Top Banner
DRAFT 1 Hegel on Legal Philosophy and Legal History N.W. Sage The initial sections of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right contain a sustained invective against those who “obscur[e] the difference between the historical and the philosophical study of law.” 1 “To consider particular laws as they appear and develop in time is a purely historical task … appreciated and rewarded in its own sphere [but having] no relation whatsoever to the philosophical study of the subject.” 2 According to Hegel, legal philosophy and legal history must “preserve an attitude of mutual indifference.” 3 There can be no dialogue between them—neither field should purport to improve, or to challenge, the other. Why does Hegel insist upon this quarantine of legal philosophy from legal history? Answering that question may help to illuminate current controversies in common law scholarship, in which philosophically‐ and historically‐minded scholars accuse each other of methodological errors that, they contend, result from mistaking the proper boundaries between distinct spheres of legal thought. 4 Understanding Hegel’s argument requires us first to ascertain what he means by legal “philosophy” and by legal “history,” in order to see how he draws the boundaries between those fields, and therefore why he insists upon keeping them distinct. 5 For Hegel, legal philosophy endeavors to show the legal concepts that judges and lawyers apply, together with the results of the application of those concepts, to be rational. Opposed to legal philosophy is the positive * S.J.D. Candidate, University of Toronto, [email protected]. This is a work in progress at a very early stage, and I would greatly appreciate any comments. 1 G.W.F. HEGEL,PHILOSOPHY OF RIGHT § 3R (T.M. Knox trans., 1952) (1821). 2 Id. 3 Id. 4 See, for example, the controversy last decade over approaches to private law among Stephen Waddams, DIMENSIONS OF PRIVATE LAW:CATEGORIES AND CONCEPTS IN ANGLO‐AMERICAN LEGAL REASONING (2003); Stephen A. Smith, A Map of the Common Law? 40 CAN.BUS. L.J. 364 (2004); Stephen Waddams, Response, 40 CAN.BUS. L.J. 396 (2004); Allan Beever & Charles Rickett, Interpretive Legal Theory and the Academic Lawyer, 68 MOD. L. REV. 320 (2005); Steve Hedley, The Shock of the Old: Interpretivism in Obligations, in STRUCTURE AND JUSTIFICATION IN PRIVATE LAW (Charles Rickett & Ross Grantham eds., 2008). 5 Hegel generally discusses the philosophy of “right,” which for him extends beyond law to include, for example, the norms of family relations and civil society. However, this paper considers Hegel’s remarks only insofar as they apply to law.
23

Hegel on legal history and legal philosophy v 2 · DRAFT 1 Hegel on Legal Philosophy and Legal History N.W. Sage The initial sections of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right contain a sustained

Sep 18, 2018

Download

Documents

lamduong
Welcome message from author
This document is posted to help you gain knowledge. Please leave a comment to let me know what you think about it! Share it to your friends and learn new things together.
Transcript
Page 1: Hegel on legal history and legal philosophy v 2 · DRAFT 1 Hegel on Legal Philosophy and Legal History N.W. Sage The initial sections of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right contain a sustained

DRAFT

1

HegelonLegalPhilosophyandLegalHistoryN.W.SageTheinitialsectionsofHegel’sPhilosophyofRightcontainasustainedinvectiveagainstthosewho“obscur[e]thedifferencebetweenthehistoricalandthephilosophicalstudyoflaw.”1“Toconsiderparticularlawsastheyappearanddevelopintimeisapurelyhistoricaltask…appreciatedandrewardedinitsownsphere[buthaving]norelationwhatsoevertothephilosophicalstudyofthesubject.”2AccordingtoHegel,legalphilosophyandlegalhistorymust“preserveanattitudeofmutualindifference.”3Therecanbenodialoguebetweenthem—neitherfieldshouldpurporttoimprove,ortochallenge,theother.

WhydoesHegelinsistuponthisquarantineoflegalphilosophyfromlegalhistory?Answeringthatquestionmayhelptoilluminatecurrentcontroversiesincommonlawscholarship,inwhichphilosophically‐andhistorically‐mindedscholarsaccuseeachotherofmethodologicalerrorsthat,theycontend,resultfrommistakingtheproperboundariesbetweendistinctspheresoflegalthought.4

UnderstandingHegel’sargumentrequiresusfirsttoascertainwhathemeansbylegal“philosophy”andbylegal“history,”inordertoseehowhedrawstheboundariesbetweenthosefields,andthereforewhyheinsistsuponkeepingthemdistinct.5

ForHegel,legalphilosophyendeavorstoshowthelegalconceptsthatjudgesandlawyersapply,togetherwiththeresultsoftheapplicationofthoseconcepts,toberational.Opposedtolegalphilosophyisthepositive

*S.J.D.Candidate,UniversityofToronto,[email protected],andIwouldgreatlyappreciateanycomments.1G.W.F.HEGEL,PHILOSOPHYOFRIGHT§3R(T.M.Knoxtrans.,1952)(1821).2Id.3Id.4See,forexample,thecontroversylastdecadeoverapproachestoprivatelawamongStephenWaddams,DIMENSIONSOFPRIVATELAW:CATEGORIESANDCONCEPTSINANGLO‐AMERICANLEGALREASONING(2003);StephenA.Smith,AMapoftheCommonLaw?40CAN.BUS.L.J.364(2004);StephenWaddams,Response,40CAN.BUS.L.J.396(2004);AllanBeever&CharlesRickett,InterpretiveLegalTheoryandtheAcademicLawyer,68MOD.L.REV.320(2005);SteveHedley,TheShockoftheOld:InterpretivisminObligations,inSTRUCTUREANDJUSTIFICATIONINPRIVATELAW(CharlesRickett&RossGranthameds.,2008).5Hegelgenerallydiscussesthephilosophyof“right,”whichforhimextendsbeyondlawtoinclude,forexample,thenormsoffamilyrelationsandcivilsociety.However,thispaperconsidersHegel’sremarksonlyinsofarastheyapplytolaw.

Page 2: Hegel on legal history and legal philosophy v 2 · DRAFT 1 Hegel on Legal Philosophy and Legal History N.W. Sage The initial sections of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right contain a sustained

DRAFT

2

studyoflaw:thestudyoflegalresultsorconceptswithoutregardfortheirrationalbasis.Oneformofpositivism,accordingtoHegel,islegalhistory.

Becauselegalphilosophyisconcernedwithlaw’srationality,andlegalhistorywiththelaw’shistoricalcausesirrespectiveoftheirrationality,thetwofieldsare“mutuallyindifferent.”Difficultiesarisewhenoneofthefieldsoverreaches:whenalegalhistorianpurportstoimproveortochallengethephilosophicalunderstandingofthelaw,orviceversa.ForHegelsuchoverreachingamountstoasortofcategorialerror,whichyieldsonlyobscurity.

Yet,despitehisadmonitionsagainstmixinglegalphilosophyandhistory,Hegelalsoenvisageswhatwemaycalla“philosophicalhistory”ofthelaw.Thisisastoryofthelaw’sdevelopmentthatendeavorstoshowthatprocesstoberational.(Thesortof“teleology”forwhichHegelisnotorious.)Arguably,anexemplarofthissortofrationalreconstructionistraditionalcommonlawreasoning:themarshalingofprecedentsthatjudgesandlawyersundertakeinordertoestablishwhatthelawis.Hegel’sworksuggestsnotonlythatthepursuitofaphilosophicalhistoryoflawislegitimate,butthatitmaybeobligatoryforthosewhoseekafullunderstandingofthelaw’srationality.

A.WhatisthePhilosophyofLaw?

InhisEncyclopediaofthePhilosophicalSciences,Hegeldefines“philosophy”asthe“thinkingstudyofobjects.”6Ithasbeensaidthat“Hegel’sbriefdefinitionsofphilosophy”alongtheselines“are,asheadmits,usuallyunilluminating.”7However,inthePrefaceandfirsttwoparagraphsofhisPhilosophyofRight,Hegelelaborateswhathemeansbythe“thinkingstudyofobjects,”discussinginsomedetailbothwhatthe“objects”oflegalphilosophyare,andwhatitmeansto“think”philosophicallyaboutthem.

i.TheObjectsofLegalPhilosophy:RealizedLegalConcepts

TheobjectsofHegel’sphilosophyoflawaretheconceptsthatarerealizedinthepracticeoflaw:theconceptsendorsedandacteduponbyjudgesandlawyersintheirofficialcapacities,andwhicharethereforeaccessibletousbecauseoftheir“publicrecognitionandformulationin

6G.W.F.HEGEL,ENCYCLOPEDIAOFTHEPHILOSOPHICALSCIENCESI§2.7MICHAELINWOOD,AHEGELDICTIONARY220(1992).

Page 3: Hegel on legal history and legal philosophy v 2 · DRAFT 1 Hegel on Legal Philosophy and Legal History N.W. Sage The initial sections of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right contain a sustained

DRAFT

3

thelawoftheland.”8Wemightthinkhereofthevariousdoctrines,rules,principles,maxims,tests,andsoonspecifiedinthecommonlaw.

Hegel’sfocusonrealizedlegalconceptsmeansthatheisnotconcernedtounderstandconceptsmerelyinabstraction,butinconjunctionwiththeconcreteresultsoftheirapplication.Indeed,forHegel,legalconceptandresultareinseparable:thereisa“completeinterpenetration”betweenthem.9Wecantrulyunderstandagivenlegalconceptonlybyconsideringthelegalresultsthatityields.10Conversely,alegalresultiscomprehensibleonlywhenviewedthroughthelensofsomelegalconcept.11Wemightsay,intoday’sjargon,that“all(legal)dataistheory‐laden”:eventheinitialisolationandcharacterizationofagivenlegalresultisinfluencedbyourbackgroundconceptualassumptions.Or,toputitanotherway,thedescriptionsofalegalresultandoftheconceptthatyieldsthatresultarereallyjustthesamedescriptionstatedatdifferentlevelsofabstraction.

Whyisitonlytherealizedlegalconcept—theunionofconceptandresult—thatinterestsHegel?Thiscanbebrokenintotwoquestions.First,whynotstudylegalresults,independentlyofthelegalconceptswhoseapplicationjudgesandlawyersclaimyieldsthoseresults?Whynottakethesetoflegalresultsandthenanalyzethemusingother,non‐legalconcepts?Somethinglikethisapproachisinfactadoptedby,forexample,manyoftoday’seconomicanalystsoflaw.Theytakeastheirdataasetoflegaloutcomes,andthenseektoevaluatetheefficiencyofthoseoutcomesusingsophisticatedeconomicconceptsthatareforeigntolegalanalysis.

OneanswertothisquestionconnectswithHegel’sthoughtthatthereisa“completeinterpenetration”betweenlegalconceptandresult,theoryanddata.Thedatasetof“legalresults”—say,forargument’ssake,thesetofdecisionsdescribedinlawreporters—isinitiallysalienttousbecauseitisasetofresultspickedoutbylegalconcepts.Theboundariesand8G.W.F.HEGEL,PHILOSOPHYOFRIGHT§1(S.W.Dydetrans.1896)(“ThephilosophicscienceofrighthasasitsobjecttheIdeaofright,i.e.,theconceptionofrightandtherealizationofthatconception.”)Hegel,notoriously,isamonist,assumingthereisultimatelyasingle“Idea,”thoughitmaytakeavarietyofdifferent“shapes.”SeePreface;§1R.Howeverthislanguageissoobscuretoourearsthatitispreferabletospeakof“concepts”intheplural,whilebearinginmindthatHegelthinkstheseareultimatelyinsomesenseunitary.Seefurtherinfranote34.9§1A(Dyde,Knox).10§1R(Knox)(“Theshapeswhichtheconceptassumesinthecourseofitsactualizationareindispensablefortheknowledgeoftheconceptitself.”)11Id.(“Allelse,apartfromthisactualityestablishedthroughtheworkingoftheconceptitself,isephemeral....”)

Page 4: Hegel on legal history and legal philosophy v 2 · DRAFT 1 Hegel on Legal Philosophy and Legal History N.W. Sage The initial sections of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right contain a sustained

DRAFT

4

natureofthesetitself(nottomentionthecharacterizationofeachresultwithintheset)arespecifiedbyconceptsoflegalauthority(suchasstaredecisis,ratiodecidendi,jurisdiction,andsoon)andsubstantivelegaldoctrine(forexample,thereporterwilldescribeonlycasesthatareimportanttoagivendoctrinalfield).Now,wecanofcourseapplynon‐legalconcepts,suchastheconceptsofeconomicanalysis,toevaluatethesetoflegalresults.Butifwedo,wewillquicklyfindthatthesetofresultsthatthelegalconceptspickoutisbothnarrowerandbroaderthanthesetofresultsthatournon‐legalconcernswouldnaturallyreach.12Forexample,theconceptsofclassicaleconomicanalysisrelatetoallinstancesofself‐interestedmaximizinghumanconduct,andnottootherformsofhumanconduct,irrespectiveofwhethertheconductisdescribedinlawreporters.Theconjunctionofonesetofconceptswiththesetofresultspickedoutbyanothersetofconceptsisthereforeintellectuallyarbitrary.AndforHegel,anygenuinefieldofintellectualinquirymustavoidsucharbitrarylimitationsonitsscope.Eachfieldmustpursueitssubject‐mattersystematically.13

Furthermore,ifouraimistoexplainouractuallegalpracticesandinstitutions,thenstudyinglegalresultsusingnon‐legalconceptswillinevitablyproduceafailureofexplanation.Thisisbecause,totheextentoneseekstoexplainthelegalresultsusingconceptsotherthanthosethatjudgesandlawyersthemselvesusetoproducethoseresults,thenonefailstoexplainwhatthoselegalactorsareactuallydoing,oratleastwhattheypurporttobedoing.Legalactorsthemselvesinvokelegalconceptstoexplainthelegalresultsatwhichtheyarrive.Ifweuseother,non‐legalconceptstoexplainthelegalresults,thentheroleofthelegalconceptsthatjudgesandlawyersthemselvesusebecomesutterlymysterious.

(Perhapsthelegalconceptsthatjudgesandlawyersthemselvesusecanbeexplainedawayasadelusion,orafraud—adeceptionthattheytellthemselves,orothers,inordertoconcealthetruemotivationsforwhattheyaredoing.14However,evenifitisacceptabletoexplainawaylegalactors’conductasdelusionalorfraudulent,thisapproachneverthelessfailstoexplaintheconceptualcontentofthedelusionorfrauditself.Whythisdelusion,thisfraud—asopposedtoothersthat

12Cf.MICHAELOAKESHOTT,ONHUMANCONDUCT9‐10(1975).13See,e.g.,INWOOD,supranote7,at265‐68(“ScienceandSystem”).HegelnotesinthePhilosophyofRightthatthatworkpresupposesanacquaintancewithgenuinely“scientific”procedure,assetoutinhisScienceofLogic.SeePreface,§2R.14CompareJodyKraus,TransparencyandDeterminacyinCommonLawAdjudication:APhilosophicalDefenseofExplanatoryEconomicAnalysis,93VA.L.REV.287(2007).

Page 5: Hegel on legal history and legal philosophy v 2 · DRAFT 1 Hegel on Legal Philosophy and Legal History N.W. Sage The initial sections of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right contain a sustained

DRAFT

5

mighthavebeenjustaseffective?15Thelegalconcepts—theconceptsthatare“publicallyrecognizedandformulatedinthelawoftheland”—hereremainunexplained.)

Second,thequestionofwhyitisonlyrealizedlegalconceptsthatinterestHegelcanbeposedintheoppositeway:whynotinvestigateabstractconcepts,irrespectiveofwhethertheyarerealized,i.e.,haveyieldedconcreteresults?ForHegel,legalphilosophyisunconcernedwithconceptsthataremerefanciesorimaginings,whichareas‐yetunrealizedintheactualpracticeandinstitutionsofthelaw—suchasthewishesofutopiansorpotentialmoralentrepreneurs,forexample.Butwhyshouldonenotphilosophizeabouttheproposalsofutopiansandwould‐bereformers?

Therearetwoanswerstothisquestion,eachasideofthesamecoin.Foronething,theneedtounderstandwhatsomepersonorgrouphappenstowishaboutthelawislesspressingthantheneedtounderstandthelawitself.Wearenotsubjecttootherpersons’whimsaboutwhatthelawoughttobe.Weare,however,subjecttothelaw.Thus,thereisademandtounderstandrealizedlegalconceptsthatdoesnotexistwithrespecttomerelegalwishes.

Relatedly,thereisnoreasontoexpectpersons’merewishesaboutthelawtobesusceptibleofunderstanding,becausethereisnoreasontoexpectmerewishestobecoherent.Ajudge,forexample,canwishfortheadoptionofwhateverlegalconceptshewants,regardlessofwhetherthatwishiscompatiblewithherotherlegalcommitments—withtheensembleofrealizedlegalconceptsthatsheiswillingtoactupon.16Forexample,ajudgemaykeenlywishthatthatshedidnothavetoawarddamagesforabreachofcontractagainstanimpecuniousdefendant.However,thedisciplineofrealizingofalegalconceptinaconcreteresultforcesthejudge’shand,requiringhertoreconciletheconceptorresultforwhichshewisheswithotherlegalconceptstowhichsheiscommitted,modifyingorabandoninganyconceptstotheextenttheyaremutuallyincompatible.Forexample,thejudgewillnotrealizeherwishthattheimpecuniouscontractualdefendantbeleftunharmed,totheextentthatthatwishisincompatiblewiththeneedtocompensatetheplaintiffforhisloss.Becausetherealizationofaconcreteresultforcesone’shandinthisway,theensembleofone’srealizedconceptsmustbe15Cf.MichaelOakeshott,OnMisunderstandingHumanConduct,4POL.THEORY353,361(1976)(Nietzsche’ssyphiliscouldnotexplainZarathustra).16Cf.ARTHURRIPSTEIN,FORCEANDFREEDOM:KANT’SLEGALANDPOLITICALPHILOSOPHY109(2009).

Page 6: Hegel on legal history and legal philosophy v 2 · DRAFT 1 Hegel on Legal Philosophy and Legal History N.W. Sage The initial sections of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right contain a sustained

DRAFT

6

mutuallycoherent,inawaythatone’sunrealizedconceptsneednotbe.(Hencelegalscholarsoftencontrasttheirintellectualenterprisetothatofmoralphilosophers,whoareblissfullyunconstrainedbyanyrequirementthattheyarticulateprinciplescapableofauthoritativelyresolvingconcretedisputes.)17

ThatweshoulddemandandexpecttrueunderstandingonlyofrealizedlegalconceptsexplainsHegel’sobsession,evidentatthebeginningofthePhilosophyofRightasinmuchofhisotherwork,withdistinguishinggenuinephilosophyfromtheRomantictendencyto“philosophize”byarticulatingone’sownpersonalsentimentsorwishes.18Suchwishesarenotproperobjectsofphilosophy.Hegel’spointherewouldseemtoapplyequallytomuchcontemporarylegalscholarship.Consider,forexample,theinnovationsofcontemporaryeconomicanalystsofcontractlawwhosuggestthatthelawoughttoadopthithertounknownconceptionsofcontractualdamages,19orshouldimposecontractswithouttheparties’consent,20andsoon.

Finally,itisworthnotingthatHegelalsocontraststhestudyofrealizedconceptswithanother“unphilosophic”method,thatofproceedingbydefinition.21(Herewemightperhapsthinkoftheariddogmatismor“formalism”associatedbyAmericanLegalRealistswiththeirpredecessorsinthelegalacademy.)22DefiningthelegalconceptsatissueattheoutsetoftheinquiryisproblematicforHegel.Forastart,thisapproachislikelytoleadtoadivergencebetweenone’sdefinitionalconcepts,ontheonehand,andthelegalconceptsactuallyrealizedintheworld,ontheother.Inthisrespect,definitionalformalismwouldsufferfromthesamedefectasRomanticism.Hegel,however,ismoreconcernedwithanotherdangerofproceedingbydefinition:thatitwillyieldanunderstandingthatcomportswithreceivedopinionorcommonsenseaboutourconcepts,butwhichisnottrulyrational.23ThisconcernleadsustoHegel’sideasabouttheconnectionbetweenphilosophyandrationality.

17E.g.RICKBIGWOOD,EXPLOITATIVECONTRACTS7‐8(2003).18Preface,§2R. 19RichardCraswell,AgainstFullerandPerdue,U.CHI.L.REV.99(2000).20OmriBen‐Shahar,ContractsWithoutConsent:ExploringaNewBasisForContractualLiability,152U.PA.L.REV.1829(2004).21§2R.22HegelprobablyhasinmindSpinozaandtheGermanrationalists.SeeINWOOD,supranote7,at74‐77.23§2R,§215n.68(Knox).

Page 7: Hegel on legal history and legal philosophy v 2 · DRAFT 1 Hegel on Legal Philosophy and Legal History N.W. Sage The initial sections of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right contain a sustained

DRAFT

7

ii.ThinkinginLegalPhilosophy:RevealingaRationalBasis

Aswehaveseen,tophilosophizeaboutlawistothinkaboutcertainobjects:realizedlegalconcepts.Butwhatis“thinking”here—whatistheactivityoflegalphilosophy?AnanswerappearsinthePhilosophyofRight’sPreface,whereHegeldescribesthetaskoflegalphilosophyastomakeourrealizedlegalconcepts“appearwell‐foundedtountrammeledthinking.”24This,heexplains,meanstobringouttheimplicitrationalityofthoseconcepts.25Thatis,tomaketheimplicitrationalityofourrealizedlegalconceptsexplicit.26

What,then,isitforsomethingtobe,initially,“implicitly”rational,andforthisrationalitythentobemade“explicit”?HereHegelanalogizesourrealizedlegalconceptstothenaturalworld.27Weassumethatthenaturalworldisgovernedbyvariouslaws—physical,biological,chemical,andsoon—thatareintelligibletous.Inthiswaythenaturalworldcanbethoughtofas“implicitly”rational.Itawaitsthethinkerorscientistwhowillmakethatrationality“explicit,”bydiscoveringandarticulatingtheexplanationorlawthatmakesthenaturalphenomenonintelligible.Likewise,theHegelianlegalphilosophermustproceedonthebasisthattheconceptsrealizedinthelawareimplicitlyintelligible—thattheyaresusceptibleofunderstanding.Thephilosopher’staskistomakethisintelligibility“explicit”byarticulatingtherationalbasisofthelegalconcepts.28(Inthisrespect,itisnotablethatHegelregardsphilosophyassiblingtotwootherhumanenterprises,religionandart,whichalsoseektorendertheworldintelligibletous,butinalessarticulateorexplicitmanner.)29

Thereisasense,then,inwhichwecanregardHegelasasupremerationalist.30Hetakesnotonlythenaturalworld,butalsohumanconduct,includinglaw,tobeinherentlysusceptibleofunderstanding.Thisobviouslyrunscountertoourcontemporarytendencytoassumethat,whilenaturemayberationallyapprehended(ornot,dependingon

24Preface(Knox)at3.25Preface(Dyde)atxii.26ThisisafavoritethemeofRobertBrandom’s.E.g.MAKINGITEXPLICIT(1998).27Preface(Dyde)atxiii,(Knox)at4.28We“mustdeveloptheidea,whichisthereasonofanobject,outoftheconception.”§2(Dyde).29AscontendedinthePhenomenologyofSpiritVII.30Cf.LeoStrauss,LecturesonHegel’sPhilosophyofHistory,Lecture1at1:27(Jan.5,1965),http://leostrausscenter.uchicago.edu/course/hegel‐philosophy‐history‐winter‐quarter‐1965(“Hegelissurelythemostradicalrationalistthateverwas.”)

Page 8: Hegel on legal history and legal philosophy v 2 · DRAFT 1 Hegel on Legal Philosophy and Legal History N.W. Sage The initial sections of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right contain a sustained

DRAFT

8

whatonethinksofquantumphysics),humanpracticessuchaslawneednotbedeeplyintelligibleinthesameway.

Ifphilosophizingismakingourrealizedconcepts’implicitrationalityexplicit,whatexactlyisrationality?Itistemptingtoavoidthistopicaltogether,sinceanythingsaidaboutitwillnecessarilybecrudeandinadequate.Butsomethingmustbesaid,giventhatthecentralityoftheideaofrationalitytoHegel’sarguments,andinordertoavoidassociatingHegelwithviewsaboutrationalitytowhichhewouldobject.(Inparticular,anyformofmetaphysicalrealism.)

Wecansaythat,forHegel,agivenlegalresultisrationalifitisyieldedbyalegalconceptthatisrational.Andagivenlegalconceptisrationalifitismutuallysupportedbyourotherlegalconcepts.Thatis,iftheconceptisrequiredby(isinferablefrom),andinturnrequires(yieldsbyinference)theotherlegalconceptsthatweendorse.31

First,then,foragivenlegalresulttoberational,itmustflowfromtheapplicationofalegalconcept.Aconceptmustbethereasonfortheresult.32Totakeafacileexample,acourtmightholdathree‐year‐olddefendantnotliablefornegligencebecauseoftheconceptthatpersonsshouldnotbelegallyliableuntiltheyhavereachedatleasttheageofseven.Aresultsuchasthisthatflowsfromtheapplicationofalegalconceptcancontrastedwithanon‐rationalresult:onethatisnotexplicableinconceptualtermsbecauseithasanonconceptualcause.Thiswouldbethecase,forexample,ifthejudgedecidedtherewasnoliabilityjustbecauseof“whatshehadforbreakfast.”

Second,foragivenlegalconcepttoberational,itmustbeonethatstandsinarelationofmutualinferabilitywiththeotherlegalconceptsthatweendorse.Agivenconceptisobviouslyirrationalifitisincompatiblewithotherlegalconceptsthatweendorse:theseven‐years‐old‐before‐liabilityrulecouldnotrationallystandtogetherwiththenotionthateveryoneisfullyresponsiblefortheirconductnomattertheirage.Incontrast,alegalconceptisrationalifitstandsinarelationofmutualsupportwiththeotherlegalconceptsthatweendorse:ifitisinferablefrom,andcanitselfbeusedtoinfer,thoseotherconceptualcommitments.Theseven‐years‐old‐before‐liabilityrulemightstandina

31See,e.g.,ROBERTB.BRANDOM,REASONINPHILOSOPHY:ANIMATINGIDEASch.4§4(2009).32Ofcourse,itmaybeobjectedthatlegalconceptsaretooindeterminatetoyieldconcreteresults.Thatobjectioncannotbeadequatelyaddressedhere,butseeBrandom,infranote71.

Page 9: Hegel on legal history and legal philosophy v 2 · DRAFT 1 Hegel on Legal Philosophy and Legal History N.W. Sage The initial sections of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right contain a sustained

DRAFT

9

rationalrelationofthissorttotheconceptthatlegalresponsibilityrequiresacertainlevelofintellectualmaturity,andtheconceptthatthatstageofmaturityisreachedatageseven.

Itmightbethoughtthatalegalconceptmayberational,evenifitdoesnotstandinanyrelationofmutualsupportwithourotherconcepts,solongasitisnotincompatiblewiththem.However,whilesuchaconceptwouldnotberationallynegated,itwouldberationallyinexplicable.Sinceitwouldbeunconnectedwithanyotherconceptthatweendorse,wewouldsimplyhavenobasisuponwhichtosaythatitisrational.Sucha“concept”(ifitcouldbecalledaconcept)wouldhavenorationalsignificancewhatsoever.33

BecauseHegelianrationalityinvolvesrevealinghoweachofourconceptsstandsinarelationofmutualsupportwithourotherconcepts,wearequicklypropelledtowardsasortofradicalconceptualholism.34Anencompassing,amorphousholismisavicewithwhichHegelisoftenassociated.However,ourexpectationsinthisrespectarelikelytobeupsettosomeextentbythePhilosophyofRight,becausethereHegelcautionsattheoutsetagainstatoo‐quickpursuitofholisticexplanation.InthesecondparagraphofthePhilosophyofRight,Hegelsaysthat“theorigin[s]”oftheconceptsoflawfall“outsideof”thephilosophyoflaw,andthatlegalphilosophymustpresupposeratherthanseektoprovethoseorigins.35

Wemightunderstandthisremarkinthefollowingway.Eventually,giventheHegelianphilosopher’staskofpursuingtherationalconnectionsbetweenallofourconcepts,itwillbenecessarytoconsidertherelationsbetweenourlegalconceptsandnon‐legalconceptsemployedinotherfieldsofknowledge—suchastheconceptsofethicsandmoralitygenerally,forexample.Butphilosophizingmuststartsomewhere:itmustbeginbyinvestigatingcertainconcepts,whileleavingotherspresupposed.Forexample,wemustbeabletobeginthephilosophyofreligionwithoutunderstandingthewholeoflogicorlinguistics.36

33Seeid.34SeeRobertBrandom,HolismandIdealisminHegel’sPhenomenology,inASPIRITOFTRUST(draft,forthcoming).Seealsosupranote8.35§2(Dyde).36“Philosophyformsacircle.Ithas,sinceitmustsomehowmakeabeginning,aprimary,directlygivenmatter,whichisnotprovedandisnotaresult.”§2A(Dyde).

Page 10: Hegel on legal history and legal philosophy v 2 · DRAFT 1 Hegel on Legal Philosophy and Legal History N.W. Sage The initial sections of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right contain a sustained

DRAFT

10

Thephilosopheroflaw’sstartingpointisourlegalconcepts.And,havingbegunatthatstartingpoint,thelegalphilosophercannotthenproceedbyrelatingthelegalconceptstootherconceptsthatshearbitrarilychoosesfromdifferentdomainsofhumanexperience.Thatwouldbejustlikethearbitraryconjunctionoflegalresultswithnon‐legalconceptsthatwasrejectedabove.Genuineknowledgemust,forHegel,bepursuedsystematically.Ithastorespectandaccountfortherelationsbetweenconceptsthatourconceptsthemselvessuggest.Thus,itmustrespectandaccountforthewayinwhichdifferentkindsofconceptsaregrouped—thewayinwhichtheyarerelatedtootherconceptsofthesamekindanddistinguishedfromdifferentkindsofconcepts.Thereforethephilosopherwhobeginswithlawmustfirstunderstandhowtheconceptsoflawrelatetoeachother,beforerelatingthemtoothernon‐legalconcepts.

Ofcoursethisispossibleonlyiflegalconceptsaretosomeextentdistinguishablefromnon‐legalconcepts.Todaylegaltheoristsoftendenythis.Butawholesaledenialseemsimplausible.Wecanobservethatlegalreasoningatleastpurportstobe,tosomeextent,distinctfromotherformsofreasoning.Theconceptsthatlawyersdeploytoexplainlegalresultscomefromthe“limiteddomainofthelaw”:37theyare,forexample,conceptssuchasmensreaorstrictscrutinyorfairuse,andnotconceptssuchasentropyordialecticalmaterialismorNashequilibrium.

B.ThePositiveAspectsofLaw

Afterdescribingthenatureoflegal“philosophy”inthefirsttwoparagraphsofthePhilosophyofRight,Hegelseemstochangetackabruptly.Inthethirdparagraph,hebeginstodiscussthewaysinwhichlawmaybepositive.Asweshallsee,itisintheRemarktothisthirdparagraphthatHegeldrawsthedistinctionwithwhichweareprimarilyconcerned,betweenlegalphilosophyandlegalhistory.

Hegeltellsusthatlawmaybe“positive”both“(a)initsform”and“(b)[in]content.”38Thepositiveformoflawissomethingwithwhichwearetodayfamiliar,thankstocontemporarylegalpositivism.Hegeltellsusthatlawispositiveinformwhenithas“theformofbeingvalidinaparticularstate.”39Thus,whatHegelcallsformallegalpositivitycallstomindthecontemporarylegalpositivist’sso‐called“sourcesthesis”:the37FrederickSchauer,TheLimitedDomainoftheLaw,90VA.L.REV.1909(2004).38§3(Knox).39§3.

Page 11: Hegel on legal history and legal philosophy v 2 · DRAFT 1 Hegel on Legal Philosophy and Legal History N.W. Sage The initial sections of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right contain a sustained

DRAFT

11

thesisthattheexistenceorvalidityofalawcanbedeterminedmerelybyreferencetothesourceofitspromulgation(suchasaparliamentaryenactmentorjudicialopinion,forexample).40

However,Hegel’sothervarietiesofpositivism,whichconcernthecontentofthelaw,arelikelylessfamiliartous.Hegelliststhreewaysinwhichlawacquiresapositivecontent:

(α)throughtheparticularnationalcharacterofapeople,itsstageofhistoricaldevelopment,andthewholecomplexofrelationsconnectedwiththenecessitiesofnature;(β)becauseasystemofpositivelawmustnecessarilyinvolvetheapplicationoftheuniversalconcepttotheparticular,externallygiven,characteristicsofobjectsandcases…;(γ)throughthefinallydetailedprovisionsrequisiteforactuallypronouncingjudgmentincourt.41

Whatdoalloftheseversionsoflegalpositivityhaveincommon?

ForHegel,thepositiveisanythingthatexists,irrespectiveofwhetheritisrational—thatis,irrespectiveofwhetheritistheproductofsomeconceptthatweendorse.InHegel’smetaphoricallanguage,themerelypositiveisthat“fromwhichthespirithasflown.”42Thus,forexample,inhisearlyessay,OnthePositivityoftheChristianReligion,HegeldescribeshowtheoriginalteachingsofJesus,whichHegeltakestoberationalmoralprinciples,becameoverthecourseoftheensuingcenturieslargelypositiveastheywerecodifiedandglossedbytheCatholicChurch.

Thus,wecanseewhatlegalpositivityisforHegel:legalconceptsandresultsthatarise,orareunderstood,independentlyofanyrationalbasis.Apositiveaccountoflawexplainsalegalresultorconceptashavingsomebasisotherthanitsinferencefromalegalconceptthatweendorse.OrasHegelputsit,suchanaccountexplainsthelawbasedonfactorsorcausesthatare“external”tothelaw’srationality.

NowwecanseewhatitisthatthedifferentvarietiesofHegelianpositivismhaveincommon.Regarding(a)law’spositive“form”orsource,thisis,ascontemporarylegalpositivistsinsist,independentofor“externalto”thelaw’ssubstantiverationality.Hencetheothermajortenetofcontemporarylegalpositivism,theso‐called“separability

40JOSEPHRAZ,THEAUTHORITYOFLAW47‐50(1979).41§3(Knox).42OntheRecentDomesticAffairsofWürtemberg,inHEGEL’SPOLITICALWRITINGS244(T.M.Knoxtrans.1964).

Page 12: Hegel on legal history and legal philosophy v 2 · DRAFT 1 Hegel on Legal Philosophy and Legal History N.W. Sage The initial sections of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right contain a sustained

DRAFT

12

thesis”:thethesisthatarulemaybelawevenifitisimmoralorunjustified.43

Asto(b)thecontentofthelaw,thismayalsobepositive,or“externalto”therationalityofthelegalconceptsthatunderliethelaw.ToadaptananalogyofHegel’s,wemightsaythatrealizedlegalconceptsacquirepositivecontentinthesamewaythatone’sindividualactions,astheyarerealizedintheworld,incorporateelementsthatwerenotfullyintended.Youmayintend,forexample,toburndownyourenemy’shouse,butyoudonothaveanyintentionsabouttheparticularfibersofwoodthattheflameofyourmatchinitiallytouches,noraboutexactlyhowmuchofthehouseturnstoashes.Thosedetailsareinawaypartofyouraction,buttheyareexternaltoyourintention—theconceptyouhaveofyouraction,oryouraction’srationalbasis.44

HenceHegel’svarietiesofpositivelegalcontent.Takingtheseinreverseorder:(γ)thedetailedprovisionsinthejudgmentofacourtaretosomeextentarbitraryvis‐à‐visthelegalconceptthatthecourtisapplying.Forexample,asHegelpointsoutinalaterpassage:

Reasoncannotdetermine,norcanthe[legal]conceptprovideanyprinciplewhoseapplicationcoulddecidewhetherjusticerequiresforanoffence(i)acorporalpunishmentoffortylashesorthirty‐nine,or(ii)afineoffivedollarsorfourdollarsandninety‐three,four,etc.,cents,or(iii)imprisonmentofayearorthreehundredandsixty‐four,three,etc.,days,orayearandone,two,orthreedays.45

Suchmatters,sincetheyarebeyondrationaldetermination,arenottheprovenanceoflegalphilosophy.(InhisPreface,HegelmockshiscontemporaryFichtefordevelopinghispurportedlyphilosophicalanalysisof“passportregulationstosuchapitchofperfectionastorequiresuspectsnotmerelytosigntheirpassportsbuttohavetheirlikenessespaintedonthem.”)46

Likewise,(β)judgesarerequiredtoapplythegeneralconceptsoflawtotheparticularitiesofgivencases—particularitieswhosesourceisthenatureofthenonlegalworld,andwhicharethereforeexternaltothelaw’srationality.Thejudgemustsubsumetheparticularsofagivencaseundersomelegalconceptorother.Butwhetherornotanyparticular

43H.L.A.HART,THECONCEPTOFLAW185‐86(1994).44E.g.§132R;G.W.F.HEGEL,IntroductiontoTHEPHILOSOPHYOFHISTORYIII(2)(b).45§214R(Knox).Eventhefactthatajudgecanorderonlyaroundnumber(andnot,say,39.5lashes)isexternaltothelegalconcept.Id.46Prefaceat11(Knox).

Page 13: Hegel on legal history and legal philosophy v 2 · DRAFT 1 Hegel on Legal Philosophy and Legal History N.W. Sage The initial sections of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right contain a sustained

DRAFT

13

casefallsunderoneconcept,orunderanother,isnotalwaysdictatedbytheconceptsthemselves.Thus,forexample,Hegelnotesthatacourtmayhavetosettlewhetherornotaliteraryplagiarismshouldberegardedasa“theft.”47Analogizing(somewhatmisleadingly)thedistinctionbetweentheRomanDigestandPandects,Hegelimagineslegalconceptsasstatementsofgeneralprinciples,whoseparticularsubdivisionsandapplicationsmustbeworkedoutindetailbypositivelawyers.Again,thisissomethingwithwhichphilosophersshouldnotconcernthemselves.48

Thelawalsoacquirespositivecontent(α)fromthreeotherrelatedfactors.Twoofthesearethe“nationalcharacter”ofthepeopletowhom[thelaw]applies”andthevarious“relationsconnectedwiththenecessitiesofnature.”Herewecanthinkoffactorssuchastheculturaltraditionsofapeople,andacountry’sclimateandthefertilityofitssoil,whichHegel,followingMontesquieu,believedmayinfluenceitslaws.49Andfinally,anation’slawacquirespositivecontentbecauseitisinformedbythenation’s“stageofhistoricaldevelopment.”Thisbringsustolegalhistory.

C.WhatisLegalHistory?

Havingsetoutthevariouskindsoflegalpositivity,Hegelembarksuponwhatcanonlybedescribedasadiatribe,againstthosewho“obscuretheboundary”betweenlegalhistoryandlegalphilosophy.50ItisherethatHegeldevelopshisclaimthatthesetwofieldsare“mutuallyindifferent”—andmustremainso,ratherthanpurportingtoinformeachother.

Thenatureoflegalhistoryisbynowclear.Anhistoricallegalexplanation—whichisonekindof“positive”explanation—explainsagivenlegalresultorconceptindependentlyofanyrationalbasisitmayhave.Thus,anhistoricalexplanationmayshowagivenlegalresultorconcepttohavebeeninferredfromsomeotherconceptthatwedonottodayendorse.Oritmayshowthelegalresultorconcepttobetheproductofanhistoricalcausethatisnonconceptualinnature—for

47CompareKnoxn.10,citingHegel’shandwrittenmarginalnotes.48§3R&n.12(Knox).49Knoxn.9,citingHEGEL,PHILOSOPHYOFHISTORY,supranote44.Seealso§3R&n.13(Knox),citingMONTESQUIEU,THESPIRITOFTHELAWSI.3(1748).50§3R.Hegelhasinmindcertainacademiccolleagueswhosubscribedtothe“historicalschool”ofjurisprudenceassociatedwithSavigny.Knox§3Rn.17.

Page 14: Hegel on legal history and legal philosophy v 2 · DRAFT 1 Hegel on Legal Philosophy and Legal History N.W. Sage The initial sections of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right contain a sustained

DRAFT

14

example,whatacertainjudgehappenedtohaveforbreakfastsometimeinthepast.

Iflegalphilosophyisconcernedwithlaw’srationality,andlegalhistory”withitshistoricalcausesregardlessofwhethertheyarerational,thetwofieldsmustbe“mutuallyindifferent”toeachother.Andwheneitherlegalphilosophyorlegalhistoryoverreaches—attemptingtochallengeorimprovetheotherfield—obscurityensues.

Legalphilosophycanneitherchallengenorimprovelegalhistory.Cannotchallenge,becauseevenifwetodayregardalawashavingarationalbasis,flowingfromconceptsthatwenowendorse,legalhistorycanshowthatasanhistoricalmatterthatsamelawcametobeonthebooksduetonon‐rationalcauses—suchaspurehappenstanceorlegalactors’self‐interest,forexample.Legalphilosophycannotimprovelegalhistory,because,astoday’sacademichistoriansareacutelyaware,towriteourpresent‐dayrationalinsightsintothehistoricalrecordistocommitthesinof“presentism,”obscuringthetruehistoricalcausesandmotivationsofactionsandevents.

Hegel,ofcourse,ismoreconcernedtomaketheoppositepoint:thatlegalhistorycannotchallengeorimprovelegalphilosophy.Cannotchallenge,becauselegalphilosophycanshowthelawtoberational—toberequiredbyourpresentconceptualcommitments—regardlessofwhether,historically,itwastheproductofothernon‐rationalcauses.Ifwehavearationalbasisnowforagivenlegalruleorinstitution,itisirrelevantthatitalsohasnon‐rationalcausesthatledtoitsadoption.

Forexample,virtuallyeverymodernnationstatewasfoundedatleastinpartasaresultofactionsandprinciplesthatwetodayregardasevil.Indeed,thehistoryofalmostanystateisoneofsuccessiveepisodesofhypocrisy,perfidy,andbrutalitybythepersonsandgroupswhomadethatstatewhatitistoday.Nevertheless,wemayrationallyendorsethestateweliveintoday,ifwebelievethatitrealizesconcepts(oratleastendeavorstorealizeconcepts)towhichwearenowcommitted.51

Indeed,anargumentthatseekstochallengetherationalityofaconceptbasedonthewayinwhichthatconcepthistoricallycametobeadoptedcommitswhatlogicianscallthe“geneticfallacy.”Thefactthatsomeonehasarrivedatabeliefastheresultofafaultyreasoningprocessdoesnotentailthattheirbeliefisfalse.(Forexample,justbecauseJohn

51Cf.IMMANUELKANT,THEMETAPHYSICSOFMORALS[6:318](MaryJ.Gregored.&trans.,1996)(1797‐98).

Page 15: Hegel on legal history and legal philosophy v 2 · DRAFT 1 Hegel on Legal Philosophy and Legal History N.W. Sage The initial sections of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right contain a sustained

DRAFT

15

StuartMillmighthavearrivedatabeliefintheequalityofallhumanbeingsbecausehisfatherpressuredhimintoit,doesnotmeanthatthebeliefisfalse.)52

Norcanlegalhistoryimprovelegalphilosophy.Ifwedemonstratealawtoberational,thenportraying“themannerof[its]appearanceinhistory,alongwiththecircumstances,cases,wantsandevents”thatledtoitaddsnothingtotheassessmentofitsrationality.53Andthisistrueevenifthelawappearedastheproductofaconceptthateveryoneinthepastendorsed.Becausetotheextentthatconceptismerelyhistorical,ratherthanendorsedinthepresent,itsrationalityhasnowexpired.(“Thespirithasflown.”)

So,forexample,HegelsuggeststhatmanyaspectsofRomanprivatelawfollowinferentiallyfromtheconceptsofpatriapotestasandtraditionalRomanmatrimony.However,sincethoseconceptsarerepugnanttoustoday,wecannotendorseanyaspectsofprivatelawthatpurporttoderivetheirrationalbasisfromthem.54Likewise,monasteriesorcloistersmayoncehavebeenjustifiedonthebasisthattheypromotelearning.Hegelbelievedthatbyhistime,thatjustificationwasobsolete.(Presumablytheuniversityhadcometoperformthisfunction.)Therefore,Hegelpointsout,“sincecircumstanceshavenowentirelyaltered,themonasteriesareinthisrespectatleastsuperfluousandinappropriate.”55

Indeed,Hegelnotesthatwhenhistorianspurporttoimprovelegalphilosophyusinghistoricalexplanations,they“unconsciouslyachievetheveryoppositeofwhattheyintend.”56Byshiftingbetweentwofieldsthathavenothingtocontributetoeachother,thehistoriancommitsacategorialerror,andasaresultonlyobscuresthelaw’srationality,ratherthanelucidatingit.FollowingMichaelOakeshott,wecancomparethiskindofcategorialerrortoanothertraditionallogicalfallacy,“ignoratioelenchi”or“ignoringtheissue.”57Thisoccurswhen,forexample,someonemisunderstandsanargument,andthenemploysthatmisunderstandinginrespondingtotheargument.(Asin,“Themanwho

52JAMESDCARNEY&RICHARDKSCHEER,FUNDAMENTALSOFLOGICch.2(1964).53§3R(Dyde).54§3R.Infact,Hegelsuggests,manyaspectsofRomanprivatelawwerenotrationalinRomantimeseither.55§3R(Knox).56Id.57MICHAELOAKESHOTT,EXPERIENCEANDITSMODES(1933).

Page 16: Hegel on legal history and legal philosophy v 2 · DRAFT 1 Hegel on Legal Philosophy and Legal History N.W. Sage The initial sections of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right contain a sustained

DRAFT

16

said‘Miraclesdon’thappen’isblind.Whataboutpenicillin?”).58Becausethetwoargumentsareirrelevanttoeachother,theirconjunctioncanyieldonlyconfusion.Thisisexactlywhathappens,accordingtoHegel,whenonetriestoconjoinargumentsfromthedistinctfieldsoflegalhistoryandlegalphilosophy.

ThereareofcourseanumberofpossibleobjectionsthatmightberaisedagainstHegel’sdemandforthisstrictseparationoflegalhistoryfromlegalphilosophy.Letusconsiderthreeprominentones.

First,couldaconservativeapproachtolawnotrenderlegalhistoryrelevanttolegalphilosophy?Aconservativemightcontendthatweshouldapproachthelawtodaybycontinuingtoendorsethelegalconceptsandresultsthatourforebearsarrivedat—nomattertheirreasonsorcauses.

Suchanapproachwouldindeedmakelegalhistoryrelevanttolegalphilosophy.However,itwoulddosoonlybyadoptingapresent‐dayconcept,theguidingprincipleofconservatism(orsomesimilarprincipleofepistemologicalorpracticalcaution),whichhastheeffectofincorporatingthelaw’shistoryintothedomainofpresent‐dayrationality.Itisonlythispresent‐dayprinciplethatsuppliesthelaw’srationality—withoutit,thereisnoreasonwhatsoevertothinkthat,merelybecauseourforebearsarrivedatagivenlegalconceptorresult,weshouldendorsethatconceptorresultasrational.

Second,mightlegalphilosophersnotlearnfromthehistoryoflaw,andviceversa?Thesuggestionhereisthatscholarsineachfieldmightusetheotherfieldinstrumentally,asameanstothediscoveryoftruthsintheirownfield.Andthereissurelysomethingtobesaidfortheideathathistoryandphilosophycanspurnewlinesofthinkingineachother.

Forexample,understandingwhylawyersinthepasttookcertainlegalconceptstobejustifiedmaysuggestreasonswhylegalphilosopherstodayshoulddothesame.Ourenthusiasmforthismethodshould,however,bediminishedsomewhatwhenweconsiderotherpossiblesourcesofgoodideasforlegalphilosophy:forexample,bookspickeduprandomlywhilewalkingthroughalibrary,dreams,ortheravingsoflunatics.Thosesourcesmaylikewisebeusedinstrumentally,toinspirephilosophicalideas,thoughtherationalityofthoseideasisfarfromguaranteed.Itisthesamewithlegalhistory.Ofcoursehistoryisprobablyamorereliablesourceofgoodideasforunderstandingthe58CARNEY&SCHEER,supranote52.

Page 17: Hegel on legal history and legal philosophy v 2 · DRAFT 1 Hegel on Legal Philosophy and Legal History N.W. Sage The initial sections of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right contain a sustained

DRAFT

17

rationalityofourconceptsthan,say,dreams.Buthistory’sreliabilityinthisrespectshouldnotbeoverstated.Hegelhimselfclaimedthattheonlythingwelearnfromhistoryisthatpeopleneverlearnfromhistory:becauseourpresentcircumstancesareneverthesameasthehistoricalones,wecannotderivelessonsofrealvalue.59Likewise,today’shistoriansstresshowdangerousitistousehistorytoattemptunderstandthepresent,asitwillleadtoa“presentist”readingofthepast,whichitselfobscuresanyvaluabletruthsthathistorymightotherwisehavecontained.60Andthesameisofcoursetrueofattemptstousenewlymintedphilosophicalinsightsinordertounderstandwhatactuallyhappenedasanhistoricalmatter.

Insum,then,itisconceivablethatlegalphilosophyandlegalhistorymaylearnfromeachother,butonlyifeachfieldishighlycautiousandselective.Eachmusttreattheinsightsoftheotherfieldinmuchthesamewayaswewouldtreataninsightyieldedbyadream—nevertakingitatfacevalue,butrathersubjectingittothefullrigorsoftheapplicablediscipline.

Third,whataboutthecurrentlyfashionablemethodof“genealogy”?ThetermcomesfromNietzsche’sGenealogyofMorals,whichsoughttounderminetheconventionalviewthatourmoralityisagoodthingbysketchingahistoryinwhichmoralconceptsdevelopedoutofrivalsocialfactions’attemptstodominateeachother.(TheancientGreekrulingclassdefineditselfas“good,”aJudeo‐Christianunderclasswrestedpowerbyre‐defining“good”intermsofitsown“slavemorality,”andsoon.)61FoucaultcommendedthisapproachinhisNietzsche,Genealogy,History.Helikewisesoughttodisruptreceivedwisdomaboutoursocialinstitutions,byshowingthemtobetheproductofhistoricalaccidentsarisingoutofacontinualstruggleforpower.62

Thus,thebasicmethodofanhistorical“genealogy”istodiscreditexistingconceptsbyshowingthemtohaveignobleorigins.Moretechnically,wecansaythatagenealogyshowsagivenconceptorresultφthatwenowendorsetobetheproductofsomeconcept,orother

59HEGEL,PHILOSOPHYOFHISTORY,supranote44,atII§8(on“PragmaticHistory”).60SeeHERBERTBUTTERFIELD,THEWHIGINTERPRETATIONOFHISTORYIII,VI(1931).61FRIEDRICHNIETZSCHE,THEGENEALOGYOFMORALS(HoraceB.Samueltrans.,1913).62MichelFoucault,Nietzsche,Genealogy,History,inTHEFOUCAULTREADER(PaulRabinowed.,1984).

Page 18: Hegel on legal history and legal philosophy v 2 · DRAFT 1 Hegel on Legal Philosophy and Legal History N.W. Sage The initial sections of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right contain a sustained

DRAFT

18

cause,thatisnotinferentiallyrelatabletoφ—i.e.,thatcannotprovideareasonforustoendorseφ.63

ForHegel,agenealogicalattempttounderminetherationalityofthelawwouldbemisguided.Itdoesnotmatterifsomelawnowonthebookswas,historically,entirelycausedby,forexample,theself‐interestedpowerplaysofvarioushistoricalactorsorgroups.Ifthereisapresentrationalbasisforthelaw,thatcannotbeimpugnedbylegalhistory.

BrianLeiter,inhispaperTheHermeneuticsofSuspicion,presentsapossiblechallengetothiswayofthinkingaboutgenealogy.64Hearguesthatagenealogymaygeneratereasontosuspectthetruthofagivenpersonorgroup’sbelief,byshowingthatbelieftohavea“causaletiology”thatisunrelatedtothetruthofthebelief.Leitercontends:

Tobesure,beliefswiththewrongcausaletiologymightbetrue;but…wehavenoreasontopresumethattobethecase.Tothecontrary,wenowhavereasontobesuspicious—nothingmore—oftheirveritisticproperties.65

Thus,touseanexampleofLeiter’s,wewouldhavereasontosuspectthetruthofPresidentGeorgeW.Bush’sclaimthatSaddamHusseinposedathreattotheU.S.,ifweknewthatwhatcausedBushtoholdthatbeliefishisknowledge“thatitwouldbeintheinterestsoftheU.S.rulingclassestohavemorereliablecontroloverlargeMiddleEastoilreserves.”66

However,forourpurposesitisimportanttoclarifypreciselyhowthe“suspicion”isgeneratedhere.Inonesense,asuccessfulgenealogydoesmorethanmerelycauseustosuspect.Rather,itcompletelyrebutstheassumptionthattheactualhistoricaldevelopmentofthebelieforconceptinquestionwasrational.AsLeitersays,onceweareawareofthegenealogicalaccount,we“havenoreasontopresume”thatthehistoricalbasisfortheadoptionofthebeliefcoincidedwitharationalbasisforthatbelief.Forexample,onceweknowGeorgeW.Bush’sactual,historicalreasonfortakingSaddamtobeathreat,werealizethatBusharrivedathisbeliefwithoutanyrationalbasiswhatsoever.Likewise,agenealogyofalegalconceptcouldeffectivelyrebutthenaïveassumptionthattheactualhistoricaldevelopmentofthatconceptwasrational.

63RobertBrandom,FromIronytoTrust:ModernityandBeyond,inASPIRITOFTRUST134(draft,forthcoming).64BrianLeiter,TheHermeneuticsofSuspicion:RecoveringMarx,Nietzsche,andFreud,inTHEFUTUREFORPHILOSOPHY191‐94(BrianLeitered.,2004).65Id.at192‐93.66Id.at193.

Page 19: Hegel on legal history and legal philosophy v 2 · DRAFT 1 Hegel on Legal Philosophy and Legal History N.W. Sage The initial sections of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right contain a sustained

DRAFT

19

Atthesametime,agenealogyisunableinanywaytoimpugnapresentrationalbasisforabelieforconcept.Ifabelieforconcepthasapresentrationalbasis—andnoclaimismadethatthisrationalbasiscoincideswiththehistoricaldevelopmentofthebelieforconcept—agenealogyhasnobite.67Forexample,ifwehadsomerationalgroundforbelievingthatSaddamdidposeathreattotheU.S.,itwouldbeirrelevanttothetruthofthatbeliefthatGeorgeW.Bushhappenedtoarriveatitonanirrationalbasis.

Insum,genealogicalaccountsmaygiveusreasonto“suspect”therationalityofaconceptonlyinsofarastheyrebuttheassumptionthattheactualhistoricaldevelopmentoftheconceptwasrational.Theyarepowerlessinthefaceofavalidunderstandingoftheconcept’srationality.

D.APhilosophicalHistoryofLaw?

Althoughhedemandstheseparationofordinarylegalhistoryfromlegalphilosophy,inhisremarksfollowingthethirdparagraphofthePhilosophyofRight,Hegelalsoenvisageswhatwemaycalla“philosophicalhistory”ofthelaw.

Hegelmentionsinpassingthatanhistoricalaccountofourlegalconceptsmaybeusefultothephilosopher,

insofarasthedevelopmentoutofhistoricgroundscoincideswiththedevelopmentoftheconception,andthehistoricalexpositionandjustificationcanbemadetocoverajustificationwhichisvalidinitselfandindependently.68

Hegelhereseemstohaveinmindasituationwherethehistoricaldevelopmentofaconceptechoesthesequenceofthoughtsthroughwhichwe,today,cancometounderstandtherationalbasisofthatconcept.Herewemightthink,forexample,ofnegligencelaw,whichmaybetaughtbydescribingitsdevelopmentinthetwentiethcenturythroughaseriesofcourtdecisionsthatprogressivelyelucidatedthevarious

67ThesamepointcanbemadeinthecontextoftheGettierproblemsthatLeiterdiscusses.Cf.RobertB.Brandom,WhyTruthisNotImportantinPhilosophy,inREASONINPHILOSOPHY:ANIMATINGIDEASch.6(2009).68§3R(Dyde).

Page 20: Hegel on legal history and legal philosophy v 2 · DRAFT 1 Hegel on Legal Philosophy and Legal History N.W. Sage The initial sections of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right contain a sustained

DRAFT

20

componentsofthecauseofaction.69Thehistoricalnarrativeheremighthappentocoincidewithaphilosophicalunderstanding.

Butwhataboutwheretherationalunderstandingofagivenlegalconceptdoesnotcoincidewiththehistoricalrecord—where,asahistoricalmatter,non‐rationalfactorscontributedtotheconcept’sadoption?Mightitneverthelessbepossibleordesirableforphilosopherstopursuea“philosophicalhistory”here?HegeldoesnotexpresslyaddressthisintheopeningparagraphsofthePhilosophyofRight.However,elsewhereheis,notoriously,concernedtoconstructphilosophicalhistoriesor“teleological”accountsofourconcepts—mostfamously,portrayingtheentirecourseofworldhistoryasnothingotherthanthemarchofconsciousnesstowardsfreedom.70

Thissortof“philosophicalhistory”isacceptabletoHegel,notwithstandinghisadmonitionsagainstmixingordinaryhistoryandphilosophy,becauseaphilosophicalhistorydoesnotpurporttoalterourunderstandingofwhat“actually”happenedhistorically.Whereasanordinaryhistorytracestheactualdevelopmentofourconceptsandresults,whichareoftentheproductofnon‐rationalcauses,a“philosophicalhistory”isconcernedonlywithportrayingtheprocessofthelaw’sdevelopmentasrational.Itundertakesa“rationalreconstruction”oftheprocessofdevelopment,inordertodepictthegradualevolutionoftheconceptsthatweendorsetoday.(Whattoday’shistoriansmightcalla“Whighistory”ofourconcepts.)71Ofcourse,asamatteroffact,variousnon‐rationalcausesmayhaveledtotheadoptionofourcurrentconcepts,butaphilosophicalhistorytreatsthosenon‐rationalelementsasmereaccidentaldetails,whichdonotunderminetheoverallstoryofrationaldevelopment.Itdoesnotmatterthatagivenstepintheevolutionofaconceptwascaused,forexample,byanhistoricalactor’svenality,solongasthatstepwasalsorationallydemanded.

Arguably,aparadigmofthissortofrationalreconstructionofthehistoryofourconcepts,or“philosophicalhistory,”istraditionalcommonlawreasoning.Ajudgeorlawyer,marshalingprecedentsinordertoreachaconclusionaboutwhatthelawis,willoftenportraythecaselawashavinggraduallyprogressedtowardsthelegalconceptorresultthat

69Forexample,fromDonoghuev.Stevenson,[1932]A.C.562(H.L.)(dutyofcare),toTheWagonMound(No.1),[1961]A.C.388(P.C.)(remotenessofdamage),throughTheWagonMound(No.2),[1967]1A.C.617(P.C.)(standardofcare).70§§341‐60;HEGEL,PHILOSOPHYOFHISTORY,supranote44.71RobertB.Brandom,History,Reason,andReality,inREASONINPHILOSOPHY,supranote67,atIII.5.

Page 21: Hegel on legal history and legal philosophy v 2 · DRAFT 1 Hegel on Legal Philosophy and Legal History N.W. Sage The initial sections of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right contain a sustained

DRAFT

21

shebelievesoughttobereachedinthepresentcase.Shewillpickoutofthecaselawacontinuousthreadleadingtothedesiredconceptorresult,andwilldisregardotherthreadsthatcouldalsobefoundinthedecidedcases.Shewillalsodisregardanynon‐rationalcausesofthedesiredconceptorresult,suchaserroneousorevenbiasedjudicialreasoninginthepreviouscases.

Thisrationalreconstructionofthedevelopmentofthelawisafamiliarfeatureofcommonlawmethod.WhenSirEdwardCokesoughttoprovethatthecommonlawisrational,hepointedoutthat“aninfinitenumberofgraveandlearnedmen”had“finedandrefined”itoverthecenturies.72AsimilarideaunderliesRonaldDworkin’smetaphorofthejudicialchainnovel,inwhicheachsuccessivejudgeseekstointerpretanddevelopthelawinthebestwaypossible,asifhewerewritingachainnovel’slatestchapter.73Toconceiveofthecommonlawascontinuallyrefinedinthisfashionistounderstanditasaprogressivelyrationalprocess.

Manylegalacademicstoday,whoseethemselvesasinheritorsofthehard‐headedLegalRealisttradition,mightbeinclinedtocondescendtothisapproach,regardingitasthetellingoflegalfairytales.ButcompellingreasontoreconsideranysuchcondescensioncanbefoundintherecentworkoftheHegelianphilosopherRobertBrandom.Brandomsuggeststhatthemethodof“rationalreconstruction”or“philosophicalhistory,”isanessentialfeatureofhumanreasoning,notjustinthecommonlaw,butinanyfieldofintellectualinquiry.74Indeed,forBrandom,traditionalcommonlawreasoningisjustaparticularlyexplicitorwell‐articulatedversionofamethodthathumansdeploywhenevertheydeveloptheirunderstandingofanything.

Consider,forexample,acaricatureoftheevolutionofourconceptofthesun.Atonepoint,perhapsfortheancientEgyptians,thesunwasagod.Next,forsomeoftheGreeks,itwasaluminousdisctravellingthroughthesky,revolvingaroundtheearth.Then,inearlymodernEurope,itbecameaballofhotmetal,remainingstillwhiletheearthrevolvedaroundit.Forustoday,thesunisastarlikemanyothersinour

72CO.LITT.97b.73LAW’SEMPIRE228‐38(1986);RobertBrandom,AHegelianModelofLegalConceptDetermination:TheNormativeFineStructureoftheJudges’ChainNovel(paperpresentedtotheInlandNorthwestPhilosophyConference,Mar.23,2012).74Hegelhimselftendedtoimpugntherationalityofthecommonlaw(see,e.g.,§211R)andEnglishlawingeneral(seeTheEnglishReformBill,inHEGEL’SPOLITICALWRITINGS,supranote42).

Page 22: Hegel on legal history and legal philosophy v 2 · DRAFT 1 Hegel on Legal Philosophy and Legal History N.W. Sage The initial sections of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right contain a sustained

DRAFT

22

galaxy,whichradiatestheenergygivenoffbymassivethermonuclearreactions.

We,endorsingthelatterconceptionofthesun,takeourconceptiontobe(themost)trueorrational,andourpredecessors’conceptionstobegreatlyflawedbutprogressivelyimprovedapproximationsofthetruth.Importantly,intakingthisapproach,weassumethatthereisasingleobject,“thesun,”towhichallofthevariousconceptionsrefer.Wedonotjustsaythathumanshavethoughtindifferentwaysatdifferenttimesaboutvariousthingsthatappearedtothemintheskyduringtheday.

AccordingtoBrandom,thispositingofasingleobjectunderlyingallofthechangingconceptionsofit—whichisaninvariablefeatureofintellectualinquiryinanyprogressivediscipline—isasignthatweareundertakingarationalreconstructionofthehistoryofourconceptions.Thepositingofasingleobjectunderlyingthedifferentconceptionsofitallowsus(a)totakeourpresentconceptiontobethe(most)rationalone,(b)toacknowledgethatourpredecessors,althoughtheyalsoendeavoredtoberational,haddifferentconceptions,and(c)toseearationalprogressionfromourpredecessors’conceptionstoourown.Incontrast,ifwehadnoneedof(a)‐(c)—iftherewasnodemandtoportraythedevelopmentofourunderstandingasrational—wecouldbecontenttodiscardtheassumptionthatweandourpredecessorshavebeenattemptingtounderstandtheverysameobject.

Inthisrespectwemaycomparethewaythatacommonlawyerorjudgeclaimstoglean“whatthelawis”frompreviouscases,extractingacontinuousthreadofconceptualdevelopmentoutofaseriesofdecisionsthatoccurredovercenturies.Whereasiftherewerenoneedtounderstandthedevelopmentofthelawasrational,commonlawyerscouldbecontenttoregardthepreviouscasesnotasaprogressiveilluminationofasingleruleorprinciple,butasjustasuccessionofdifferentopinionsaboutwhatoughttobedone.

IfBrandomisrightthatthemethodofrationalreconstructionor“philosophicalhistory”isnotapeculiarityofthecommonlawbutafeatureofrationalityingeneral,thenweoughttotakethismethodseriouslyinlegalphilosophy.Indeed,thislineofthoughtsuggeststhatadedicatedHegelianlegalphilosopheroughttoregardthepursuitofa“philosophicalhistory”asobligatory.

Theendeavortorevealtherationalbasisofourpresent“time‐slice”ofthelawisfinesofarasitgoes:ifsuccessful,itdemonstratesthatour

Page 23: Hegel on legal history and legal philosophy v 2 · DRAFT 1 Hegel on Legal Philosophy and Legal History N.W. Sage The initial sections of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right contain a sustained

DRAFT

23

presentlegalconceptsarerational.Indeedthecommonlawoftenproceedsinthisway:alawyerorjudgeaddressestherationalityoftheensembleofapplicableprecedentsastheystandtoday,ignoringtheirhistoricalsequence.(Thisisthebasicmethodofcaselaw“synthesis”taughtinlawschoollegalreasoningclasses.)However,thisapproachcannotultimatelybesatisfactory,becauseitleavesunexplainedhowthelawarrivedatitspresentrationalstate—howitgothere,giventhatitwasnotalwayshere.

Legalphilosophersmustthereforepursueaphilosophicalhistoryiftheywanttounderstandtheprocessofthelaw’sdevelopmentasrational.75(Theycannotjustnaïvelyassumethattheactualhistoricaldevelopmentofthelawcoincideswithitsrationalbasis,becausea“genealogist”willeasilyrefutethat.)Andthereisapressingdemandtoshowthattheprocessofthelaw’sdevelopmentisrational,becausewearesubjecttothatprocess.Unlesswecanembraceitasrational,theprocesswillappeartousasmerelypositive.Inwhichcaseitsdemiseshouldbeimminent,forwewouldhavecompellingreasontoreplaceitwithanewprocesswhoserationalityisintelligibletous.

75Cf.RobertB.Brandom,History,Reason,andReality,inREASONINPHILOSOPHY,supranote67,§5.