Top Banner
ebating at the WUDC Berlin 2013 1. Introduction 2. Technical Rules 3. Role Fulfilment 4. Defining the Debate 5. Status Quo and Opposition 6. Extension Speeches 7. Summary Speeches 8. Points of Information
26

Adjudication camp brief

Apr 12, 2017

Download

Fardeen Ameen
Welcome message from author
This document is posted to help you gain knowledge. Please leave a comment to let me know what you think about it! Share it to your friends and learn new things together.
Transcript
Page 1: Adjudication camp brief

Debating at the WUDC Berlin 2013

1. Introduction2. Technical Rules3. Role Fulfilment4. Defining the Debate5. Status Quo and Opposition6. Extension Speeches7. Summary Speeches8. Points of Information

Page 2: Adjudication camp brief

Debating at the WUDC Berlin 2013

Judges assess which team did the best job at persuading them that the motion ought to be affirmed or rejected. They do this as the 'ordinary intelligent voter' and consider the strength of the arguments that each team presents.

Page 3: Adjudication camp brief

Role Fulfillment

Role fulfilment, then, is the context in which that persuasion must take place, the boundaries that allow each team a fair chance to persuade the judges

Page 4: Adjudication camp brief

Role Fulfillment

(1) In first proposition, to define the debate (explained in Section IV).(2) For the extension speakers, to extend the debate (explained in Section V).(3) For all teams, to ensure that their arguments are consistent with all other argumentsmade by themselves, their teammates, and the other team on their sideof the debate (contradiction is often referred to as 'knifing').(4) For opposition summary speakers, not to add new arguments (explained in SectionVII).(5) For all speakers, to take at least one point of information during their speechesand to offer points of information on a regular basis (explained in Section VIII).(6) To demonstrate proper courtesy to fellow speakers, judges, and tournament officialsat all times.(7) To speak within the time frame allotted.

Page 5: Adjudication camp brief

Role Fulfillment

The general rule for violations of role fulfilment is that speakers are to lose any advantage that violating their role might have given them and to be penalised to the extent to which their role fulfilment created difficulties in the wider debate. Some worked examples:

Violation of Role Fulfilment Suggested Penalty Adding new arguments in the Opposition summary speech.

The speaker receives no credit for any new arguments.

Any time spent making new arguments is deemed to be time wasted. Failure to take a point of information (where points of information have been consistently offered). The speaker's material is assessed as though a damaging point of information had been asked and responded to poorly. Contradicting one's own self/team/side. Contradictory material is simply ruled out as inadmissible.

Time spent making contradictory arguments is to be judged as time wasted. Speaking for longer than seven minutes.

The speaker receives no credit for material brought after seven minutes. N.B. This does NOT mean that a violation of role fulfilment results in a team taking a last. It is perfectly possible for a team to take first place de

Page 6: Adjudication camp brief

Definition

The first government speaker (a.k.a. the Prime Minister) defines the debate. This means they tell the rest of the people in the room exactly what will be debated. They need to say whether there is a policy (i.e. whether someone is doing something) and what that policy is, if it exists. Remember, debates are about the motion as defined by the opening government. It is not about what you thought the words in the motion meant.

In some cases, merely stating the motion can constitute sufficiently 'defining the debate' as that sentence may be enough to do all of the above. On the other hand, the definition might involve a many-pointed model or some extensive caveating/parameter setting. It may be that the same motion could be usefully defined in either of these ways, producing 4/9 different legitimate debates. In other words, OG needs to do enough to explain what the person, organisation, group of people etc. is doing.

Page 7: Adjudication camp brief

Definition

It is not the job of the judge to attack the definition. Only worry about the definition if teams in the debate do. If the definition is successfully attacked as being insufficiently explanatory, the OG team should be penalised only to the extent to which a lack of detail prevents teams from making arguments. Judges should give other teams the benefit of the doubt relative to OG where such a deficiency poses a problem and allow other teams to 'read-in' any fair and reasonable assumption about the definition that the first proposition team hasn't fully spelled out.

Page 8: Adjudication camp brief

Definition

Worked Example: THW: Allow Prisoners to Vote Example 1:

PM: 'We define this motion as allowing prisoners the right to take part in elections.'

LO: 'The Prime Minister has failed to confine this motion to adults in prison. Thus we must assume that children who are imprisoned will be allowed to vote, which is wrong as children are unfit to vote.'

DPM: 'That's clearly silly. Obviously child prisoners won't be allowed to vote.' The Judge Should Conclude. The DPM is correct.

The assumption made by the LO is unreasonable and must be rejected. The team in first opposition may be penalised for making a frivolous challenge. They certainly receive no credit for their challenge.

Page 9: Adjudication camp brief

Definition

Worked Example: THW: Allow Prisoners to Vote Example 2:

Example 2:

PM: 'We define this motion as allowing prisoners the right to take part in elections.'

LO: 'The Prime Minister has failed to tell us which sorts of prisoners are allowed to vote. This definition is illegitimate because it doesn't tell us which- and that might include murderers.'

DPM: 'That's silly! Of course our model doesn't extend to murderers and the like, that would be completely unreasonable!'

The Judge Should Conclude. Neither the DPM nor the LO are correct. There was nothing wrong with the Prime Minister's definition, it merely left the opportunity for the Opposition teams to make arguments about why allowing murderers to vote would be a bad idea.

Page 10: Adjudication camp brief

Status Quo & Opposition

So, government decides what they want to do or say is true. What about opposition? In a debate about a policy, the opposition must say that we shouldn't do it; that is, that something is better than doing this policy.

This can be the status quo in some countries, or it can be something which is currently done nowhere, it may be described as 'doing nothing' rather than 'doing the policy' (though naturally, teams doing this don't necessarily recommend wholesale government inaction, but are running the comparative 'whatever other broadly sensible relevant policies one is carrying out, the addition of this one makes things worse').

So long as opp provide reasons not to do the policy, this is fine.

There are many ways for someone to disagree with a policy, and -- as long as they actually constitute disagreements – you should be willing to accept them. Keep in mind that at an international tournament like this, there is no dometics policy status quo of significance.

Page 11: Adjudication camp brief

Extension SpeechesThe third speaker on each side of the debate (the first speaker on each of the secondproposition and the second opposition teams) is responsible for contributing an extensionto the debate.An extension is defined as anything that hasn't yet been said by that side of the debate. Anextension can take a number of forms including:(1) New arguments which have not yet been made in the debate.(2) New rebuttals.(3) New examples.(4) New analysis or explanation of existing arguments.(5) New applications of existing argumentation (e.g. if the extension speaker pointsout that that one of the first-half's arguments is able to defeat a new argumentfrom the other side).In short, saying ANYTHING other than a word-for-word repetition of first-half's materialwill- in some sense- constitute an extension. In that sense, role fulfilment here is fairly easyand most extension speakers will succeed in fulfilling their role.been made.As a result, extension speakers do not defeat the first team on their side of their debatemerely by 'having an extension' (any more than first proposition teams win the debate for'having a definition'). A winning extension will bring out material that is most able toperuade the judge that the motion should be affirmed or rejected.

Page 12: Adjudication camp brief

Summary Speeches

Summary speeches should summarise the debate from the perspective of their side. A good summary speech will note the major disagreements in the debate (points of clash) between the two sides and will make use of the best arguments from each team on their side to make their case that the motion ought to be affirmed or rejected.

A summary speaker which makes effective use of arguments that were introdued in the first half should receive credit for doing so, if those arguments are employed successfully. A summary speaker which ignores or minimises arguments made by the first-half is not effectively fulfilling their role as a summary speaker.

Debating is unfair if teams can make new arguments in the last speech (opposition summation), to which no one can respond. So they aren't allowed to do that. Proposition summation speakers are permitted to make new arguments, but should receive diminished credit for new arguments they raise, as these should really have been in the extension.

Page 13: Adjudication camp brief

Summary Speeches

What do we mean by a 'new argument'? Debates are about doing things, or arguing that things are true.

Therefore, we mean new reasons to do things, claims that new things will happen, or claims that new moral truths are the case. We do not mean: • New defences of arguments already made. • New explanations of previously-made arguments. • Rebuttal • New examples to support existing arguments • Anything the other side can reasonably be expected to understand that team intends from the 3rd speech. At times, it's often difficult to assess the difference between new rebuttals and analysis (which are permitted) and new arguments (which are not). The good judge will consider whether or not the making of the claim raises a new issue, to which the other side has no ability to respond.

Page 14: Adjudication camp brief

Adjudication

1. Deciding who wins2. Decision-Making Process

3. Deliberation4. Announcing the Result

5. Feedback on Adjudicators6. Some Pitfalls to Avoid in Decision-Making and Feedback

Page 15: Adjudication camp brief

Assessing Argumentation

The outcome of the debate should obviously depend on what the teams do and don't say. Judges must not intervene in the debate. Don't invent arguments for teams, don't complete arguments and don't rebut arguments.

Judges often speak about a speaker "getting at a good point” even if "(s)he didn't quite get there”. This is just an excuse for a judge to invent an argument (s)he'd like to hear. Don't do it.

As we don't do teams' rebuttal for them, we don't consider claims invalid just because we disagree, or because we can see holes in their arguments. Arguments stand as 'true' once they are made until they are responded to.

This has an important implication: if OG, for instance, make arguments whose conclusion is 'we should do the policy' which everyone ignores, then they don't lose because 'the debate moved on from them'. Rather, their unrebutted arguments are still true and should be weighed as such. In fact, teams like this very often should beat the teams on the opposite bench. There is one legitimate exception to this – if an argument is clearly absurd (such that you cannot conceive of anyone we would consider sane believing its logic and/or premises) and it was very marginal to the speech of the speaker making the claim, then it is reasonable for a team to decide to spend their time elsewhere, particularly where there is other stronger material in the round.

Page 16: Adjudication camp brief

Assessing Argumentation

What is and is not rebutted is therefore of vital importance to judging debates. Note that speakers don't have to use the word "rebuttal” to respond to an argument. It is tidier if they do, but judges should not ignore material that adequately deals with an argument just because the speaker doesn't point out that it does.

Equally, this doesn't mean speakers should be 'punished' for not refuting everything: some claims do not do any harm at all to the opposite side. For example, in a debate about the legalisation of drugs, if the government say 'pink elephants are cute because they have those nice ears and are a pleasant colour', this flawed argument can be safely allowed to stand as it isn't a reason to legalise drugs. There is, therefore, no need to point out that blue elephants are obviously more tasteful. So too, if they said 'some drugs are less harmful than others', this could also be ignored. While it is clearly more related to the debate than the cute pink elephants argument, it is pre-argumentative – that is, it has not got sufficient surrounding words to be a reason to do or not do the policy. Opp can quite happily say 'yes, some drugs are more harmful than others' and move on. Or just ignore this argumentative non-sequitur. Often as a judge, it can be tempting to complete arguments for teams that are interesting but pre-argumentative. Don't.

Page 17: Adjudication camp brief

Assessing Argumentation

Certain things don't matter (in themselves) in debating:• The number of arguments a team makes,• How clever or sophisticated the argument was,• How interesting the argument was

Page 18: Adjudication camp brief

Assessing Argumentation

What matters, once an argument is made, is how important its conclusion seems to be in the debate, based on what people have said in this debate, and the extent to which it seems to be responded to (and how robust it is under such attacks).

We've now come full circle. The team who seems to win the logical argument wins the debate. This must be assessed solely through material provided in the debate. Don't penalise teams for failing to make arguments. Don't consider arguments that you're aware of but which weren't made.

Page 19: Adjudication camp brief

Mechanisms for persuasion

Examples of such mechanisms are: • Good analysis • Good rebuttal • Good style • Good strategic decisions • Using examples

One thing which is certainly unpersuasive is inconsistency. Teams should not contradict themselves or their bench partners. Internally inconsistent teams cannot simultaneously get credit for two areas of mutually exclusive argument. We're forced to credit them for the least effective of the two.

Page 20: Adjudication camp brief

The Ordinary Intelligent Voter

There is obviously a need for judges to abstract themselves from their personal positions when in debates. If we simply judged as ourselves then the result would depend strongly on what we know, how we think and what opinions we hold. We would be making personal judgments about how compelling we find particular arguments. This would give teams who know us a great advantage, and would make the results more about us than them. Therefore, we attempt to judge as an abstract 'ordinary intelligent voter', and minimise the impact that our knowledge and opinions have on the result. This is a difficult process, and something that bears thinking about

However, thinking as the ‘ordinary intelligent voter’ does not absolve us from our responsibility to rationally judge the debate- that is to evaluate the logical flow of arguments and determine the extent to which teams have seemed to win them.

There is another important feature of how the ordinary intelligent voter judges, as distinct from how we do. Many of us debate a lot, and we develop aesthetic preferences about speaking as well as in-jokes and references which we find terribly funny. This is completely natural, but distracts somewhat from debating. As voters we are much less likely to credit policies for being advocated in a 'sophisticated' or 'funny' way; these things might lead us to believe them better, but we would not say we voted for someone because she was funny, but because she'd make our life better.

Page 21: Adjudication camp brief

The Ordinary Intelligent Voter

The ordinary intelligent voter:• Attempts to evaluate logically what the best thing to do is, • Using as inputs the arguments made by the teams, • Persuaded by a variety of tools which are not strictly logical, such as, • Style, neatness, clarity, etc. and their inverses. Critically, the ordinary intelligent voter is actually open to persuasion, as some

actively try to avoid being!

Page 22: Adjudication camp brief

The Ordinary Intelligent Voter

• Many of us have a vast knowledge in varying fields. However, Our ordinary intelligent voter does not come from where you do; there are no 'domestic examples' requiring less explanation, even where everyone in the room comes from that country. Wherever you are from, assume your audience is from somewhere else.

• Following on from the above, the ordinary intelligent person does not know technical terms that one would require a particular university degree to understand. She can be assumed to possess the sort of generalist vocabulary that comes from a university education of some sort, but probably not yours. He does not have the sort of half way there economic or legal jargon that we as debaters have become familiar with either. Saying 'Laffer curve' to most people is equivalent to making some clever-sounding noises. Similarly, using terms like 'economic efficiency' will lead to their being understood only as a layperson would grasp them, losing any technical specificity. Judges should judge accordingly

Page 23: Adjudication camp brief

What counts as new material

Anything teams say that has not already been said in the same way is a new contribution and worthy of credit (or, if it is harmful, debit). This means they get credit for everything beneficial they do: arguments, rebuttals, framing, examples, etc. Their contribution is valuable insofar as what they say benefits their side more than what has already been said.

So, a whole new argument that is entirely theirs is valuable to the extent that argument helps their side; an improvement on an existing argument is valuable insofar as their addition to the argument helps their side; rebuttal is valuable insofar as defeating that specific material helps their side.

All this is determined by the current state-of-play. One conclusion of this is that it is not enough for a closing team to make an argument somewhat better than their opening: they gain credit only for the improvement on the previous argument. They must make improvements and additions to the opening case that outweighs the totality of that case.

Page 24: Adjudication camp brief

Comparing Contributions

Where teams have a chance to rebut each other, assessing relative contribution is easy. Judges should track the argument and assess, given their responses to each other, which team's contribution was more significant in furthering their cause to logically persuade us that we should do the policy, or that we should not.

Where teams don't get a chance to rebut others, this is trickier. This happens fairly often: • Teams on diagonals • O4 explains something in a new way • Opening teams shut out of POIs

In these circumstances judges are forced to perform some more independent assessment of the 'robustness' of the arguments teams made. The question to ask is 'how robust to 6/10 potential rebuttals was a team's contribution?' More 'robust' material is a greater contribution than less 'robust' material. Ideally, assessing robustness will involve a comparison with material on the table, or very minor extensions thereof. For instance, when comparing with a team diagonally in front, judges should first ask whether anything in that team's case is relevant or (ideally) rebuttive. Did the team being assessed deal with this material? Check whether they allowed the diagonal team in on POIs, to give them an opportunity to engage. Deliberately shutting out engagement from a team whose material is relevant is often obvious and deeply unpersuasive.

Page 25: Adjudication camp brief

Pitfalls To Avoid

A) Dealing in generalities rather than specifics''We thought that second opposition really brought the case home for us, so they won thedebate.''''First proposition talked about rights, but I really didn't find it persuasive.''''First opposition had some interesting things to say, but the analysis didn't get better untilsecond opposition.''It's perfectly fine for adjudicators to use general language to introduce their reasons,provided that each general statement is supported by examples of what actually happened.No statement of the sorts that we've listed above should ever go unsupported byspecific examples of the claim being made, either during the deliberation or duringfeedback.

B) Failing to judge the debate as it happened.''Proposition never talked about rights in this debate.''''It took until the summation speaker until we heard anything about rights.''''I really wouldn't have propped it like that.''Judges may have their own opinion as to what the best arguments for each side in thedebate will be, but these are not the criteria on which the debate is to be judged. Judgesmay advise teams that there were interesting avenues of analysis left unexplored, but theymay not penalise teams for their approach to the motion, or the things that each teamdecided to emphasize.to find as many reasons as possible to exclude consideration

Page 26: Adjudication camp brief

Pitfalls To Avoid

C) Granting certain ''classes'' of arguments undue priority"Second opposition were the only team who told us about the importance of principles.""Only first proposition knew the names of major Brazilian cities."10/10"Second prop won because their arguments were moral rather than practical.""You didn't name any actual footballers in your speech."This judging pitfall takes a number of forms. One of which is the fetishisation of the use ofspecific knowledge in the making of arguments. Teams which make strong argumentsbuttressed by good knowledge should be rewarded, but not because of the total amountof facts they named, but because of the strength of the arguments which those facts weremarshalled in support of. A clever use facts makes an argument stronger and better, itdoes not make an argument.A second form of this pitfall is according improper priority to arguments that are ofvarious types (moral/philosophical/economic/practical). A 'principled' argument, forexample, is not necessarily better or worse than a practical one. It depends what eachargument seeks to prove and how well it does so.

D) 'Penalty judging' & “Judging on Format”A good referee is not one who incessantly blows their whistle and stops play. Similarly, a good judge isn't one who tries to find as many reasons as possible to exclude consideration of a team's arguments and speak instead about the form- rather than the content- of their contribution. If a team violates the duties of role fulfilment, they should be penalised only up to the point of removing any harm they caused to the debate through failure to fulfil their role.