Top Banner

of 11

Hellenophilia vs History of Science

Jun 02, 2018

Download

Documents

dekonstrukcija
Welcome message from author
This document is posted to help you gain knowledge. Please leave a comment to let me know what you think about it! Share it to your friends and learn new things together.
Transcript
  • 8/10/2019 Hellenophilia vs History of Science

    1/11

    The History of Science Society

    Hellenophilia versus the History of ScienceAuthor(s): David PingreeSource: Isis, Vol. 83, No. 4 (Dec., 1992), pp. 554-563Published by: The University of Chicago Press on behalf of The History of Science SocietyStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/234257

    Accessed: 22/11/2008 09:45

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless

    you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you

    may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

    Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ucpress.

    Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed

    page of such transmission.

    JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the

    scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that

    promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    The University of Chicago Pressand The History of Science Societyare collaborating with JSTOR to digitize,

    preserve and extend access toIsis.

    http://www.jstor.org

    http://www.jstor.org/stable/234257?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ucpresshttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ucpresshttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/234257?origin=JSTOR-pdf
  • 8/10/2019 Hellenophilia vs History of Science

    2/11

    ellenophilia

    r s u s

    t h

    i s tory

    o

    Sc ience

    By

    David

    Pingreet

    THE GENESIS

    OF

    THIS PAPER

    lies

    in a conversation that I

    had with A. I.

    Sabra of Harvard on

    the

    perennial problem

    of

    the

    definition of

    science

    appropriate

    o

    a

    historian of

    science;

    its

    corruption

    (including

    the

    deliberately

    extreme mode of

    its

    expression)

    is

    entirely

    a result

    of

    my

    own

    labors. For the

    piece representsthe attitudestowardthe subjectthatI havedevelopedover some

    three and

    a

    half decades of

    studying

    the

    history

    of the

    exact sciences

    (as

    I

    will

    persist

    in

    calling

    them

    despite

    the lack

    of exactitude

    in

    some of

    them),

    as

    prac-

    ticed

    in

    ancient

    Mesopotamia,

    in

    ancient and

    medieval

    Greece,

    India,

    and

    the

    Latin-speaking

    West,

    and

    in

    medieval Islam. It

    is

    this

    experience,

    then,

    and the

    desire

    to reconstruct a

    complex

    history

    as

    accurately

    as

    possible,

    that motivates

    me-these

    two,

    and the wish to

    provide

    an

    apologia

    or

    my

    claim to be a

    historian

    of

    science

    rather than

    of

    quackery.

    For the sciences

    I

    study

    are those related

    to

    the

    stars,

    and

    they

    include

    not

    only

    various astronomies and the

    differentmath-

    ematicaltheories

    they

    employ,

    but also astral

    omens,

    astrology, magic,

    medicine,

    and law (dharmasastra).All of these subjects, I would argue, were or are sci-

    ences

    within the contexts of

    the

    cultures

    n

    which

    they

    once flourished

    or

    now

    are

    practiced.

    As such

    they

    deserve to

    be

    studied

    by

    historians of

    science

    with

    as

    serious

    and

    thorough

    a

    purpose

    as are the

    topics

    that

    we

    usually

    find

    discussed in

    history

    of

    science

    classrooms or

    in the

    pages

    of

    Isis.

    This

    means

    that

    their intel-

    lectual content

    must be

    probed deeply,

    and not

    simply

    dismissed as

    rubbish

    or

    interpreted

    n the

    light

    of modern historical

    mythology;

    and that

    the

    intellectual

    content

    must

    be related to

    the

    culture

    that

    produced

    and

    nourished

    each,

    and

    to

    the

    social

    context

    within which each arose

    and

    developed.

    In

    stating

    these

    opinions

    I

    may appear

    to

    have set

    myself

    up

    as

    a

    relativist,

    but

    I woulddeny the applicabilityof thatepithetto my positionsince my interest lies

    not

    in

    judging

    the truth or falsehood

    of these or

    any

    other

    sciences,

    nor

    in

    dis-

    covering

    in

    them some

    part

    that

    might

    be

    useful

    or relevant

    to

    the

    present

    world,

    but

    simply

    in

    understanding

    how,

    why,

    where,

    and

    when

    they

    worked

    as func-

    tioning systems

    of

    thought

    and

    interactedwith each other and with other

    systems

    of

    thought.

    It

    is

    with these considerations

    n

    mind, then,

    that

    I

    have embraced the word

    employed

    in the title

    of

    this

    article,

    Hellenophilia,

    as it

    is

    a

    most

    convenient

    description

    of

    a set of attitudes

    that I

    perceive

    to be of

    increasing

    prevalence

    t Box 1900,BrownUniversity,Providence,Rhode Island 02912.

    This

    paper

    was

    originally

    deliveredas a lecture

    at the

    Department

    f

    History

    of

    Science,

    Harvard

    University,

    14

    November 1990.

    ISIS,

    1992,

    83:

    554-563 554

  • 8/10/2019 Hellenophilia vs History of Science

    3/11

    CULTURES

    OF ANCIENT SCIENCE

    within the

    profession

    of the

    history

    of

    science,

    and

    which

    I

    believe to

    be

    thor-

    oughly pernicious.

    I like

    Hellenophilia

    as

    a

    word because it

    brings

    to

    mind

    such other

    terms

    as

    necrophilia,

    barbaric xcess that

    erupts

    as

    a

    disease from

    the passionate rather than from the rationalsoul; whereas the true love of the

    Greeks, Philhellenism,

    hough

    also

    an

    attribute

    of

    barbarians

    uch as

    are

    we-the

    epithet

    Philhellene

    was

    proudly

    borne

    by

    ancient

    Parthians,

    Semites,

    and Ro-

    mans-arises

    preeminently

    rom

    well-deserved admiration.

    A

    Philhellene s one

    who

    shares

    in what used to

    be,

    when children in the West

    still were

    taught

    the

    classics,

    a

    virtually

    universal awe

    of

    Greek

    literature, art,

    philosophy,

    and

    sci-

    ence;

    a

    Hellenophile

    suffers from a form of madness

    that blinds him

    or

    her

    to

    historical

    truth and creates

    in

    the

    imagination

    he

    idea

    that one

    of several false

    propositions

    is true. The first

    of

    these is that the Greeks invented

    science;

    the

    second is

    that

    they

    discovered

    a

    way

    to

    truth,

    the scientific

    method,

    that

    we

    are

    now successfully following;the third is that the only real sciences are those that

    began

    in

    Greece;

    and

    the fourth

    (and

    last?)

    is that

    the

    true definitionof

    science is

    just

    that

    which

    scientists

    happen

    to be

    doing

    now,

    following

    a

    method

    or

    methods

    adumbrated

    by

    the

    Greeks,

    but never

    fully

    understoodor utilized

    by

    them.

    Hellenophiles,

    it

    might

    be

    observed,

    are

    overwhelmingly

    Westerners,

    display-

    ing

    the cultural

    myopia

    common

    in all

    cultures

    of the world

    but,

    as

    well,

    the

    arrogance

    hat characterized he medieval

    Christian's

    recognition

    of his own

    in-

    fallibility

    and that has now been inherited

    by

    our modern

    priests

    of

    science.

    Intellectually

    hese Western

    Hellenophiles

    are still

    living

    in

    the miasmathat

    per-

    meated

    Europe

    until

    the nineteenth

    century,

    before the

    discovery

    of Sanskrit

    and

    the crackingof cuneiformdestroyed such ethnocentricrubbish;such persons

    have

    simply

    not been

    exposed

    to the

    knowledgethey

    would need to

    arrive

    at a

    more balanced

    judgment.

    But,

    sadly,

    I

    must

    report

    that

    many

    non-Westerners

    have

    caught

    a form of the disease

    Hellenophilia;

    hey

    are

    deluded

    into

    believing

    that the

    greatestglory

    an

    Indian,

    a

    Chinese,

    an

    Arab,

    or

    an

    African

    scientist

    can

    have

    acquired

    is that

    gainedby having anticipated

    either a Greek

    or

    a

    modern

    Westerner.

    So

    some

    Indians,

    for

    instance,

    busily reinterpret

    heir

    divinely

    in-

    spired

    R?gveda

    o that it teaches such modern

    hypothetical

    theories

    as that

    of

    relativity

    or

    the latest

    attempt

    to

    explain

    black

    holes,

    as if these

    transitory

    deas

    were eternal

    complete

    truths. In

    doing

    this

    they

    are

    behaving

    as did those

    Chris-

    tians who once believed it importantto demonstratethat Genesis agrees with

    Greek science. These

    attempts

    do not enhance the brillianceof the

    authorsor

    the

    reinterpreters

    of their sacred

    or

    scientific

    texts,

    but rather reveal a

    severe

    sense

    of cultural

    nferiority.

    Parallel o

    this

    form of cultural

    denigration,practiced

    by

    the

    culture

    tself

    or

    by

    historians of

    science,

    is,

    say,

    the false claim that medieval

    Islam

    only

    preserved

    Greekscience and transmitted

    t as

    Muslimshad received

    it

    to the

    eager

    West. In

    fact Arab

    scientists,

    using

    Indian, Iranian,

    and

    Syrian

    sources

    as well

    as

    their

    own

    genius,

    revised

    the Greek

    sciences,

    transforming

    hem into the

    Islamic

    sci-

    ences

    that,

    historically,

    served as the main basis

    for

    what little

    science

    there

    was

    in Western Europe in the twelfth and followingcenturies and for the amazing

    developments

    that

    happened

    three

    and four centuries later in

    Italy

    and

    Central

    Europe.

    Another form that this Western

    arrogance

    takes is the naive

    assumption

    that

    other

    peoples

    in the

    world not

    only

    should

    be like

    us,

    but

    actually

    are

    or

    were-

    555

  • 8/10/2019 Hellenophilia vs History of Science

    4/11

    PINGREE: HELLENOPHILIA

    V. HISTORY OF

    SCIENCE

    were

    because

    this

    particular

    allacy usually

    affects those who

    study

    Stone

    Age

    and other

    preliterate

    cultures

    that have been left defenseless

    in

    the

    face

    of

    mod-

    ern

    reconstructions

    of their

    thoughts

    by

    their

    inability

    to record

    them

    in

    perma-

    nent

    form.

    In the

    history

    of the exact sciences the scholars who

    perpetrate

    wild

    theories of

    prehistoric

    science

    call themselves archaeoastronomers.

    The

    basic

    premise

    of

    some archaeoastronomers

    s that

    megalithic

    and

    other

    cultures in

    which

    writing

    was not

    known built stone

    monuments,

    some

    quite

    massive,

    in

    order to record

    their

    insights

    into

    the

    periodicity

    of celestial

    motions.

    This seems

    to

    me a trivial

    purpose

    to motivate such monumental

    communal

    efforts as the

    building

    of

    Stonehenge

    or the

    pyramids.

    There are

    many strong arguments

    o be

    raised

    against

    many

    of

    these

    interpretations.

    At this

    point,

    however,

    I wish

    only

    to

    point

    out

    that

    they go

    against

    the

    strong

    evidence from

    early

    literate societies

    that

    early

    man

    had little interest

    in

    the stars before

    the end of the

    third

    millen-

    nium

    B.C.;

    the

    cataloguing

    of stars and the

    recording

    of stellar and

    planetary

    phenomena

    are not

    a

    natural,

    but a learned

    activity

    that

    needs a motivation such

    as that

    which

    inspired

    the

    Babylonians,

    who

    believed that the

    gods

    send

    mes-

    sages

    to mankind

    hrough

    he celestial bodies.

    The

    realization hat some of these

    ominous

    phenomena

    are

    periodic

    can

    be dated

    securely

    in

    Mesopotamia

    o a time

    no earlier

    than the late second millennium

    B.C.;

    mathematicalcontrol of

    the

    re-

    lation

    between

    solar and

    lunarmotion

    came

    only

    in about 500 B.C.

    The

    Egyptians

    also

    first

    began using

    selected stars

    as a sort of crude clock

    only

    in

    about 2000

    B.C. and

    progressed

    no

    further

    in

    mathematical

    astronomy

    till

    they

    came

    under

    Babylonian

    nfluence. The

    earliest

    traces

    of a

    knowledge

    of

    astronomy

    n

    Greece

    and India seem also to be derived, in the early first millennium

    B.C.,

    from Mes-

    opotamia.

    I cannot

    speak

    of the

    astronomy

    of

    the

    early

    Chinese with

    authority

    because

    I am

    ignorant

    of their

    language,

    but I

    gather

    from what

    I

    have read that

    not

    even

    the

    beginnings

    of the

    system

    of

    the hsiu

    or lunar

    lodges

    can be dated

    before the

    late

    second

    millennium

    B.C. From the

    written

    evidence, then,

    it

    ap-

    pears

    that

    an interest

    in the stars

    as omens arose

    in

    Mesopotamia

    after 2000

    B.C.

    and started to

    develop

    toward

    mathematical

    astronomy

    in

    about

    1200

    B.C.,

    but

    that

    the

    Babyloniansbegan

    to

    invent mathematical

    models useful

    for

    the

    predic-

    tion

    of

    celestial

    phenomena

    with

    some

    degree

    of

    accuracyonly

    in about 500

    B.C.

    From

    Mesopotamia

    these astronomical

    deas

    rapidly

    radiated

    to

    Egypt,

    later

    to

    Greece and India, and finally,perhaps,to China;in each of these culturesthey

    were

    molded

    by

    the

    recipient

    scientists into

    something

    new,

    though

    still

    having

    recognizable Mesopotamian

    origins.

    The astral

    sciences

    spread

    from

    one

    civili-

    zation to another

    like a

    highly

    infectious disease.

    It is within the

    context

    of

    this

    documented

    history

    that

    I find

    implausible

    the

    suggestion

    that less

    advanced

    civilizations,

    without

    any

    known

    systems

    of

    writing

    or accurate record

    keeping,

    independently

    discovered

    complex

    lunar

    theories,

    or

    precession,

    or even an

    ac-

    curate intercalation

    cycle.

    The

    example

    of

    the

    Babylonians,

    with their need for a

    specific

    motive for

    observing

    stars

    and the fact that

    it took them a millenniumand

    a

    half to

    arrive

    at

    a workable

    mathematical

    astronomy,

    and the

    examples

    of

    the

    Egyptians,Greeks, and Indians,if not the Chinese,who initiallyborrowed their

    astronomies from

    the

    Babylonians

    before each

    developed

    its science

    in

    its own

    way,

    seem

    to me to

    invalidate the

    theoretical basis

    for much of

    archaeoastron-

    omy.

    I

    return

    now

    to

    the four variants

    of

    Hellenophilia

    that I

    mentioned earlier.

    556

  • 8/10/2019 Hellenophilia vs History of Science

    5/11

    CULTURES

    OF ANCIENT

    SCIENCE

    Each,

    I would

    claim,

    distorts

    the

    history

    of science

    in two

    ways: passively,

    it

    limits

    the

    phenomena

    that the historian s

    willing

    or able to

    examine;

    actively,

    it

    perverts

    understanding

    both of Western

    sciences,

    from the Greeks till

    now,

    and

    of non-Westernsciences. Thus those who still believe that the Greeks invented

    science

    either are

    altogether

    ignorant

    of,

    say,

    Babylonian

    mathematics

    and

    as-

    tronomy

    or

    else,

    though

    aware

    of

    them,

    fall

    into

    my

    second

    category

    and refuse

    to

    recognize

    them as

    sciences.

    The

    ignorance

    of the first

    group,

    of

    course,

    can

    and

    should

    be remedied

    through

    education;

    the

    obstinacy

    of the second

    in

    not

    acknowledging

    hat

    Old

    Babylonian

    nvestigations

    of

    irrationalnumbers

    ike

    \/2,

    of arithmetical

    and

    geometrical

    series,

    or of

    Pythagorean

    riplets

    are

    science

    even

    though

    they

    are

    mathematically

    correct,

    or

    in

    asserting

    that the

    arithmetical

    schemes

    that

    they

    successfully

    used to

    control

    the

    many

    variables nvolved in the

    prediction

    of

    the time of the

    first

    visibility

    of the lunarcrescent cannot bear the

    august

    name of scientia even

    though

    the

    predictions

    were

    essentially

    correct-

    this

    obstinacy

    is hard

    to

    deal

    with. It leaves the

    obstinate, however,

    in

    the awk-

    ward

    position

    of

    denying

    the status of science

    to one

    of

    the main

    contributors o

    the Greek

    astronomy

    that

    is

    the forebear of our

    positional

    astronomy.

    Such a

    person,

    of

    course,

    can

    name an

    arbitrary

    date at which

    positional

    astronomy

    comes

    to fit into

    his

    or

    her definitionof

    science;

    but this

    cannot

    be

    accepted

    by

    a

    historian,

    as it is the

    historian's

    ask to seek

    out the

    origins

    of the ideas that he

    or

    she is

    dealing

    with,

    and these

    manifestly

    lie,

    for

    astronomy,

    in

    the

    wedges

    im-

    pressed

    on

    clay

    tablets

    as well as

    in

    the observed

    motions

    of

    the

    celestial

    bodies.

    It is

    certainly

    possible

    to be

    a

    modern scientist

    without

    knowing

    history,

    or even

    with a firm belief in historicalmythology;but can a historianof science function

    effectively

    under

    such

    disabilities?

    While

    ignorance

    of

    Babylonianastronomy

    destroys

    the historian's

    ability

    to

    understand

    he

    origins

    and

    development

    of Greek

    and other

    astronomies

    ogether

    with their

    more modern

    descendants,

    it also

    tempts

    him

    or

    her

    to

    imagine

    that

    there

    is

    no other

    way

    to

    do

    astronomy

    han

    through

    he

    Greek and

    modern

    way

    of

    making

    observations

    and

    buildinggeometric

    models.

    But

    Babylonian

    astronomy

    reveals how few observations

    are

    needed and how

    imprecise

    they

    may

    be

    if

    the

    astronomers

    are clever

    enough;

    and

    it

    also demonstrates

    hat

    simple

    arithmetical

    models suffice

    for

    predicting

    the

    times and

    longitudes

    of

    periodic

    celestial

    phe-

    nomena. The Babylonian solutions are brilliant applicationsof mathematical

    structures

    o rather

    crude

    data,

    made

    purely

    to

    provide

    the

    possibility

    of

    predic-

    tion

    without

    any

    concern for theories of

    cosmological

    structure

    or

    celestial me-

    chanics.

    The Greeks added

    the concern

    both

    for the

    geometrical

    structureof

    the

    universe and

    for the cinematics

    of the

    heavens,

    with

    a

    strong

    prejudice

    n

    favor

    of

    circles or

    spheres

    rotating

    with uniform

    motion;

    but

    they

    also,

    to

    a

    large

    extent,

    simply

    expressed

    the

    Babylonian period

    relations

    and arithmetical

    zigzag

    and

    step

    functions

    in a

    geometricallanguage, using

    observations

    to

    modify Babylo-

    nian

    parameters

    and to fine-tune

    heir

    own

    geometrical

    models.

    A third

    variety

    of

    astronomy emerged

    from

    the

    synthesis

    of

    Babylonian

    arithmetical

    models,

    Hel-

    lenistic geometricalmodels, and local mathematical raditions that occurred in

    India in

    the fifth

    century

    A.D.

    In

    this

    astronomyquestions

    of celestial

    cinematics

    receded into

    trivial

    mechanisms

    while

    computational

    inesse harnessed a broad

    range

    of

    mathematical

    echniques

    to

    the solution of astronomical

    problems,

    with

    the

    role

    of

    observations

    being

    limited to the

    confirmation,

    f

    possible,

    of

    accepted

    557

  • 8/10/2019 Hellenophilia vs History of Science

    6/11

    PINGREE:

    HELLENOPHILIAV. HISTORYOF SCIENCE

    theory.

    There were

    historically

    many

    more

    astronomies,

    manifesting

    a

    variety

    of

    ways

    in

    which the

    same

    phenomena

    might

    be made

    predictable

    by

    mathematical

    means.

    These different

    astronomies reflect

    the

    different

    ntellectual

    traditionsof

    the variouscultures as well as the

    specific problems

    that each

    society

    wished its

    astronomers

    o

    address-for

    example,

    the

    Babylonians

    were

    interested

    in

    certain

    horizon

    phenomena

    that

    they regarded

    as

    omens;

    the Greeks

    brought

    philosoph-

    ical

    and

    physical

    problems

    nto a science

    that had been

    purely

    mathematical,

    and

    as

    well introduced

    the more social

    aim of

    casting

    horoscopes;

    and

    the

    Indians

    devoted

    their

    efforts

    to

    the

    purely pragmatic

    goals

    of

    casting

    horoscopes,

    of

    pre-

    dicting

    eclipses

    because of

    their

    significance

    as

    omens,

    and

    of

    evolving

    and

    reg-

    ulating

    an

    extraordinarily omplex

    calendar.

    I

    believe

    that

    those historians who

    limit

    themselves to the

    study

    of

    only

    one of these

    approaches

    to mathematical

    astronomy

    will

    blunder,

    as

    indeed

    many

    have,

    by

    not

    fully

    understanding

    he

    range

    of

    possibilities

    or the

    shaping

    orce of

    purely

    cultural actors on the course

    that

    any

    science

    takes.

    If it is evident

    that

    for

    a historian

    the

    proposition

    that

    the Greeks invented

    science

    must

    be

    rejected,

    it

    necessarily

    follows

    that

    they

    did not discover a

    unique

    scientific method.

    Indeed,

    they-and

    we-have not

    one,

    but

    many

    scien-

    tific

    methods;

    biologists, physicists,

    and

    astronomers

    went,

    and

    go,

    their

    separate

    methodological

    ways.

    I

    choose, therefore,

    to focus

    on the

    pride

    of Greek science:

    Euclidean

    geometry-which,

    of

    course,

    is

    purely logical

    and

    nonexperimental.

    This is

    often and

    justly praised

    for the

    rigor

    and

    power

    of

    its

    axiomatic

    system

    and for its

    ability

    to

    offer

    ogical

    deductive

    proofs.

    Indeed,

    Babylonian

    and Indian

    mathematicsarefrequentlycriticizedfor relyingnot on proofsbut on demonstra-

    tions.

    But

    without

    axioms

    and without

    proofs

    Indian

    mathematicians olved

    in-

    determinate

    equations

    of

    the second

    degree

    and discovered

    the infinite

    power

    series for

    trigonometrical

    unctions centuries

    before

    European

    mathematicians

    independently

    reached

    similarresults.

    These

    achievements

    amply

    demonstrate,

    I

    believe,

    that

    the

    Euclidean

    approach

    s not

    necessary

    for

    discovery

    in mathemat-

    ics. Those who

    deny

    the

    validity

    of alternative

    scientific methods

    must

    somehow

    explain

    how

    equivalent

    scientific

    truths can be

    arrivedat

    without

    Greek meth-

    ods.

    And in their denial

    they

    clearly

    deprive

    themselves

    of

    an

    opportunity

    to

    understandscience

    more

    deeply.

    To departbrieflyfrom the exact sciences, I wouldlike to draw attentionto the

    fascinating

    work

    of Francis

    Zimmermann

    on

    ayurveda,

    the Indian

    science

    of

    longevity,

    as

    it was and is

    currentlypracticed

    in Kerala. While

    he

    stronglysup-

    ports

    the idea

    of

    the

    historical

    dependence

    of

    ayurveda

    on

    the

    Galenic

    theory

    of

    humors,

    Zimmermann s also

    keenly

    aware

    of

    the

    many

    ways

    in

    which Indian

    vaidyas

    have

    altered

    foreign

    notions

    while

    incorporating

    hem into their own

    cultural

    traditions to

    create

    a

    theory

    of

    harmony

    and mutual

    influence between

    the

    humans,

    animals,

    and

    plants

    inhabitingany region

    and that

    region's

    terrain

    and climate.

    In

    Kerala

    these

    ecological

    deas

    produced

    a local

    interpretation

    f

    ayurvedic

    doctrine

    that,

    it would

    appear,

    maintaineda

    generally

    healthy

    human

    population,at least to that population'ssatisfaction,as long as the people were

    not

    subjected

    to

    wars, famines,

    or

    epidemics.

    The

    ayurvedic approach

    to medi-

    cine does not

    inspire

    its

    practitioners

    o make discoveries

    in molecular

    biology,

    but

    it

    is

    the correct medical

    science

    for

    the culturalcontext

    within which it

    op-

    erates.

    And it

    attempts

    to address

    psychological,

    social,

    and

    environmental

    as-

    558

  • 8/10/2019 Hellenophilia vs History of Science

    7/11

    CULTURES OF ANCIENT SCIENCE

    pects

    of health that our mechanistic medicine tends

    to

    ignore.

    Western

    doctors

    have

    something

    to learn about medical care

    from

    dyurveda,

    and

    so do Western

    historiansof medicine.

    The third fallacious

    opinion

    that

    I

    have

    associated

    with

    the

    Hellenophiles

    is

    that the

    only

    sciences

    are

    those that accredited Greeks

    recognized

    as such.

    This

    opinion generally

    takes the

    form of

    allowing

    Aristotle to define

    science

    for

    us,

    so

    that it

    excludes

    even the

    genuinely

    Greek

    sciences of

    astrology,

    divination,

    magic,

    and other so-called

    superstitions.

    This

    brings

    us

    squarely

    to the funda-

    mental

    question

    of this

    paper:

    What is the

    proper

    definition

    of science for a

    historianof science?

    I

    would offerthis as

    the

    simplest,

    broadest,

    and

    most useful:

    science is a

    systematic

    explanation

    of

    perceived

    or

    imaginary

    phenomena,

    or else

    is

    based on such

    an

    explanation.

    Mathematics

    inds a

    place

    in

    science

    only

    as one

    of the symbolicallanguagesin which scientificexplanations may be expressed.

    This definition

    deliberately

    ails

    to

    distinguish

    between

    true and

    false

    science,

    for

    explanations

    of

    phenomena

    are never

    complete

    and

    can

    never

    be

    proved

    to be

    true.

    Obviously,

    this

    shortfall

    s as true of modern

    scientific

    hypotheses

    as of

    ancient

    ones. It

    is, therefore,

    inappropriate

    o

    apply

    a standardof

    truthfulness o

    the

    sciences,

    at

    least viewed

    as historical

    phenomena,

    for the

    best

    that

    modern

    scientists can

    claim-I

    cannot

    udge

    whether

    ustly

    or not-is that

    they

    are closer

    to some truth

    than were

    their

    predecessors;

    nor,

    for the reasons I

    have

    already

    stated,

    can the

    methodologies

    of science be limited to

    just

    those

    employed

    by

    present-day

    scientists.

    If my definitionof science as it must be viewed by a historian s accepted, it is

    easy

    to show that

    astrology

    and

    certain learned

    orms of

    divination,

    magic,

    alchemy,

    and so on

    are

    sciences. Some

    may

    regard

    his

    procedure

    or

    elevating

    superstition

    o the rank of scientific

    theory

    as

    arbitrary

    nd

    unfair,

    but

    remember

    that modern science

    is the initial

    culprit

    in that it

    arbitrarily

    sets

    up

    its

    own

    criteria

    by

    which it

    judges

    itself and all

    others.

    If

    I

    am a

    relativist,

    then,

    it

    is

    precisely

    at this

    point

    where,

    as

    a

    historian,

    I

    refuse to allow modern

    scientists

    who

    know little

    of

    history

    to define

    for

    me the bounds of what in

    the

    past-or

    in

    the

    present-I

    am

    allowed

    to consider

    to be

    science.

    It

    pains

    me

    to

    hear

    some

    scientists,

    who have not

    seriously

    considered

    the

    subject,

    denounce

    astrology

    as

    unscientific

    when all

    that

    they

    mean

    is

    that it

    does not

    agree

    with

    their

    ideas

    about the

    way

    the universe functionsand

    does not

    adhere

    to their

    concept

    of a

    correct

    methodology.

    It

    pains

    me not because I

    believe that

    astrology

    is

    true;

    on

    the

    contrary,

    I believe it

    to

    be

    totally

    false. But the anathemas

    hurled

    at it

    by

    some scientists remind

    me more of the anathemas leveled

    by

    the

    medieval

    Church

    against

    those

    who

    disagreed

    with its

    dogmas

    thanof

    rational

    argument.

    n

    its

    persecution

    of hereticsas in its

    missionary

    zeal and its

    tendency

    to

    sermonize

    and to

    pontificate,

    our

    scientific establishment

    displays

    marked

    similarities o

    the

    Church,

    whose

    place

    in

    our

    society

    it

    has

    largely

    usurped.

    That

    Church,

    like modern

    science,

    condemned

    divination,

    astrology,

    and

    magic, though

    on the

    grounds

    that

    they

    limitGod's

    power

    and

    human

    free will

    rather than that

    they

    fail to conformto our current laws of nature. Both

    of

    these

    arguments,

    to

    my

    way

    of

    thinking,

    are

    arbitrary

    and

    irrelevant

    to

    a

    histo-

    rian,

    who should remain

    free of either

    the

    Church's

    or

    modern

    science's

    theol-

    ogy.

    559

  • 8/10/2019 Hellenophilia vs History of Science

    8/11

  • 8/10/2019 Hellenophilia vs History of Science

    9/11

  • 8/10/2019 Hellenophilia vs History of Science

    10/11

    PINGREE: HELLENOPHILIA V. HISTORY OF SCIENCE

    within its cultural

    context,

    but to

    attempt

    to discover

    within

    the

    science elements

    similar

    to elements of modern

    Western

    science. One

    example

    I can

    give

    you

    relates

    to

    the

    IndianMadhava's

    demonstration,

    n about

    1400

    A.D.,

    of the

    infinite

    power

    series of

    trigonometrical

    unctions

    using geometrical

    and

    algebraic

    argu-

    ments.

    When this was

    first

    described

    in

    English by

    Charles

    Whish,

    in

    the

    1830s,

    it

    was

    heraldedas

    the Indians'

    discovery

    of the calculus. This

    claim

    and

    Madha-

    va's achievements

    were

    ignored by

    Western

    historians,

    presumably

    at first

    be-

    cause

    they

    could not admit

    that an Indian discovered the

    calculus,

    but later

    because

    no one read

    anymore

    the

    Transactions

    of

    the

    Royal

    Asiatic

    Society,

    in

    which

    Whish's article

    was

    published.

    The matter resurfaced in the

    1950s,

    and

    now

    we have the

    Sanskrit

    texts

    properly

    edited,

    and

    we

    understand

    he

    clever

    way

    that

    Madhava derived the series without

    the

    calculus;

    but

    many

    historians

    still find it

    impossible

    to

    conceive of the

    problem

    and

    its solution

    in

    terms of

    anythingotherthan the calculusandproclaim hat the calculus is whatMadhava

    found.

    In this case the

    elegance

    and

    brilliance

    of

    Madhava's mathematics are

    being

    distorted

    as

    they

    are buried under the

    current mathematical olution to a

    problem

    to which he

    discovered

    an

    alternateand

    powerful

    solution.

    Other

    examples

    of this

    dangerous

    tendency

    abound. For

    instance,

    since the

    1850s

    historians

    ignorant

    of

    Madhava's

    work have

    argued

    about

    whether

    Indian

    astronomers

    had the

    concept

    of the infinitesimal alculus on the basis

    of

    their

    use

    of the

    equivalent

    of the

    cosine

    function

    in

    a formula or

    finding

    he

    instantaneous

    velocity

    of the

    moon,

    a

    formula

    that occurs

    already

    in a

    sixth-century

    Sanskrit

    text,

    the

    Pancasiddhantika.

    I cannot

    tell

    you

    how

    that

    formula

    was

    derived,

    since

    its author, Varahamihira,has not told me; but I find it totally implausiblethat

    some Indian discovered

    the calculus-a

    discovery

    for which

    previous

    develop-

    ments

    in Indian

    mathematics

    would not

    at all have

    preparedhim-applied

    his

    discovery only

    to the

    problem

    of

    the

    instantaneous

    velocity

    of

    the

    moon,

    and

    then threw

    it

    away.

    The

    idea that he

    might

    have discovered the calculus arises

    only

    from the

    Hellenophilic

    attitude that what

    is

    valuable

    in

    the past is what we

    have

    in

    the

    present;

    this

    attitudemakes historiansbecome treasurehunters seek-

    ing pearls

    in the

    dung heap

    without

    any

    concern

    for where the

    oysters

    live

    and

    how

    they

    manufacture

    gems.

    One

    particularlydangerous

    orm of this

    aspect

    of

    Hellenophilia

    s

    the

    positivist

    positionthatis confidentthatmathematicalogic providesthe correct answers to

    questions

    in

    the

    history

    of

    the exact sciences.

    I,

    of

    course,

    am not

    denying

    the

    power

    of

    mathematics to

    provide

    insights

    into

    the

    character and structure

    of

    scientific

    theories;

    obviously,

    Otto

    Neugebauer's

    brilliant

    analysis

    of the

    astro-

    nomical tables

    written in

    cuneiform

    during

    the

    Seleucid

    period gives

    us a

    pro-

    found

    understanding

    of how

    this

    astronomy

    worked

    mathematically,

    and it tells

    us

    something

    about some

    stages

    in

    the

    development

    of the science as recordedon

    the hundredsof tablets

    that he

    investigated.

    But it

    does not

    and

    cannot,

    as Neu-

    gebauer

    well

    knew,

    answer

    a

    whole

    range

    of

    historical

    questions.

    We

    do not

    know

    by

    whom,

    when,

    or

    where

    any Babylonian

    unar or

    planetary

    theory

    was

    invented;we do not knowwhatobservationswere used, or where andwhy they

    were

    recorded;

    we

    do not

    know much about the

    stages by

    which

    Babylonian

    astronomers

    went

    from the crude

    planetary

    periods,

    derived

    from

    omen

    texts,

    found

    in

    MUL.APIN

    to the

    full-scale

    ephemerides

    of the last few centuries

    B.C.

    Historians

    need to be

    very

    careful

    in

    assessing

    the nature

    of

    the

    questions

    the

    562

  • 8/10/2019 Hellenophilia vs History of Science

    11/11

    CULTURESOF ANCIENT SCIENCE

    material at

    hand

    will

    allow them to answer

    with a

    reasonable

    expectation

    of

    probability;

    and

    they

    must

    hope

    for and search out new evidence.

    But the

    posi-

    tivists

    jump

    in

    to claim that mathematicalmodels

    (and

    they

    usually

    use

    quite

    simple

    ones) sufficeto describe the

    idiosyncratic

    behaviorof

    people

    and to ac-

    count for

    the

    perverse

    quirks

    in their

    personalities.

    I

    will

    not

    here

    name

    names,

    but

    the

    number

    of

    historians

    of

    the

    exact sciences who suffer rom

    this

    malady

    is

    appallingly

    arge; they

    can be

    easily

    recognized

    by

    the

    characteristic rait

    that,

    in

    general,

    the

    remoter the time and the

    scantier

    the

    evidence,

    the

    more

    precise

    their

    computations.

    Millenniaof

    history

    are made to

    depend

    on the

    measurement

    of an arc of

    a

    few minutes

    or

    degrees

    when it

    has not even been

    convincingly

    demonstrated

    hat

    any

    arc

    was

    being

    measuredat

    all.

    So far

    I have been

    attempting

    o discredit

    Hellenophilia

    on

    the

    grounds

    that it

    renders those affected

    by

    it unable to

    imagine many significantquestions

    that

    legitimatelyshould be addressedby historiansof science and thatit pervertstheir

    judgment.

    Much

    of

    my argument

    has

    been based on

    the

    anthropological

    percep-

    tion

    that science is not

    the

    apprehension

    of

    an external set

    of truths that

    mankind

    is

    progressively

    acquiring

    a

    greater

    knowledge

    of,

    but

    that

    rather he

    sciences

    are

    the

    products

    of humanculture.

    But

    this

    viewpoint

    must

    be

    modified

    by

    a

    further

    consideration,

    to which

    I

    have from time to time alluded since it

    strengthens

    he

    arguments

    n

    favor of

    the

    definition

    of

    science

    that

    I

    proposed.

    This

    consideration

    is

    that,

    as

    a

    simple

    historical

    fact,

    scientific ideas

    have been

    transmitted or mil-

    lennia from culture to

    culture,

    and

    transformed

    by

    each

    recipient

    culture into

    something

    new. This

    is

    particularly

    noticeable

    n the astral

    sciences that

    I

    study-

    astronomy, astral omens, astrology, and astral magic-but can be readily dis-

    cerned

    in

    many

    others. The

    taproot

    and trunkof the tree of

    the astral

    sciences are

    buried

    in

    the

    Mesopotamian

    desert,

    with

    subsidiary

    roots

    in

    Egypt

    and

    China

    (I

    have

    lopped

    the

    Mayas

    off this arboreal

    image,

    as

    they

    are

    self-rooted).

    From

    Babylonia

    the tree branchedout to

    Egypt,

    to

    Greece,

    to

    Syria,

    to

    Iran,

    to

    India,

    and to

    China;

    grafted

    onto differentculturalstocks

    in

    each

    of

    these

    civilizations,

    it

    developed

    variant

    eaves, shoots,

    and

    flowers.

    The

    process

    of

    the

    intertwining

    of these diverse

    varieties of astronomies

    throughout

    Eurasia and

    North

    Africa

    was

    amazingly

    complex,

    as

    ideas,

    mathematical

    models,

    parameters,

    and instru-

    ments

    circulated

    rapidly

    over the

    vast

    expanse

    of

    divergent

    raditions.Out

    of this

    process modern Westernastronomysprangfrom a rather ate branchthat grew

    from

    and was fed

    by

    an

    incredibly

    complicated

    undergrowth.

    For

    very

    complex

    reasons this modern Western

    astronomy

    has

    choked off all of its

    rivals and de-

    stroyed

    the intellectual

    diversity

    that mankind

    enjoyed

    before

    it

    moved from

    simple

    communication

    to Western domination. We

    cannot

    know

    what the Is-

    lamic, Indian,

    or

    Chinese astral sciences

    might

    have

    become had this

    not

    hap-

    pened, except

    that

    they

    would not have become

    what our

    culture

    has

    produced.

    But

    unraveling

    the intertwined

    webbing

    of these sciences is a

    fascinating

    and

    a

    rewarding

    task for a

    historian,

    and

    one

    in

    which much

    remains to be done. I

    strongly

    recommend to those of

    you

    who

    have

    the

    opportunity

    hus to broaden

    yourperspectivesto graspit.

    563