Top Banner
Inequality Larry Temkin
57

Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

Jan 03, 2016

Download

Documents

Tracey Henry
Welcome message from author
This document is posted to help you gain knowledge. Please leave a comment to let me know what you think about it! Share it to your friends and learn new things together.
Transcript
Page 1: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

Inequality

Larry Temkin

Page 2: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

Larry Temkin

• Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton

• Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers

Page 3: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

Central Question:

• When is one situation worse than another with respect to inequality?

Page 4: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

Complaints

• Temkin introduces the idea of a “complaint with respect to inequality”

• If one situation is worse than another with respect to inequality, it will be worse for some person or persons in that situation.

• That person or those persons are then said to have a complaint.

Page 5: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

Complaint 1:

• Any who are worse off than average have a complaint.– If society has n total welfare, then any who have

less than one nth of the total through no fault of their own have a complaint.

– One who is below the average then has less than their fair share, and a complaint seems warranted in a way that it does not from anyone with their fair share or more.

Page 6: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

Complaint 2:

• All except the most well-off have a complaint.– Consider the following diagram:

Page 7: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

• q has a complaint in each case, because q has less than p through no fault of q.

Page 8: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

• The presence of r and s only seem to multiply the complaints.

Page 9: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

• The situation for q even seems worse in C than in A or B, even though q is 10 units closer to average in C than in A.

Page 10: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

Size of Complaints

• There are 3 plausible ways of judging the size of complaints:

1. How far below average is the one with the complaint

Page 11: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

Size of Complaints

• There are 3 plausible ways of judging the size of complaints:

1. How far below average is the one with the complaint

2. How far below the most well off is the one with the complaint

Page 12: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

Size of Complaints

• There are 3 plausible ways of judging the size of complaints:

1. How far below average is the one with the complaint

2. How far below the most well off is the one with the complaint

3. How those less well off compare with everyone who is better off than they

Page 13: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

Size of Complaints

• The first two parallel our thinking concerning who has a complaint.

1. How far below average is the one with the complaint

2. How far below the most well off is the one with the complaint

3. How those less well off compare with everyone who is better off than they

Page 14: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

Size of Complaints

• The first two parallel our thinking concerning who has a complaint.

• The third requires some explanation…

1. How far below average is the one with the complaint

2. How far below the most well off is the one with the complaint

3. How those less well off compare with everyone who is better off than they

Page 15: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

Size of Complaints

• The third requires some explanation…

• If it is bad to be worse off than someone else through no fault of your own, it is worse to be worse off than more than one such person.

1. How far below average is the one with the complaint

2. How far below the most well off is the one with the complaint

3. How those less well off compare with everyone who is better off than they

Page 16: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

Principles of Equality

• The maximin principle of equality seeks to first, maximize the position of the least-well-off group, and then minimize the number of people in that group.

1. Maximin Principle

Page 17: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

Principles of Equality

• The additive principle simply adds together the sizes of each complaint, and worlds with a greater total complaint are worse than worlds with less total complaint.

1. Maximin Principle2. Additive Principle

Page 18: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

THE SEQUENCE

• Temkin’s main tool to think about inequality is a series of simple situations referred to as “The Sequence”.

Page 19: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

THE SEQUENCE

• Temkin’s main tool to think about inequality is a series of simple situations referred to as “The Sequence”.

• The Sequence represents 999 distinct situations to be analyzed with respect to inequality

Page 20: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.
Page 21: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

• Notice that both the total and average utility get worse and worse as the sequence progresses.

Page 22: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

• Notice that both the total and average utility get worse and worse as the sequence progresses.

• For our purposes, this is an irrelevant feature. We simply want to know what inequality does over the course of the sequence.

Page 23: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

• View 1: The sequence gets BETTER AND BETTER with respect to inequality.

Page 24: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

• View 1: The sequence gets BETTER AND BETTER with respect to inequality.– The distance between those who have less and

the average decreases as the sequence progresses

Page 25: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

• View 1: The sequence gets BETTER AND BETTER with respect to inequality.– The number of people better off than those who

are less well off decreases as the sequence continues.

Page 26: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

• View 1: The sequence gets BETTER AND BETTER with respect to inequality.– It looks like someone is unjustly punished at the

beginning and someone is unjustly rewarded at the end, and unjust punishments are more objectionable than unjust rewards.

Page 27: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

• View 1: The sequence gets BETTER AND BETTER with respect to inequality.– The maximin principle of equality prefers the

complaints to be more evenly distributed, instead of heaped upon a few or one.

Page 28: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

• View 1: The sequence gets BETTER AND BETTER with respect to inequality.– The costs to the well-off to fix the inequality

increase as the sequence progresses, and the gain for the worse-off decreases as the sequence progresses, so the inequality is more egregious at the beginning and less so at the end.

Page 29: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

• View 2: The sequence gets WORSE AND WORSE with respect to inequality.

Page 30: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

• View 2: The sequence gets WORSE AND WORSE with respect to inequality.– The additive principle states that the more people

with a complaint, the worse a situation is.

Page 31: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

• View 2: The sequence gets WORSE AND WORSE with respect to inequality.– At the beginning, the worse-off has a complaint

against the best-off. As the sequence progresses, more people have the same complaint.

Page 32: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

• View 3: The sequence gets WORSE THEN BETTER with respect to inequality.– The endpoints are closer to absolute equality than

the middle, so as the sequence progresses, we move further from absolute equality, and then closer past the midpoint.

Page 33: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

• View 3: The sequence gets WORSE THEN BETTER with respect to inequality.– If you look at complaints against all those who are better

off and use the additive principle, then the middle, where a large number have a large complaint will be worse than the beginning, where a small number have a large complaint, and the end where a large number have a small complaint.

Page 34: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

• View 3: The sequence gets WORSE THEN BETTER with respect to inequality.– If you look at complaints of all those who are below

average and use the additive principle, then the middle, where a large number have a large complaint will be worse than the beginning, where a small number have a large complaint, and the end where a large number have a small complaint.

Page 35: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

• View 4: The sequence gets BETTER THEN WORSE with respect to inequality.

Page 36: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

• View 4: The sequence gets BETTER THEN WORSE with respect to inequality.– “By now it may seem that there are bound to be

several plausible positions supporting the judgment that the Sequence first gets better, then gets worse. If there are such elements, however, I am not aware of them.” (116)

Page 37: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

• View 5: The worlds of the sequence are EQUIVALENT with respect to inequality.

Page 38: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

• View 5: The worlds of the sequence are EQUIVALENT with respect to inequality.– If social institutions there are are responsible for

the presence of inequality, but not for the number of people in each group, then the worlds of the sequence are equivalent.

Page 39: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

• View 5: The worlds of the sequence are EQUIVALENT with respect to inequality.– Temkin’s analogy: two judges who accept bribes

for all their cases are equally corrupt even if one has tried fewer cases than the other.

Page 40: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

The Complexity of Inequality:

• If there are only two general principles of equality, and only three ways of having complaints with respect to inequality (which is surely false) then there are six different ways to explain what is happening with The Sequence, broken down as follows:

Page 41: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

The Complexity of Inequality

below average

below best

below all better

Additive Principle

worse then better

worse and worse

worse then better

Maximin Principlebetter and better

worse and worse

better and better

Page 42: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

Fractal Complexity

• There are surely additional plausible principles of equality, which, when combined with the reasons for complaint (which may well number more than three) yield further distinct analyses of inequality.

Page 43: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

Fractal Complexity

• There are surely additional plausible principles of equality, which, when combined with the reasons for complaint (which may well number more than three) yield further distinct analyses of inequality.

• There are also specific modifications of both the principles of equality and the reasons for complaint that yield further variation.

Page 44: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

Fractal Complexity

• Also, consider any situation more complex than The Sequence (e.g. real life) and you see that there are a great many plausible ways to think about when a situation is better or worse than another with respect to inequality.

Page 45: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

Common Measures of Inequality

• Economists sometimes use the following measures of inequality:

Page 46: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

Common Measures of Inequality

• Economists sometimes use the following measures of inequality:– Range: calculates the difference between the

highest and lowest observations of a particular variable of interest

Page 47: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

Some Common Measures of Inequality

• Economists sometimes use the following measures of inequality:– Range: the difference between the highest and

lowest observations of a particular variable of interest

Page 48: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

Some Common Measures of Inequality

• Economists sometimes use the following measures of inequality:– Range: the difference between the highest and

lowest observations of a particular variable of interest

– Coefficient of Variation: the standard deviation of a variable divided by the mean.

Page 49: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

Some Common Measures of Inequality

• Economists sometimes use the following measures of inequality:– Range: the difference between the highest and

lowest observations of a particular variable of interest

– Coefficient of Variation: the standard deviation of a variable divided by the mean.

– Gini Coefficient: a measure of the degree of deviation from perfect equality (see following)

Page 50: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.
Page 51: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

Some Common Measures of Inequality

• Economists sometimes use the following measures of inequality:– Range: the difference between the highest and

lowest observations of a particular variable of interest

– Coefficient of Variation: the standard deviation of a variable divided by the mean.

– Gini Coefficient: a measure of the degree of deviation from perfect equality (see following)

Page 52: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

Range:

A B0

1

2

3

4

5

6

pq

Page 53: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

Some Common Measures of Inequality

• Economists sometimes use the following measures of inequality:– Range: below best + maximin– Coefficient of Variation: the standard deviation of

a variable divided by the mean.– Gini Coefficient: a measure of the degree of

deviation from perfect equality (see following)

Page 54: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

• The curve on the left has more people below the average and more people far below the average than does the much tighter curve on the right, so the sum totals of each individual complaint will be higher in blue than red.

Page 55: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

Some Common Measures of Inequality

• Economists sometimes use the following measures of inequality:– Range: below best + maximin– Coefficient of Variation: below average + additive– Gini Coefficient: a measure of the degree of

deviation from perfect equality (see following)

Page 56: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

• Because the total area between the curve and perfect equality, each person with less is being compared to how many people have more and how much more they all have.

Page 57: Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.

Some Common Measures of Inequality

• Economists sometimes use the following measures of inequality:– Range: below best + maximin– Coefficient of Variation: below average + additive– Gini Coefficient: below all better + additive