Top Banner
PREFACE My professional career has ended and I am now happily retired. However, there are a few unpublished papers that I would like to make available. While research on the hedonic view of happiness and well-being has flourished very little has focused on Aristotle’s eudaimonic theory. These might add something to the existing literature. I believe that virtue is the most important, but greatly misunderstood, idea in Aristotle’s theory. I have included several chapters on the topic of virtue in a recent book entitled THE PSYCHOLOGY OF HAPPINESS: A GOOD HUMAN LIFE, published by Cambridge University Press. I have also included a study on crowding that may be of interest. It suggests that crowding and scarcity of resources may lead to both political and social upheaval. Although the study was conducted in the 1970’s it may portend the future for some.
18

An Examination of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-Being

May 14, 2023

Download

Documents

Welcome message from author
This document is posted to help you gain knowledge. Please leave a comment to let me know what you think about it! Share it to your friends and learn new things together.
Transcript
Page 1: An Examination of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-Being

PREFACE

My professional career has ended and I am now happily retired. However, there are a few unpublished papers thatI would like to make available. While research on the hedonic view of happiness and well-being has flourished very little has focused on Aristotle’s eudaimonic theory. These might add something to the existing literature.

I believe that virtue is the most important, but greatly misunderstood, idea in Aristotle’s theory. I have included several chapters on the topic of virtue in a recent book entitled THE PSYCHOLOGY OF HAPPINESS: A GOOD HUMAN LIFE, published by Cambridge University Press.

I have also included a study on crowding that may be of interest. It suggests that crowding and scarcity of resources may lead to both political and social upheaval. Although the study was conducted in the 1970’s it may portend the future for some.

Page 2: An Examination of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-Being

AN EMPIRICAL EXAMINATION OF ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPT OF VIRTUE

AND ITS RELATIONSHIP TO WELL—BEING

Samuel S. Franklin California State University, Fresno

PAPER PRESENTED AT THE MEETING OF THE WESTERN PSYCHOLOGICALASSOCIATIONLOS ANGELES APRIL, 1994

Page 3: An Examination of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-Being

AN EMPIRICAL EXAMINATION OF ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPT OF VIRTUE AND ITSRELATIONSHIP TO WELL-BEING

SAMUEL S. FRANKLIN

CALIFORNIA STATE UNIVERSITY, FRESNO

Aristotle's Nichomachean Ethics (NE) contains a well developed and

elaborate theory of the good life which he called 'eudaimonia.' Although

the eudaimonic theory has been largely overlooked by contemporary

researchers of well-being and happiness, we believe it has much to offer.

The theory is based upon the assumption that a good life is achieved to

the extent that one actualizes or fulfills potentials. Aristotle would

probably very much agree with Ryff's observation that "Central emphasis

has been given to short-term affective well-being (i.e. happiness), at the

expense of more enduring life challenges such as having a sense of purpose

and direction, and achieving a sense of self-realization" (Ryff, 1989).

Actualization requires the satisfaction of certain needs. According to

Aristotle we have both physical and psychological needs, or 'needs of the

soul', as he called them, such as the need for friends, art, learning,

etc. In eudaimonic theory, how we fulfill our needs is crucial.

Aristotle emphasizes the necessity of acquiring the things we need at the

right time, in the right amount and in the way. Most of the things we

need, or 'real goods' as Aristotle called them, are 'limited'; we need

them for actualization, but only in certain amounts and only at certain

times, and they may be good only if obtained in certain ways. Food, for

example, is a real good but it is not beneficial in unlimited quantities,

at any time and under all circumstances. Too little food is damaging and

too much food is equally harmful. The same may be said for most all the

things we need. In most things we are well advised to seek the 'golden

mean'.

To correctly obtain what we need, virtue is required.

...if virtue , like nature, requires more accuracy and is better than any art, then it will aim at the mean.... In feeling fear, confidence, desire, anger, pity, and in general pleasure and pain,one can feel too much or too little; and both extremes are wrong. The mean and the good is feeling at the right time, about the right things, in relation to the right people, and for the right reason; and the mean and the good are the task of virtue. Similarly, in regard to actions there are excess, deficiency, and the mean. (Nichomachean Ethics [NE] II, 5. Bambrough, 1963, p. 309)

While Aristotle may appear to be uncompromising about what is 'right', he

is not. Right is always defined relative to the person. Aristotle says "We

may now define virtue as a disposition of the soul in which, when it has

to choose among actions and feelings, it observes the mean relative to

us..." (NE II, 5. Bambrough, 1963, p. 309)

Virtue is a complex idea that became terribly misunderstood when it fell

into the company of words like sin and chastity during the middle ages

(Maclntyre, 1981). As the ancient Greeks used the term, however, virtue

is an extremely meaningful concept and I think translatable into the

language of contemporary psychology. It is the purpose of this paper to

Page 4: An Examination of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-Being

attempt such a translation and to empirically examine the relationship

between virtue and well-being. First, I will attempt to show that

Aristotle's concept of virtue is composed of several measurable

psychological processes.

VIRTUE AND REASON

The first component of virtue is reason. For the Greeks, only humans

have the capacity to think. Reason is our ergon, our highest and most

unique function. "The function of man is activity of soul in accordance

with reason..." (NE I. 7. Bambrough, p. 293). According to Aristotle

there are two related but distinguishable types of reason. Intellectual

virtue refers to something like our general intelligence, abstract

reasoning, theory, and the understanding of general principle. It

appears to be somewhat similar to what we now call fluid intelligence.

Moral virtue, on the other hand, refers to the ability to apply general

principles to specific instances. It is sometimes called practical

intelligence. Moral virtue must be learned by doing, by practice.

"Moral virtue is a product of habit" (NE II, 1. Bambrough, p. 303).

And, it is important to acquire moral virtue early in life: "It makes no

small difference, then, whether we form habits of one kind or another from

our very youth; it makes a very great difference, or rather all the

difference." (NE II, 1. Ross, p.29)

VIRTUE AND DESIRE

A second component of virtue is desire. Today we might call

desire motivation. Action alone cannot be virtuous; the

motivation which propels the behavior must also be considered.

Wanting to do what is right and best (relative to your life) is

as important as the act itself. Urmson notes that the virtuous

person wants to be virtuous and enjoys virtuous action.

"..whether one has excellent character (virtue) ... depends not merely on what one does but also on what one likes doing." Virtue is a..."settled disposition to want to act and to act in a way appropriate to the situation." (Urmson, 1988. p.26 ff)

VIRTUE AND CHOICE

Reason and desire combine to produce the third component of virtue:

choice. "Choice, therefore, is thought along with desire, or desire

along with thought." (NE VI. 2. Bambrough p. 345.) Adler (1980) notes

"... moral virtues are habits of making the right choices..." (p.94).

Once we know the appropriate action, and desire it, we must choose to

behave appropriately. Choice mediates between knowing - wanting and

acting.

VIRTUE AND SELF-CONTROL

A fourth component of virtue is self-control or restraint. Aristotle

acknowledges that desires may compete with each other and that restraint

is often required. We may know the best thing to do, and desire it too,

but we may also know and desire a contrary action. Self control

Page 5: An Examination of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-Being

influences our choice. "Virtue is within our power, and so, too is vice.

The point is that where we can act, we can also refrain, and vice versa"

(NE III. 5. Bambrough p. 323). To act one way frequently requires that

we inhibit an alternative response.

VIRTUE AND ACTION/FEELING

Finally, there is the virtuous action itself. Virtuous action includes

behavior and emotion appropriately chosen; at the correct time, in the

right amount, for the right reason. For Aristotle, action and feeling go

together, feeling 'supervenes upon acts'. That is why punishment can be

effective; pain and act go together. "...to feel delight and pain rightly

or wrongly has no small effect on our actions." "...virtue then, is

concerned with pleasures and pains, and ....the acts from which [they

arise]" (NE II, 3. Ross, p. 33).

Virtue then, includes several psychological functions all of which serve

to guide us toward the goods we need for actualization. Virtue "...is

concerned with passions and actions, in which excess is a form of failure,

and so is defect, while the intermediate is praised and is a form of

success..." (NE II, 6. Ross p. 38).

Summarizing what we have said above, the concept of virtue includes the

following psychological functions:

KNOWING the appropriate thing to do and feel, both

theoretically and practically, by application of correct

principle to the current circumstance.

DESIRING/WANTING to act and feel appropriately.

CHOOSING the appropriate action and feeling.

SELF—CONTROL, or the inhibition of competing behaviors and

emotions.

ACTING and FEELING appropriately.

The present investigation was an attempt to examine this theoretical

structure of virtue and its relationship to well-being.

PROCEDURES

Subjects were 68 advanced undergraduate psychology students, 16 males, 48

females and 4 subjects who did not declare their gender. Their mean age

was 25.55 years. The disproportionate number of females was the result

of our psychology department's student population in which females are

strongly over represented. This is not particularly disconcerting to the

author since in this study, and in earlier investigations of the

problem, age and sex have not been important to the study of well-being

and its causes. (Costa, et. al., 1987; Franklin, LaMarca, & Barton 1991;

Page 6: An Examination of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-Being

Franklin and Torzynski, 1993).

The subjects were given three different packets of psychological scales

over the course of a semester. The scales were completed both in class

and out of class. The rate of return was 86%. Not all subjects

completed all scales or all items of each scale so the N's for different

variables and analyses vary slightly.

SCALES

REASON/THINKING

Three scales were used to measure virtuous thinking. Moral virtue or

practical thinking, was measured by the Decision Making Scale (DMS)

consisting of 12 items. The items identified 12 different domains of

life; family, education, friends, work, etc., and Ss rated their

'decision making ability' and 'the quality of the solutions they usually

find' for the day to day problems in each domain. A Likert type scale

was used where 1 was bad and 5 described excellent decision making.

This was the first time the DMS has been used and the correlation alpha of

.72 seems quite reasonable. Because the 12 items of the scale refer to

different life domains we might expect a less than perfect inter-item

correlation.

A second measure of moral virtue consisted of the four 'ways' items from

the Will And Ways Scale ( ). A similar

Likert type scale was used here to rate statements like "I can think of

many ways to get out of a jam" and "Even when others get discouraged, I

know I can find a way to solve the problem." The alpha obtained in the

present study was .69, not especially impressive, but since the scale had

only 4 items and since it correlated reasonably well (r = .55, p < .00)

with the DMS measure it was decided to combine the two to derive our

measure of moral virtue.

The third measure of reason was an attempt to tap the more generalized,

theoretical thinking that Aristotle called intellectual virtue. For this

purpose four subscales from the Constructive Thinking Inventory (Epstein

& Meier, 1989) were used. The subscales are designed to measure

categorical thinking, superstitious thinking, esoteric thinking, and naive

optimism. All these subscales are potential impediments and blocks to

good generalized thinking. A person high in 'categorical thinking',

('making... undifferentiated judgments'), for example, would be likely to

exhibit poor intellectual virtue because of a prevailing tendency to

overgeneralize. A person high in superstitious thinking, e.g.

one who agrees with the statement 'When something bad happens to

me, I feel that more bad things are likely to follow' would also

seem to reason poorly. Of the four intellectual virtue measures, only

two; the Superstitious Thinking and the Categorical Thinking scales were

shown to be statistically tied to the variables of the present study.

Page 7: An Examination of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-Being

Therefore, early in the data analyses a new measure consisting of the 8

item Superstitious Thinking scale and the 12 item Categorical Thinking

scale was created and used in all analyses involving intellectual virtue.

In the present study, the inter-item alpha's of the two measures were .80

and .74 for the superstitious and categorical thinking scales,

respectively. Since intellectual virtue was measured by scales designed

to tap the opposite of good generalized thinking, the label 'Contra-

Intellectual Virtue' is used throughout the paper to refer to performance

on this scale.

DESIRE AND CHOICE

Aristotle claims that the truly virtuous persons wants to feel and act

appropriately. Some like and enjoy doing the right thing while others do

not. The present study does not include the data on desire and choice but

leaves them for examination in later papers.

SELF-CONTROL

Several measures of self-control were employed. The Deferred Gratification

Scale (Ray and Najman, 1986), the NEO Impulsiveness subscale (Costa and

McRae, 1985), The Procrastination Scale (Tuckman, 1991), and two subscales

from Epstein and Meier's (1989) Constructive Thinking Inventory: The

Emotional Coping (CTIEC) and the Behavioral Coping (CTIBC) subscales.

These two subscales consisted in a combined total of 37 items all of which

refer to the subjects capacity to moderate his or her feelings and

actions. Sample guestions from the emotional coping subscale read as

follows: "The slightest indication of disapproval gets me upset" and "I

don't worry about things I can do nothing about." Sample behavioral coping

items are: "When I realize I have made a mistake, I usually take

immediate action to correct it" and " When I have a lot of work to do by a

deadline, I waste a lot of time worrying about it instead of just doing

it." All self-control measures correlated significantly with each other

but a hierarchical regression analysis to virtuous behavior (see below)

led us to restrict our attention to only the two coping scales from the

Constructive Thinking inventory. Their correlation alpha's reached

respectable levels; .89 and .85 for the Emotional Coping and Behavioral

Coping scales respectively.

VIRTUOUS BEHAVIOR

The present investigation did not measure virtuous behavior directly but

did examine the disposition to respond appropriately. The Self Appraisal

Scale (SAS) was constructed to assess ones ability to attain the right

amount, at the right time, and in the right way. From Urmson's list

(1988, p.34) of the ancient Greek virtues several of the most commonly

recognized (including temperance, courage, liberality, justice, and

pride) were selected and used to construct 48 True / False items regarding

the tendency to engage in virtuous behavior. For example, the first

item "I give too freely of myself" is intended to tap ones ability to give

Page 8: An Examination of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-Being

the right amount (liberality) of himself to others. Another item, "I

tend to seek the easy way out in most situations" concerns ones 'courage',

the ability to endure temporary discomfort for future gains. "I always

want to win" was used to measure the virtue Aristotle calls justice. The

SAS, designed as a measure of the disposition for virtuous behavior, has

been successfully used in previous investigations (Franklin, LaMarca &

Barton, 1992, Franklin & Torzynski, 1993). It's alpha in the present

investigation was .88.

NEED SATISFACTION

The Satisfaction Index (SI) was developed to assess the acquisition of

real goods. The scale consisted of the same 12 life domains appearing in

the Decision Making Scale (family, work, money, love, etc.) and subjects

rated each on a 1 (terrible) to 5 (Great) Likert scale regarding "...

the quality of each area of your life over the last few years?" It was

assumed that a qualitative judgment regarding a particular domain would

reflect the level of need satisfaction in that area. The domain items

were presented in a different order than they assumed on the DMS.

WELL-BEING

The recent literature on happiness and well-being seems to be in general

agreement regarding two fundamental components a good life: life

satisfaction and a favorable balance of positive and negative affect

(Diener, 1984). This modern view seems quite consistent with Aristotle's

notion of eudaimonia. Surely, he would agree that happy people, people

who fulfill their potentials, would find their lives both satisfying and

pleasurable. Thus, well-being, the major dependent variable in this

study, was operationalized in this way. Life satisfaction was measured

by the Satisfaction with Life Scale (Diener, Emmons, Larsen and Griffen

1983). Affect was assessed by the Affect Balance Scale (Bradburn, 1969).

Both measures are widely used by researchers in the area of happiness and

well- being and both have much to recommend them. In the present study

the alpha for the Satisfaction with Life Scale (SWLS) was .87. Separate

correlation alpha's for the positive and negative affect sub-scales of the

Affect Balance Scale (ABS) were .91 and .50, respectively.

Page 9: An Examination of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-Being

RESULTS

The purpose of this investigation was to empirically examine the

theoretical structure of Aristotle's concept of virtue and to further

assess his claim that virtue is essential to well-being. The scales used

are presented in Table 1, along with their means, standard deviations, and

alpha's. Table 2 presents a correlation matrix of the variables. It

may be noted from Table 2 that most of the scales, although structured

very differently and intended to measure very different psychological

processes, are quite highly correlated. While alternative explanations

for these correlations may be possible, (e.g. all measures may reflect

the same psychological construct), we believe the relationships shown in

Table 2 lend strong support to the eudaimonic theory.

The model presented in Figure I will serve as a guide for our discussion

of the results.

It should be noted at the outset that neither age nor sex was

significantly correlated with any of the measures used in the study.

VIRTUOUS THINKING AND MORAL ACTION

In the eudaimonic model the most important determinant of virtuous

behavior is good thinking. One can not do the appropriate thing unless he

or she knows what is appropriate. Such knowledge consists of two distinct

but related forms of reason. First, intellectual virtue requires that we

understand certain principles which can be used to guide our actions. For

example, to be just, we must understand the idea of fairness. But an

intellectual understanding is not enough. We must also know how to use

this knowledge. We must be able to select the right amount of fairness

for the situation at hand. We need both intellectual virtue and moral

virtue. From Table 2 it can be seen that while contra-intellectual and

moral virtue are significantly correlated (r = -.29, p = .03) the

correlation is not especially high. This finding is consistent with

Aristotle's dichotomous treatment of virtuous thinking.

Table 2 also reveals that both contra-intellectual and moral virtue are

significantly related to moral action. Poor general thinking, assessed

by the categorical and superstitious thinking subscales of the CTI,

correlated -.53 (p <.000) with SAS scores. Moral virtue, (combined DEC

and WAYS scales) correlated .52 (p < .000) with the SAS. Both forms of

virtuous thinking are strongly associated with virtuous action.

SELF CONTROL AND MORAL ACTION

While adequate knowledge is essential to moral action, it is not enough.

We must also be able to restrain some actions in favor of others.

Several measures of self-control were administered (CTIEC, CTIBC,

Procrastination, Deferred Gratification) but when regression analyses

revealed that the two scales from Epstein's CTI were actually inclusive of

Page 10: An Examination of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-Being

the others, our operational definition collapsed to the combined CTIEC

(emotional coping) and CTIBC (behavioral coping) scores which we labeled

Self-Control. Table 2 shows that Self-Control is strongly related to all

variables of the model but especially to SAS (virtuous action), r = .72 (p

< .000). Once again, Aristotle's model appears to be supported.

Restraint as well as reason is integral to moral action.

It is also interesting to note in Table 2 that virtuous thinking and self-

control are far from independent. The strong relationships between these

measures are quite consistent with the confusion in Aristotle's writings

over the importance of will (self-control) in eudaimonic theory, and

whether will can be explained entirely in terms of reason and thinking

(Dahl, 1984). This is not an issue, however that can be addressed in the

present paper.

VIRTUE AS A MEANS

Another confusion in Aristotle's writings concerns the issue of whether

virtue, that is, the interaction of reason, restraint, choice, desire, and

action, is a means to happiness, or is happiness itself. Aristotelian

scholars differ on the question but some suggest both views are correct.

The position taken in this paper is that virtuous thinking and self-

control permit virtuous action, which in turn enables the acquisition of

the goods we need for fulfillment. That is, virtue is a means. While not

explicitly proposed by Aristotle, we predicted that virtuous behavior

would be highly correlated with need satisfaction. Table 2 supports this

prediction. The correlation between the SAS (virtuous behavior) and the

SI (Satisfaction Index) is .47 (p <.O00). Those who act appropriately

appear to acquire the goods they need.

VIRTUE AND WELL-BEING

According to the model presented in Figure 1 getting the external and

psychological goods we need leads to happiness; to well-being. Although I

have some doubts whether Aristotle would limit his definition of happiness

to life satisfaction and a positive affect balance, I think he would

concur that they are important pieces of the good life. Table 2 again

demonstrates support for the eudaiemonic theory. Need satisfaction (SI)

is strongly correlated with both Life Satisfaction (r = .60, p < .000) and

with Affect Balance (r = .40, p = .001). It can be noted here,

incidentally, that support for the intrinsic value of virtue might also be

found in the substantial correlations between the two measures of well-

being (SWLS and ABS) and virtue (reason, restraint and moral action),

without regard to need satisfaction.

REGRESSION ANALYSES

A series of hierarchical regression analyses was used to further examine

the data. In the first analysis the SAS (virtuous action) scores served

as the dependent variable. The intellectual and moral virtue measures and

the self-control scores were the predictors. Moral virtue (as measured by

the combined DEC and WAYS) predictS 29% of the variance in the moral

Page 11: An Examination of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-Being

action scores, contra-intellectual virtue (CTICT + CTIST) accounted for

another 14%, and self-control (CTIEC & CTIBC subscales) explained an

additional 12 %. Altogether then, the three independent variables

comprising virtuous thinking and self-control explain 56% of the variance

in moral action. It appears from the Beta weights shown in Table 4 that

the three independent variables (contra-intellectual and moral virtue and

self-control) are relatively independent at this level in the model.

In the second step of the hierarchical regression analysis need

satisfaction (SI) served as the dependent variable while moral action

(SAS) was added to the predictors used in step 1. By this procedure the

contribution of all four variables to need satisfaction can be assessed.

The independence of the predictors is reflected in their Beta weights.

Taking Figure 1 and Table 4 together then, reveals that the four variables

above need satisfaction (SI) explain 59% of its variance. As might be

expected from the model, contra-intellectual and moral virtue still retain

some of their individual contributions to SI but moral action (SAS),

being strongly influenced by the predictors above it, looses its unique

predictive power.

The third and fourth steps of the hierarchical analysis regressed all

predictor variables of the Model to the constructs that define well-being;

Life Satisfaction and Affect Balance. From Table 4 we note that all

variables of the model explained 49% of life satisfaction, and 26% of the

affective dimension of well-being.

Table 4 also reveals that none of the Beta weights remain significant in

the final steps of the hierarchical analysis. This finding seems to make

good sense in the context of the model. Reason and restraint are the

basis of moral action, moral action enables the acquisition of the goods

we need, and the latter is the basis of well-being. All variables of

the model are interrelated. Thus, while it is clear that reason and

restraint are the basis for about half the variance in life satisfaction,

their effects are disbursed over the mediating variables of moral action

and need satisfaction, thus dissipating most of their individual

contribution.

Page 12: An Examination of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-Being

DISCUSSION

Virtue plays a cardinal role in Aristotle's theory of the good life.

Actualization requires that needs be met correctly; in the right amount,

at the right time, in the right way, and for the right reason. Virtue

enables us to 'hit the target.' One of the goals of this investigation

was to examine the theoretical structure of virtue. To this end, we

looked at the relationships between the two types of reason, self—

control, and moral action/feeling.

VIRTUE AND REASON

Intellectual virtue may be characterized as "understanding" or "reasoning

cogently and validly", or by the "grasp of what is most fundamental-first

principles", or by "the powers of the mind." (Adler, 1990, p.175 ff).

Moral virtue applies reasoning and understanding to the practical matters

of living. Moral virtue depends, in part, on intellectual virtue but

the two are by no means, uniformly aligned. For a variety of reasons,

theoretical knowledge may not be used or may be applied incorrectly.

The less than perfect union of the two kinds of reasoning seems to be

supported by the data. The correlation between our contra-intellectual

and moral virtue measures was only -.29 (p = .03). To do the right thing

requires that we understand certain principles and apply them correctly;

but variables, like desire, choice, self-control and the habits

developed over a life time also play a role in the practical world.

Theoretically then, the modest correlation between intellectual and moral

virtue seems consistent with eudaimonic theory. The failure of previous

investigations to find a connection between general or fluid

intelligence, (which cannot be too far removed from what Aristotle called

intellectual virtue) and well-being (Diener, 1984; Epstein & Meier, 1989,

Valiant, 1977) might be explained by the neglect of moral virtue and all

the variables which affect it. In eudaimonic theory, both are required.

VIRTUE AND SELF—CONTROL

There is controversy in the philosophical literature regarding the role

of will in Aristotle's ethics (Dahl, 1984). On the one hand he seems to

recognize the importance of restraint and self-control, and on the other

he suggests that restraint is ultimately explained by reason, or its

deficiencies. It can be argued that the person who fails to act rightly

does so because of ignorance not because of weakness. "No man chooses

evil because it is evil; he only mistakes it for happiness, the good he

seeks." (Mary Wollstonecraft). Dahl (1984) believes Aristotle does

provide a place for will or self-control and emphasizes Aristotle's

concept of Akrasia, or the 'weakness of will'.

The findings concerning the relationship between reason and self-control

appear to mirror the confusion in the philosophical literature. A

hierarchical regression analysis showed that contra-intellectual virtue

explained 31% of the variance in self-control and moral virtue accounted

for another 16%. Poorly managed behavior may well be caused by poor

thinking, both theoretical and practical. It is also possible that

Page 13: An Examination of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-Being

thinking and self-control are bi-directionally related. In any case, the

link between self-control and cognition is we11-documented. Lazarus

(1991) suggests that emotional and behavioral reactions are regulated by

our cognitive appraisal. There is still much to learn about the

relationship of self-control and virtuous thinking.

VIRTUE AND ACTION/FEEING

The coupling of action and feeling has a long tradition in psychology

(James, 1890; Klinger, 1977), but Aristotle antedates them all. Virtue

includes both, in concert; two aspects of the same thing. And, maybe

this is the essence of the good life. If we think, desire, control and

choose correctly we will act/feel correctly. And, maybe that's what

happiness is. "..happiness is activity of the soul in conformity with

virtue" - period! Our examination of the relationship between virtue

and well-being might stop here. Virtue culminates in virtuous

action/feeling. Virtue and happiness may be two aspects of the same

thing. There is much to be said for this position and Aristotle does

not hesitate to embrace it. The data also seem to support it. Reason and

self-control account for 56% of the variance in virtuous behavior (SAS)

and virtuous behavior is strongly correlated with well-being. Table 2

clearly shows that the correlations of contra-intellectual virtue, moral

virtue and virtuous behavior with the two well-being measures are all

highly significant. Virtue alone may bring happiness.

However, Aristotle takes the other side too. We also need goods. "It is

impossible to do fine acts without a supply of 'goods' "...happiness does

seem to requires this external bounty." (NE I, 8. Brambough, p. 296).

Aristotle seems comfortable with both sides: virtue is an end, and virtue

is a means.

Virtuous action/feeling is a means to the goods we need for growth; for

fulfillment and actualization. Table 2 indicates a significant

relationship between our SAS measure of virtuous action and the SI

measure of need satisfaction (r = .47, p < .00). Figure 1 tells us

that almost 60% of the variance in need satisfaction comes from virtue.

As the eudaimonic theory claims, virtue pays off, both intrinsically, and

by moving us toward the perfection that Aristotle believed was in the

reach of everyone. (NE I, 9, Brambrough, p.296)

Figure 1 reveals that virtue, by its intrinsic value, and by the goods it

delivers, predicts about 50 percent of the variance in life satisfaction

and about 25 percent of our affect. Good thinking and self-control

appear to be much more important to our lives than most of the extrinsic

goods we usually dream about. Fortune, youth, education, occupation, and

the like, the things we usually equate with the good life, are far less

important to our well-being. (Andrews and Withey, 1974; Campbell,

1976; Myers, 1992). Virtue is an old idea, but it's still a good one.

Page 14: An Examination of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-Being

REFERENCES

Adler, M.J. (1980) Aristotle for everybody. New York: Bantam.

Andrews, F. M., & Witney, S. B. (1976). Social indicators ofwell-being: Americans perception of life quality. New York: Plenum Press.

Bambrough, R. (Ed.) (1963). The philosophy of Aristotle (trans. A.E. Wardman & J.L. Creed). New York American Library/Mentor.

Bradburn, N.M. (1969). The structure of psychological well-being. Chicago: Aldine.

Campbell, A. (1976). Subjective measures of well-being. American Psychologist, 31, 117-124.

Costa, P.T. Jr., & McCrae, R. R. (1980). Influence ofextraversion and neuroticism on subjective well-being: happy and unhappy people. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 38 f 668 -678.

Costa. P. T. Jr., & McCrae, R. R. (1985). The NEO personality inventory manual. Odessa, Fl: Psycholgical Assessment Resources, Inc.

Costa, P.T., Jr., Zonderman, A.B., McCrae, R.R., Cornoni-Huntley, J., Locke, B.Z., & Barbano, H.E. (1987) Longitudinal analyses of psychological well-being in a national sample: Stability of mean levels. Journal of Gerontology, 42, 50-55.

Dahl, N.O. (1984). Practical reason, Aristotle, and weakness of the will. Minneapollis: Univ. Minnesota Press.

Diener, E. (1984). Subjective will-being. Psychological Bulletin, 95, 542-575.

Diener, E., Emmons, R., Larsen, R. & Griffin, S. (1985). The satisfaction with life scale. Journal of Personality Assessment, 49, 71-75.

Epstein, S., & Meier, P. (1989). Constructive thinking: a broad coping variable with specific componesnts. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 57, 332-350.

Franklin, S. LaMarca P., & Barton, L. (1991). An examination ofAristotle's eudaimonic theory of happiness. Paper presented at the Western PsychologicalAssociation, April 1991, San Francisco.

Franklin, S. & Torzynski, R. (1993). Virtue and well-being: evidence for Aristotle's eudaimonic theory of happiness. Paper presented at the Western Psychological Association, April 1993, Phoenix, AZ.

James, William (1969). Psychology: Briefer course. London:Col1i er-Macmi1i an.

Klinger, E. Meaning and void: inner experience and the incentives in peeople's lives. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

Lazarus, R.S. (1991). Emotion & adaptation. New York. Oxford University Press.

Maclntyre, A. (1981). After virtue: a study in moral theory. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

Meyers, D-G. (1992). The pursuit of happiness. New York: Avon.

Ray, J. L.,& Najman, J. M. (1986). The generalizability of deferment of gratification. The Journal of Social Psychology, 126, 117-119.

Ross, D. (1986). Aristotle: The nicomachean ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Ryff, C . (1989). Happiness is everything, or is it?Exploration of the meaning of psychological well-being.

Jouranal of Personality and Social Psychology, 57, 1069 - 1081.

Tuckman, B. W. (1991). The development and concurrent validityof the procrastination scale. Educational and Psychological Measurement, 51, 473-480.

Urmson, J.O. (1988) Aristotle's ethics. Great Britain: Basil Blackwell.

Vaillant, G. E. (1977). Adaptation to life. Boston: Little, Brown.

Page 15: An Examination of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-Being
Page 16: An Examination of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-Being
Page 17: An Examination of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-Being
Page 18: An Examination of Aristotle's Concept of Virtue and its Relationship to Well-Being