minded

economists whose careers were dominated by questions of social reform.. Even more than their

Cambridge counterparts, many of them went into the extension and settlement movements,

Page 6: Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economicskomine/hope/backnishi0612.pdf · Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economics Roger E. Backhouse and

exemplified by Toynbee trust and Toynbee Hall. Some retained Green’s liberal values, but others

moved in a more collectivist direction, especially after the “bitter cry of outcast London” came to

their attention in the 1880s (see Stedman Jones 1984). Bernard Bosanquet and J.H. Muirhead, like

Sidgwick, were supporters of the COS. John Atkinson Hobson, Leonard Hobhouse and Graham

Wallas moved towards the Fabians (though Hobson remained a Cobdenite Liberal in many

respects). Of these, ‘The two Hobs’ became the leading intellectual spokesmen for a New

Liberalism of social reform (Clarke 1996: 43).

In contrast, the Cambridge welfare economists became professional, academic economists in the

modern sense. This was particularly so in Pigou’s case; while Marshall attempted the

professionalization of economics in general, Pigou did for the economics of welfare, whose

‘official’ history starts with Pigou. Marshall’s Principles begins by trying to show that what is good

for economic man is normally good for ‘total man’; Pigou’s Wealth and Welfare begins by

postulating this. The battle to professionalize economics was primarily a battle between those who

saw it as a discipline comparable to the natural sciences and those who saw it as an adjunct to

immediate social reform, the absolutist ‘trait’ method and the historical-relativist method (Maloney

1985, 183-4, 232). They sought to observe the positive-normative distinction and engaged in

economic analysis that was separate from their policy advice. This analysis might be comprise dry

logical dissection of problems (as in Sidgwick’s major books) or technical, mathematical arguments

such as used by Marshall, or Pigou, or it might be analysis of specific problems of policy. A major

exception was the Tariff Reform Campaign of 1903, where Marshall, Pigou and others sought to

enter political controversy directly. Even here, however, they were seeking (with disastrous

consequences) to impose the authority of an economic science that lay above the political arena.

In contrast, the Oxford economists and their students became involved much more in

organisations designed to have a direct influence on policy or social reform. They might not seek to

enter Parliament, but they did not retreat into academia; some became bureaucrats (for example,

Llewellyn Smith, Michael Sadler, Beveridge) whilst others went into journalism (for example,

Page 7: Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economicskomine/hope/backnishi0612.pdf · Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economics Roger E. Backhouse and

Hobson and Hobhouse). They became involved in groupings such as the New Liberals and the

Fabian Society. Hobson and Hobhouse worked alongside politicians such as Samuel and Haldane

(both Ministers in Asquith’s 1906 government) and Ramsey McDonald (later Labour Prime

Minister). Olivier and Graham Wallas (both Oxford products) founded the Fabian Society with

George Bernard Shaw and Sidney Webb. Perhaps more significant, there was no demarcation

between the economic and the political; they were political economists in a fairly literal meaning of

the term. This overlap of the political and the economic is shown most clearly in Hobson’s writing,

where his ideas on welfare were developed not only in books that addressed the problem

specifically, such as Work and Wealth (1914) but also in clearly political writings such as The

Crisis of Liberalism (1909) or The Social Problem (1901), or in the close cooperation that

developed between him, Hobhouse (who became Professor of Sociology at LSE) and Wallas (a

Professor of Political Science). A similar difference in attitude is also found in economic and social

history. John and Barbara Hammond, and R.H. Tawney, history could, in the tradition of Toynbee’s

Lectures on the Industrial Revolution, be used to make a clearly political point.. In the twentieth

century many of this group were linked to LSE and they provided many of those whom Hamilton

labelled ‘the English school of welfare economics’ (Hamilton 1919: 318).

In arguing that these two strands of thought – welfare economics and the welfare state – need to

be considered alongside each other because they involved overlapping communities and that

contemporaries did not draw the same dividing line as do modern economists, and in arguing that

a crucial distinction that needs to be made in this context is between Cambridge and Oxford, there

are several points that it is important to remember. The first of these is that, though it can be argued

that ideas coming out of Oxford had more effect on politicians, and hence on the movement towards

the welfare state, influence is hard to establish. For example, it has been argued that Hobson’s

arguments about the surplus had more effect on the move towards progressive taxation in Lloyd

George’s ‘People’s budget’ of 1908 than more orthodox utilitarian arguments. Hobson did move in

the circles frequented by decision makers, and his views were certainly more important in

Page 8: Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economicskomine/hope/backnishi0612.pdf · Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economics Roger E. Backhouse and

influencing the climate of opinion on taxation than his almost complete neglect among historians of

academic economics would suggest. However, politicians pick up ideas from surprising sources.

Toye (this volume) illustrates this by showing that Churchill and Lloyd George may have been

persuaded to adopt certain welfare policies, not as a result of arguments by economists (however

broadly defined) but by H. G. Wells. Wells, of course, was associated with the Fabians and thereby

with the Oxford side of the division discussed here, but he was by no stretch of the imagination an

Oxford economist. In his hands, ideas were given new twists. In the same way, Sidney and Beatrice

Webb, who had even stronger connections, through LSE, with Oxford economists, and of whom

Sidney was classified by Hamilton as a welfare economist (as was Cannan, another link between

Oxford and LSE ), were not themselves from that tradition.

3. Idealism, utilitarianism and morality

The two men who like at the roots of this period’s welfare economics, Sidgwick and Green, offered

contrasting philosophical foundations for the subject: utilitarianism and idealism. However, despite

this, they were both responding to the mid-Victorian loss of religious faith caused by the results of

biblical criticism emanating from Germany and the evolutionary ideas associated with Charles

Darwin and Herbert Spencer. They both struggled with this crisis of faith, the problems they faced

resonating with those of their friends and students. Sidgwick is renowned for, in Keynes’s words,

never doing anything but ‘wonder whether Christianity was true and prove that it wasn’t and hope

that it was’.4 He sought, though his involvement in spiritualism, to recover the supernatural

element lost with traditional Christianity; in his philosophy he sought to find a secular basis for

ethics. Green, in contrast, sought to accommodate Christianity to the new developments: to

reinterpret the Christian religion as a system of ethics that could stand independently of Christian

dogma. In doing this, Sidgwick turned to the utilitarianism of Bentham and Mill, and Green, to the

idealism of Kant and Hegel.

4 Quoted by Harrod (1951: 116-7). Cf. Richter (1964: 138).

Page 9: Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economicskomine/hope/backnishi0612.pdf · Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economics Roger E. Backhouse and

Sidgwick’s great work on utilitarianism was The Methods of Ethics (1874), a book which

arguably changed the direction of moral philosophy away from discussion of ethical judgements

themselves to discussion of the principles on which ethical judgements should be based.5 Though it

argued the case for utilitarianism, it posed clearly the dilemma that dominated his ethical thought.

He could not find a decisive reason why utilitarianism was better than egoism as a criterion for

moral judgement. This meant that utilitarianism, the purpose of which was to provide a justification

for ethical judgements, rested on an intuition. He might claim that this was an intuition shared by

the relevant community – that there was a consensus among experts – but he had not provided a

rational argument that should persuade a sceptic who did not share this intuition.

In contrast, Green was known as much for the ethics he espoused as for the philosophical basis

on which he sought to ground them. It was not unusual for students attending his lectures to be

baffled by the technical arguments, but to come away impressed with the speaker’s sincerity and

passion: Green ‘transmitted earnestness with a charismatic force’ (Clarke 1978: 13). His ethics was

one of social reform: challenging the Evangelical claim that faith was a matter of personal piety.

This social gospel, to use an anachronistic term, was not new, but Green, unlike earlier Methodists

and High Church figures, was dissociating it from traditional theological doctrines. In one of his

highly influential lay sermons, one of the few things published before his death, Green concluded

that though criticism had invalidated much traditional Christian doctrine, ‘it is not the reality of God

or of the ideal law of conduct that is in question, but the adequacy of our modes of expressing them’

(Green 1888: 276). He went on to claim that ‘Faith in God and duty will survive much doubt’. It

was an ethic of self-sacrifice, for ‘if once we have come to acquiesce in such a standard of living as

must make us wish God and duty to be illusions, it must surely die’. The pairing of God and duty

(twice in the last two sentence of his sermon) reflected a sense of duty that Sidgwick would

wholeheartedly have endorsed, but such language was far from anything Sidgwick would have used.

The philosophical basis on which Green sought to base this Christianity-as-ethics was idealism, 5 This has been discussed in much more detail in Backhouse (2006), which contains further references. The principal

ones are Schultz (2004) and Schneewind (1977). See also Collini (2001).

Page 10: Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economicskomine/hope/backnishi0612.pdf · Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economics Roger E. Backhouse and

taken from Kant and Hegel. In Hegel’s hands, idealism was a conservative doctrine, but Green

sought to turn it around and use it to ground social reform.

Green adapted idealism to the needs of those who wanted justification for the moral

code of their parents; he gave conscience a social and political meaning, and gave an

outlet to the strong sense of duty and obligation to serve, so characteristic of his

generation. (Richter 1964: 12)

For Green, the world was the realization of a spiritual principle: an eternal consciousness (God) was

realizing itself gradually but imperfectly in the human organism. Moral good was the realization of

moral capability.6 Because the process was imperfect, people had a duty to help bring it about. In

so doing, people were realizing their true freedom, doing not simply what they wanted to do, but

fulfilling one’s capabilities according to the divine plan, or doing what was it was rational to do.

This view of freedom in terms of identification with an ultimate end has been seen as justifying

totalitarianism (cf. Popper 1945). What frees Green from this charge is the values he placed at the

centre of this process. He was committed to democracy and freedom; he argued that one had to

recognise the rights of others and that the community had obligations to its members; he believed in

social harmony. It was a major flaw in his philosophy is that these ethical principles were arguably

not based on reason so much as on a will to believe. Yes this will to believe was characteristic of

men of his generation for whom traditional Christian doctrines had become untenable. The idea that

freedom meant freedom to do something worthwhile – that duty called for self-sacrifice – was what

many of them wanted to hear. One of those who picked up this message was Arnold Toynbee, a

student at Balliol from 1875-8, and who was on the verge of taking up a Fellowship there when he

died, in 1883 at the age of 30. The spirit of Green’s religion was captured in the settlement

movement, in which Toynbee had become involved, which involved middle class men moving into

the slums and working alongside people there. The most influential such settlement was Toynbee

Hall, in the East End of London, names in his memory. 6 This and the following two paragraphs draw very heavily on Richter 1964.

Page 11: Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economicskomine/hope/backnishi0612.pdf · Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economics Roger E. Backhouse and

Some of Green’s students took up his idealistic philosophy, R. L. Nettleship, J. H. Muirhead,

Bernard Bosanquet and F. H. Bradley being the most prominent. However, what was more

important was that it was not simply a philosophical doctrine, but its influence was felt far more

widely than that. One of the remarkable aspects of Green’s influence was its breadth. It lay beneath

the substantially secular London Ethical Society, as well as the Christian Social Union and the

Anglo-Catholic Lux Mundi movement. Politically, Green’s influence was also diverse. Bosanquet,

C. S. Loch and the Charity Organisation Society focused on the reform of character: the aim of the

COS was to making sure poor relief did not harm character by going to the undeserving poor. In

contrast, for others such as the New Liberals, Hobhouse and Hobson, the effect of Green’s

philosophy was to liberate them from the individualism of the Manchester School and

nonconformist religion. Though the Cambridge School never took up Green’s idealistic philosophy,

they shared many of his ideals. Sidgwick and Green were close friends. Marshall was exposed to

Green’s lecturing in his year at Oxford and spent significant time studying Kant and Hegel.

Marshall himself was an admirer of Toynbee and was a Trustee of Toynbee Hall. Students from

Cambridge as well as Oxford flocked into the settlement movement.

A vital additional ingredient added to the intellectual and emotional stimulation coming from

Sidgwick and Green was provided by Ruskin. His influence was so strong that one historian has

gone so far as to claim that ‘It would be difficult to overestimate Ruskin’s position as cultural hero

at Oxford in the 1870s’ (Kadish 1982: 32). Ruskin was neither Liberal (many of his views were

extremely conservative) nor a philosopher, at least in the technical sense, but the moral values

found in his analysis of culture and society could be used to offer a profound challenge to the values

of political economy. Unto This Last, which first appeared in 1860 as ‘four essays on the first

principles of political economy’, had as its stated aim to give ‘a logical definition of WEALTH’ for

the first time in plain English. Following on from this, its second aim was to show that the

acquisition of wealth was possible under certain moral conditions of society (Ruskin 1994: vii-ix).

Ruskin defined value as ‘to avail towards life’ and declared that it was an intrinsic quality of things.

Page 12: Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economicskomine/hope/backnishi0612.pdf · Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economics Roger E. Backhouse and

What varied greatly was the ability to appreciate and to use the valuable: Wealth was ‘The

possession of the valuable by the valiant’ (Ruskin 1994: 118, 125).7 In final part he put it in one of

his best known remarks: ‘There is no wealth but life. Life. , Life including all its powers of love, of

joy, and of admiiration’ (Ruskin 1994: 156).8

4. Pluralism in welfare economics

In the period from around the 1880s to the 1920s, ideas on welfare economics were being

developed by academic economists, concerned to give economics the authority of a science, by

other academics pursuing the subject as part of a political analysis that could provide a framework

for transforming British society, by political activists outside, or on the fringes of academia, and by

administrators seeking administrative solutions to social problems. Arguments were based on

utilitarianism, idealist philosophy, the moralism of Ruskin and on moral values taken straight from

religion. Clearly, much of the resulting literature did not meet the academic standards laid down by

Marshall and Pigou and, making judgements foreign to those of modern economics, does not look

like welfare economics as it is understood today. However, it would be anachronistic to use modern

standards to demarcate part of this literature as welfare economics and the rest as something else

(such as political or religious tracts).

Evidence for this view comes from outside observers. When Walton Hamilton (1919) wrote of

the English welfare school, be listed “Webb, Hobson, Cannan, Tawney and Clay” (Hamilton 1919:

318).9 Whatever the reasons for his exclusion of Pigou, Hamilton was associating with the idea of

welfare economics a group comprising both academics and political activists involved in moves

towards the welfare state. This was a group with whom he and his institutionalist colleagues in the

United States had extensive links (see Rutherford, forthcoming). Similarly, Wesley Mitchell, in his

lectures of 1919, also associated welfare not with Pigou but with Hobson. Paul Homan (1928) picks

7 The entire phrase is capitalised in the original. 8 The first seven words are capitalised in the original. 9 Which Webb is not specified, but presumably Sidney.

Page 13: Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economicskomine/hope/backnishi0612.pdf · Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economics Roger E. Backhouse and

out Hobson as representing welfare economics. Outside Europe and the United States, the Japanese

economist, Fukuda, and the Chinese economist Liu, also found inspiration for their welfare

economics not in Pigou but in Hobson and Oxford idealism (see Nishizawa, below). It was perhaps

no accident that Fukuda shared with Hamilton and Mitchell an institutional, ethical way of

thinking that went back to the German historical school.

Almost paradoxically, further evidence is provided in Robbins’s Essay (1932), over a decade

later, where it is clear that the main target is not Pigou (who receives only brief criticism, on what

might be seen as a technical point) but Stamp, Hobson, Hawtrey and Cannan. Hobson, significantly,

appears in both this list and Hamilton’s and Fukuda’s. The significant point here is that both

Hamilton and Robbins are associating with welfare economics thinkers who, today, would not be

taken seriously as welfare economists. The conclusion that should be drawn is that, in this period,

welfare economics, in so far as it is appropriate to use the term to describe a body of literature that

was not a precisely defined discipline, was pluralistic: it was approached in a wide variety of ways.

As is argued below, the significance of Robbins’s Essay lies in the effect it had on this diverse,

pluralistic field, not in any dispute with the Cambridge school.

4. Cambridge welfare economics

The conventional story of Cambridge welfare economics is too well known to require recounting in

any detail.10 It runs from Sidgwick, who, though still very classical in his general approach to

economics, used the notion that price was equal to marginal (not average) utility to argue for a

distinction between two measures of wealth, one calculated through valuing goods at their market

prices, the other through valuing them according to their average utilities. These two concepts were

the basis for Pigou’s later title, Wealth and Welfare (1912). It was Marshall who, through his

concept of consumers’ surplus, proposed a method whereby welfare (or at least changes in welfare)

could be measured. Pigou then proposed a more general analytical framework through

10 See for example Blaug 1997.

Page 14: Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economicskomine/hope/backnishi0612.pdf · Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economics Roger E. Backhouse and

distinguishing social costs and benefits from their private counterparts. In the hands of the

Cambridge economists, the list of exceptions to laissez-faire, for which government action to

remedy market failure, was greatly enlarged, first by Sidgwick and then by Pigou, in comparison to

those recognised by Mill. Blaug (1997:***) went so far as to claim that Pigou provided a virtual

blueprint for the welfare state. The Cambridge economists thus used an aggregative, utilitarian

framework to show how the state should intervene if welfare was to be maximized.

Though the conventional view clearly has some basis, but needs extensive qualification and

revision. Though Mill was a utilitarian, he argues that individual liberty was paramount, which

narrowed the scope of the utilitarian criterion: Sidgwick applied utilitarian arguments more

consistently, arguing that in some cases they might trump arguments from liberty (Medema

forthcoming). However, though Sidgwick worked out the implications of utilitarianism, in the

absence of any quantitative evidence that might indicate the point at which the costs and benefits of

utilitarianism might be balanced, he retreated from its implications, being fearful of the effects of

redistribution on incentives (Backhouse 2006). In practice, therefore, he adopted a view that was

more conservative, particularly in regards to distribution, than his utilitarianism would have

suggested.

Marshall too, as Groenewegen (this volume) points out, held similarly conservative views on

social policy: like Sidgwick, they were both supporters of the position held by the Charity

Organisation Society, which focused on making sure that poor relief was given in such a way that it

did not undermine the incentive to work. A dimension that Marshall added was that poor relief

might serve to improve character, thereby raising productivity and possibly even paying for itself.

Though he failed to anticipate the commitment to health provision that became one of the central

elements of the welfare state, his emphasis on education moved in that direction. It fitted in with the

emphasis, apparent in his application of consumers’ surplus analysis, on the importance of

exploiting opportunities provided by increasing returns. Groenwegen points out that, though he was

aware of the technical problems with his proposal for using a system of taxes and bounties to shift

Page 15: Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economicskomine/hope/backnishi0612.pdf · Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economics Roger E. Backhouse and

resources into industries that exhibited increasing returns, his belief in the growth potential arising

from increasing returns was so strong that he would not abandon the idea. There were thus two

Marshalls. The pessimistic Marshall, evident in his public statements on the poor laws in the early

1990s, and his support for the Charity Organisation Society, was, like Sidgwick, very cautious and

concerned not to undermine character through perverse incentives. The optimistic Marshall, on the

other hand, saw the potential for raising productivity through education and exploitation of

increasing returns. It was the optimistic Marshall who wrote on economic chivalry in 1907 and in

the final edition of the Principles.

It is with Pigou that the problems with the conventional view are perhaps greatest. Suzumura

(this volume) and Backhouse (this volume) point out that Pigou, though conducting much of his

analysis within a utilitarian framework that has many classical features (such as aggregative

analysis and focusing on weighing utility costs and benefits of various interventions) distanced

himself considerably from utilitarianism. His use of the terms ‘satisfaction’ and ‘desiredness’

rather than ‘utility’ was significant. Furthermore, like Sidgwick, he drew back from many of the

implications of his utilitarianism – implications to which contemporaries such as Hobson attached

great significance. His reasons for doing so may have been pragmatic – that to assume that

variations in wealth were in practice a good indicator of variations in welfare was to make possible

‘scientific’ analysis of welfare – but they nonetheless served to distance Pigou from utiliarianism.

There is also a great problem with the notion, particularly strong in the public choice tradition,

that the Cambridge economists had an excessively rosy view of the possibilities for state action.

The caution Groenewegen (this volume) identifies in Marshall reflects this. But this caution was

part of a wide-ranging doubt about the scope for government action, which recognised (as does

modern public choice literature) that government action was taken by politicians and bureaucrats,

who were not only imperfect but had their own interests. There was a belief that the capabilities of

the state were increasing, and that it could do significantly more than in the early nineteenth

century, but its competence was still very limited. These remarks apply to Sidgwick, Marshall and

Page 16: Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economicskomine/hope/backnishi0612.pdf · Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economics Roger E. Backhouse and

Pigou (Backhouse and Medema 2006). Medema (this volume) shows that when it came to applying

his ideas, Pigou did not think, as the conventional picture suggests, of a sharp distinction between

laissez-faire and state action, the latter being required only when market failures prevented laissez-

faire from working properly. His argument was that laissez-faire was beneficial only because

human institutions had been arranged to that it was so. Thus state intervention was not something

apart from what was involved in all markets.

There is, in roughout the work of the Cambridge economists there is an attempt to construct

welfare economics on scientific foundations. Sidgwick is important in philosophy because he

moved ethics away from analysing what was or was not ethical behaviour into the analysis of the

foundations on which ethical judgements might rest. His aim, therefore, was to ground ethics, and

hence discussions of welfare, on foundations that might be termed scientific. However, whilst he

clung to the intuition that utilitarianism could provided a ground for ethics, his successors in

Cambridge drew a different conclusion. Particularly influential on Cambridge economics was G. E.

Moore, who renounced utilitarianism completely. For Moore, good and bad were elementary

qualities, apprehended directly: they could not be reduced to any other qualities. The principle

underlying utilitarianism, that moral worth derived from something else, was flawed.

The Cambridge economist to explore this Mooreian analysis furthest was Ralph Hawtrey,

towards the end of a general treatise on economics, The Economic Problem (1926). Though he

accepted that ‘economics cannot be dissociated from ethics’ Hawtrey (1926: 184), his ethics was

directly influenced by Moore: utilitarianism was flawed, for it presumed that pleasure or

happiness was the right end to pursue. This was not necessarily true, and to think so was to

participate in the ‘cult of individualism’ (Hawtrey 1926: 182). Welfare was, for Hawtrey, not an

aggregate of satisfactions: ‘The aggregate of satisfactions is not an aggregate of welfare at all. It

includes good satisfactions which are welfare, and bad satisfactions, which are the reverse’

(Hawtrey 1926: 215). Different individuals’ satisfactions are compared through feelings of approval

and disapproval, ‘which the course of evolution has planted in our nature in regard to certain classes

Page 17: Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economicskomine/hope/backnishi0612.pdf · Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economics Roger E. Backhouse and

of objects. ... In so far as other people have similar feelings of approval and disapproval, he and

they will find common ground in the search for a solution’ (Hawtrey 1926: 187). Welfare

judgements, therefore, had to be based on ‘the common ethical judgements of mankind’ – on those

judgements that are common to all ethical systems (Hawtrey 1926: 188). If mankind could not

agree, then Hawtrey had little to offer.

Though others would no doubt have differed from Hawtrey over the details, Hawtrey’s argument

against utilitarianism would have been shared by his Cambridge friends and fellow Apostles. The

most famous of them, Maynard Keynes, did not write on the theory of welfare, but his views would

not have been far from Hawtrey’s in relevant respects. Moore was his inspiration and he accepted

Moore’s rejection of utilitarianism. The good was an end in itself: activities were not good because

they yielded utility. This perspective would completely justify his drawing policy conclusions

directly from his economic theories: the value of maintaining a high and stable level of employment

was something that could be perceived directly, especially after the Great Depression. The same

was true of Beveridge’s scheme for social insurance. Unlike Pigou, he did not see the need for

offering utilitarian or other arguments as to why it was good to protect people from poverty. In his

discussions with Beveridge relating to the institutions of the welfare state (Marcuzzo, this volume)

he focused on the affordability of schemes for social insurance, but he did not adopt a Pigovian

approach of weighing its social costs and benefits against each other.

5. “Oxford” welfare economics and the welfare state

Oxford was dominated by idealism, as represented by Green and his disciples. Yet, although it is

arguable that idealist philosophy lay behind moves towards the welfare state in the early twentieth

century, its relationship with reform was very different from that between Cambridge utilitarianism

and the welfare state. Green’s ethics, as Shionoya (this volume) points out, was not collectivist (in

Page 18: Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economicskomine/hope/backnishi0612.pdf · Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economics Roger E. Backhouse and

many ways he was a traditional liberal) but neither was it purely individualistic, for he saw

individuals as developing and exercising their deliberative capacities in relation to other people.

Self-realisation was thus achieved in relation to the common aims of a wider society. Though one

might question whether this did more than express Green’s own ethical beliefs, it provided a

framework for thinking about questions of welfare that inspired many of his students. The

significant point, however, is that he inspired many who did not accept the idealist philosophy on

which his ethics were based. Thus, though it is possible to speak of an Oxford tradition,

encompassing those who came through Oxford, there was no direct link between idealism and what

Hamilton called the English welfare school (even though most of their number came from Oxford

amd though some them were explicitly idealists) comparable to that between utilitarianism and

Cambridge welfare economics. Though Oxford did produce economists who discussed questions of

welfare directly (notably Hobson, Clay and Tawney) it also produced those who were involved as

activists as much as thinkers (Bosanquet and Beveridge).

The most important of these Oxford economists was arguably Hobson (Backhouse, this volume).

Hobson’s starting point was to complete Ruskin’s task of determining what were life-giving things,

and to develop a human standard of value. He was never attracted to idealism, but shared with many

of his fellow Oxford graduates a historical and organic approach. However, whilst he was a critic of

Pigou, he was content to express himself in the language of utilitarianism: indeed, it is arguable that

Hobson was taking seriously the statements made by Pigou at the beginning of Wealth and Welfare

about how economic welfare was not the same as overall welfare. He used judgements inspired by

Ruskin to drive a wedge between economic and overall welfare where Pigou, having acknowledge

the distinction, proceeded to minimize its significance.. Language of organicism was radically

different from Pigou’s language, but in practice came close to Pigou’s social costs and benefits.

In making his critique, Hobson, inspired by Ruskin, was prepared to make a broader range of

value judgements than Pigou was prepared to make. He was aided in this because he was not

committed to being ‘scientific’: indeed, he explicitly attacked the idea of economic science, which

Page 19: Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economicskomine/hope/backnishi0612.pdf · Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economics Roger E. Backhouse and

he associated with quantification and a mistaken search for exactness, and hence as implying a

mechanical approach. To assess the relation between wealth and welfare, Hobson claimed, it was

necessary to rely on a very broad range of value judgements, not to reduce the comparison to

something mechanical. These values were based in consensus – in the common sense of mankind.

Though there were limits to such agreement, these limits were, he contended, much broader than

what his more orthodox contemporaries such as Pigou were willing to concede.

Henry Clay was another economist to come through the Oxford classics school. In a well-

received textbook, Economics: an Introduction for the General Reader (1916), he started from the

view that welfare depended on ethical views, and that it was nonsense to attempt to divorce the two.

He proceeded to explain why wealth and welfare might differ. One reason concerned what he called

the internal and external causes of welfare. The external causes of welfare are material goods,

whereas the internal causes are factors, internal to the individual, which determine wants. In that it

focused solely on the external causes of welfare, completely ignoring the internal causes,

conventional economics was materialistic. ‘Materialism is the subordination of the internal sources

of satisfaction to the external; most religions exalt the internal over the external, and teach that

welfare lies in the former, to which the latter must be sacrificed: ‘The Kingdom of Heaven is within

you.’ (Clay 1916: 447–8). This was enough to establish that the relation between wealth and

welfare was dependent on a system of ethics. In addition, however, he offered more technical

arguments, some of which overlapped with those recognised by Pigou, about why weath and

welfare might diverge, though his belief in the endogeneity of wants meant that he was more radical

in his conclusions.

An argument to which Clay paid much attention was the argument that the business system was

neutral, on the grounds that under a system of free enterprise activity will conform to the wants and

tastes of the time, and hence the ethical values of the time. A system of free enterprise took account

of demands and not needs; inequality in the distribution of income caused these to diverge, and

those ‘who subordinate everything else to money-getting will exercise the greatest influence’

Page 20: Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economicskomine/hope/backnishi0612.pdf · Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economics Roger E. Backhouse and

whereas those who ‘devote themselves to altruistic objects and neglect the pursuit of private wealth’

will have little influence (Clay 1916: 452). Furthermore, economic organisation interacts with

moral standards (1916: 455–60). Under free markets many receive incomes for which no service

has been provided (for example, the unearned increment of land values) which ‘obliterates’ the

distinction between ‘social and anti-social effort’: ‘wealth is respectable however won, and great

wealth is honoured, because it is powerful, whatever its source’ (1916: 460). The economic

organisation of his day strengthened materialistic tendencies at the expense of idealistic ones.

Clay’s critique of materialism has much in common with Tawney’s critique of ‘the acquisitive

society’ (Tawney 1920, 1921).11 Though they use different terminology, this similaritiy may not be

accidental, for Tawney was described by Clay (1916: ix) as one of the friends who had read a

substantial part of his manuscript. An acquisitive society was one where a priority was given to

protecting economic rights, in particular property rights, whilst leaving economic functions to fulfil

themselves (except under exceptional circumstances). Tawney argued that goods and activities had

to be judged according to the contribution made to the public purpose. People were not isolated

individuals but parts of societies that had common goals and purposes, or moral principles.

However, individualism had destroyed these moral principles and the purpose, without which

society could not exist. Utilitarianism did not provide such a purpose, for ‘to make happiness the

object of society is to resolve society itselt into the ambitions of numberless individuals, each

directed towards the attainment of some personal purpose’ (Tawney 1920: 17). The existence of a

common purpose provided a criterion by which to judge that some goods were better than others,

and that some should never have been produced at all.

However, whereas some Oxford-trained economists moved towards more ‘organic’ conceptions

of welfare, and were prepared to be critical of the capitalist system, others remained individualist.

Bosanquet, for example, though idealist in his philosophy (alone among those considered here)

remained committed to the liberalism of the Charity Organisation Society, opposing the attempt by

11 These represent three elaborations, at increasing length, of the same theme.

Page 21: Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economicskomine/hope/backnishi0612.pdf · Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economics Roger E. Backhouse and

the Webbs to replace the poor law with institutions closer to ones we now see as representing the

welfare state. (cf. McBriar 1987). Even if Tawney’s vision of a common purpose could be

interpreted in terms of idealism, his ideals were very different from Bosanquet’s. Another Oxford

economist who remained a Liberal, opposed to the Fabianism towards which many other Oxford

economists (Hobson, Hobhouse, Tawney) gravitated, but who nonetheless had a profound influence

on the welfare state, was Beveridge (see Komine, this volume). Though, early in his career, he

saw himself as socialist, and even engaged with the Fabians, he espoused a very individualistic

form of socialism, and for the rest of his career moved further away from it (Harris 1977: 88).

Beveridge exemplifies the way the Oxford of Green, Toynbee and their followers could inspire a

passion for social reform that could result in action that eventually proved conducive to the welfare

state. Beveridge’s genius lay in his ability His importance for the emergence of the welfare state lay

in his administrative abilities, which enabled him to work out schemes that would work. Although

their ethico-philosophical positions may have been different, he and Keynes were, as Marcuzzo

(this volume) shows, able to think along similar lines. Differences in the theory of employment

were more important.

7. Robbins and the science of welfare

The focus of Robbins’s Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science (1932) was on

economics as a science. In the field of welfare economics, it is conventional to focus on his

argument that inter-personal utility comparisons, even though they may be inescapable in policy

analysis, lie outside economic science, and to draw the conclusion that it was Pigou’s utilitarian

welfare economics that was the target. However, if we see the previous two decades’ welfare

economics as having diverse and pluralistic rather than monopolized by the Cambridge school, a

very different picture emerges, in which Robbins is very close to Pigou.

To see the force of Robbins’s argument about economic science, it is helpful to look at the

difference between Pigou and Hobson. As is argued here, their main difference did not lie in

Page 22: Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economicskomine/hope/backnishi0612.pdf · Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economics Roger E. Backhouse and

utilitarianism, for both used a framework that was, at the very least, strongly influenced by

utilitarianism: the real difference was that Pigou attached greater importance to being scientific,

even though this meant narrowing the scope of welfare economics. At the beginning of Wealth and

Welfare, Pigou argued that welfare comprised more than simply economic welfare:

Economic welfare, however, does not contain all welfare arising in this connection [the

earning and spending of the national dividend]. Various good and bad qualities

indirectly associated with income-getting and income-spending are excluded from it. It

does not include the whole psychic return, which emerges when the objective services

constituting the national dividend have passed through the factory of the body; it

includes only the psychic return of satisfaction. Thus economic welfare is, as it were, a

part of welfare. (Pigou 1912: 3-4; emphasis in original)

These were sentiments that Hobson (and many others influenced by Ruskin) endorsed

wholeheartedly: much of Work and Life was an exploration of precisely these differences between

what Pigou here calls ‘the whole psychic return’ and ‘the psychic return of satisfaction’. However,

after recognising these differences, Pigou goes on to minimize their importance, arguing that

economic welfare will generally be a good proxy for overall welfare. In other words, Pigou

drastically narrows the scope of his inquires in order to tackle them scientifically, making a much

narrower range of value judgements than those that Hobson, Clay, Tawney, Hawtrey and others

were thought it necessary to make.

Though he took it a stage further, this is exactly what Robbins was doing, a point that Hobson

saw very clearly.

Supporters of Pigou contend that, if we introduce distinctively ethical criteria, we and

ourselves in a region not merely outside measurable facts, but outside agreed facts. This

is clearly put by Mr. Lionel Robbins [1927: 176]. “It is not because we believe that our

science is exact that we wish to exclude ethics from our analysis, but because we wish

Page 23: Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economicskomine/hope/backnishi0612.pdf · Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economics Roger E. Backhouse and

to confine our investigations to a subject about which positive statement of any kind is

conceivable.” (Hobson 1929: 128).

Pigou and Robbins were both guilty of narrowing economics to what could be quantified and stated

exactly, which forced them to play down the differences between wealth and welfare.

Thus when Robbins argued for the confining economic science to matters that did not rest on

value judgements, he was continuing along a path already taken by Pigou. Thus his only explicit

criticism of Pigou does not relate to measurability of utility, but to his argument that the measuring

rod of money could be used to measure economic welfare (Robbins 1935: 2, 21). Robbins attacked

the confusion wrought by economists’ failure to distinguish sufficiently carefully between the

propositions of positive economic science and those that relied on ethical judgements He was not

arguing that economists should not make such judgements – to the contrary, he recognized that

policy advice required them – but that they were not part of positive economic science, which dealt

with the allocation of resources to achieve given ends. This was a criticism of the aggregative

approach of Pigovian welfare economics, where aggregation requires that interpersonal

comparisons of utility be made, even though Pigou had tried to avoid arguing in terms of utility.

6. Conclusions

We argue that welfare economics was, in the years before 1932, much more pluralistic than the

conventional story admits. Alongside Pigou and Pareto, there were economists who brought ethical

judgements different from Pigou’s into the subject, drawing its inspiration from a range of sources

among whom T. H. Green and John Ruskin were arguably the most influential. It also brings out the

parallels, neglected in the standard history, between Cambridge welfare economics and Oxford

idealism.

Rather than dismissing the work of the thinkers who inspired the welfare state as political

philosophers, or some other term that implies what they were doing was not welfare economics, we

Page 24: Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economicskomine/hope/backnishi0612.pdf · Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economics Roger E. Backhouse and

claim that they should be taken seriously as welfare economists, and that they were seen as such by

their contemporaries. What is conventionally considered welfare economics (the Cambridge

School’s work) has to be seen alongside a variety of other work that did not meet modern criteria of

what it means to do scientific economics. Although the terms ‘art’ and ‘science’ of economics were

well established by this date, the distinction between the arguments about the welfare state (part of

the art of economics) and welfare economics (the science) was not at all clear. It has been well-

established that it is mistaken to view Marshall through the lens of modern economics; this is even

truer of the profession as a whole, for the methodological conventions and distinctions that lie

beneath contemporary work were not then established.

Once this change of perspective is made, Robbins’s essay appears in a very different light. Its

prime aim was not to criticise Pigou, but to engage with and reject the ideas of this broader group of

thinkers whose ideas differed radically from those of either himself or Pigou. The effect of his essay

was to exclude from the discipline a group thinkers whose ideas had previously been considered

important contributors to welfare economics. Many of the thinkers whose work was thereby

excluded from the canon of welfare economics, came not from Cambridge but from Oxford. With

the reaction of philosophers, after Russell and Moore, against idealism, the philosophical

foundations of their work became invisible.

However, though their work was pushed out of welfare economics, the New Welfare Economics

of Hicks and others owing even less to their work than to Cambridge, it was thinkers coming out of

the Oxford tradition who arguably had most influence on the the set of policies that came to be

known as the welfare state. This group comprised not only philosophical idealists but those inspired

by Ruskin and the “rational bureaucrats” of whom Beveridge was the outstanding example. That

their moral arguments could not be proved and that they blurred what economists from Marshall to

Robbins thought were the proper boundaries of economic science, did not cause their ideas to lack

persuasive power. The thinkers, such as Hobson, the Webbs or Beveridge, who made the case for

the welfare state, are an important part of the history of welfare economics.

Page 25: Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economicskomine/hope/backnishi0612.pdf · Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economics Roger E. Backhouse and

References Backhouse, R. E. 1985. A History of Modern Economic Analysis. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. ---. 2006. Sidgwick, Marshall and the Cambridge School of economics. History of Political Economy 38 (1):15-44. Backhouse, R. E., and S. G. Medema. 2006. Public choice and the Cambridge school: a new view. Unpublished paper. Blaug, M. 1997. Economic Theory in Retrospect. 5th ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Clarke, P. 1978. Liberals and Social Democrats. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ---. 1996. Hope and Glory: Britain 1900-1990. London: Penguin Books. Clay, H. 1916. Economics: An Introduction for the General Reader. London: Macmillan. Collini, S. 2001. My roles and their duties: Sidgwick as philosopher, professor, and public moralist. In Henry Sidgwick. Proceedings of the British Academy, 109, ed. R. Harrison, 9-49. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Green, T. H. 1883. Prolegomena to Ethics. Edited by A. C. Bradley. Fifth edition 1907. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Hamilton, W. H. 1919. The institutional approach to economic theory. American Economic Review 9 (1):309-18. Harris, J. 1977. William Beveridge: A Biography. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Harrod, R. 1951. The Life of John Maynard Keynes. London: Macmillan. Harvie, C. 1976. The Lights of Liberalism. London: Allen Lane. Hawtrey, R. G. 1926. The Economic Problem. London: Longmans, Green. Hobson, J. A. 1909. The Crisis of Liberalism. Brighton: Harvester Press. Edited with an introduction by P. F. Clarke, 1974. ---. 1901. The Social Problem. : . ---. 1929. Wealth and Life. London: Macmillan. Homan, P. T. 1928. Contemporary Economic Thought. New York: Harper. Kadish, A. 1982. The Oxford Economists in the Late Nineteenth Century. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Maloney, J. 1985. Marshall, Orthodoxy and the Professionalization of Economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Page 26: Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economicskomine/hope/backnishi0612.pdf · Introduction: reinterpreting the history of welfare economics Roger E. Backhouse and

McBriar, A. M. 1987. An Edwardian Mixed Doubles: the Bosanquets versus the Webbs. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Pigou, A. C. 1912. Wealth and Welfare. London: Macmillan. ---. 1920. The Economics of Welfare. London: Macmillan. ---. 1932. The Economics of Welfare. 4th ed. London: Macmillan. Reprinted 1946. Popper, K. R. 1945. The Open Society and its Enemies. 2 vols. London: Routledge. Richter, M. 1964. The Politics of Conscience: T. H. Green and His Age. London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson. Robbins, L. C. 1927. Mr. Hawtrey on the scope of economics. Economica 20:172-78. ---. 1932. An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science. London: Macmillan. ---. 1935. An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science. 2nd ed. London: Macmillan. Rutherford, M. forthcoming. Institutionalism and its English connections. European Journal of the History of Economic Thought. Schneewind, J. B. 1977. Sidgwick's Ethics and Victorian Moral Philosophy. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Schultz, B. 2004. Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Sidgwick, H. 1874. The Methods of Ethics. London: Macmillan. Stedman Jones, G. 1984. Outcast London: A Study in the Relationship Between Classes in Victorian Society. 2nd ed. New York: Pantheon Books. Tawney, R. H. 1920. The Sickness of an Acquisitive Society. London: Fabian Society/George Allen and Unwin. ---. 1921. The Acquisitive Society. London: G. Bell and Sons.