Top Banner
A sharp way of thinking, a productive way of living. When Foucault meets Wittgenstein Paolo B. Vernaglione In the present time an archaeological reconstruction of the subjectivity as a set of relations between powers, knowledge and subjects based on language's faculty, is on the agenda. But every set of different forms of power and knowledge, accomplishes a mobile subjectivity, fragmented and definitly not identitarian. According to Wittgenstein, a private language doesn’t exist, just as Foucault assert that individual identity from which it’s possible to infer our own subjectivity doesn’t exist, as he remarked in The Archaeology of Knowledge and in The Discourse on Language, as in L’ ordre du discours with respect to the literary authors. As of an analysis of language is occupied with studying and clarifying grammar rules in the language that we speach daily, it is precisely this function that Foucault recognizes in Wittgenstein's thought. In fact, with the enquiry of daily speech we discover not only the rules of language but also the way in which those rules are practiced when we speach, write and communicate as effects of expression; so in this way, they are a process of subjectivation. This essential recomendation brings the Wittgenstein’s conception near Foucault’s perspective of subjectivity, wich he elaborated over the mid Seventies of Twentieh Century, that is no more linked to the individual identity, but, as on Nietzsche, to certain discoursive regimes, produced in the relationship beetwen differents areas of knowledge and of power. So the public faculty of language, that is valorized in this postfordist era, after decline of industrial capitalism and the rise of “net society” and the financial power, now shows its structure in which history (as individual, contingent daily praxis) and meta history (as a set of conditions of life and of agency) are strictly intertwined. So the relevance of subjectivation as an activity of human beings leaves the general processes of “secolarization” and the generic issue of total dominance of the state over the individuals in the background, and marks the role of individuality as a voluntary assumption of values, as a form of subordination to the state power, but in the meantime as a “counterbehavior”, there is a possibility of resistence, and also a possibility to build spaces of freedom. At the cross point of the processes of subjectivation and of an ontology of the self we find a miracoulous meeting: Foucault looks at Wittgenstein, as a philosopher of the rules of the language, because he pays attention to the forms in which language is used. In fact, the position of Wittgenstein on the logic of language is different from others such Russell or Frege, who think of language in terms of applications of formal logic. From this point the language testifys to the way
23

A sharp way of thinking, a productive way of living. When Foucault meets Wittgenstein

Jan 27, 2023

Download

Documents

Welcome message from author
This document is posted to help you gain knowledge. Please leave a comment to let me know what you think about it! Share it to your friends and learn new things together.
Transcript
Page 1: A sharp way of thinking, a productive way of living. When Foucault meets Wittgenstein

A  sharp  way  of  thinking,  a  productive  way  of  living.    

When  Foucault  meets  Wittgenstein  

 

Paolo  B.  Vernaglione  

 

In  the  present  time  an  archaeological  reconstruction  of  the  subjectivity  as  a  set  of  relations  between  powers,  

knowledge   and   subjects   based   on   language's   faculty,   is   on   the   agenda.   But   every   set   of   different   forms   of  

power   and   knowledge,   accomplishes   a   mobile   subjectivity,   fragmented   and   definitly   not   identitarian.  

According   to  Wittgenstein,  a  private   language  doesn’t  exist,   just  as  Foucault  assert   that   individual   identity  

from  which   it’s   possible   to   infer   our   own   subjectivity   doesn’t   exist,   as   he   remarked   in  The   Archaeology   of  

Knowledge   and   in   The   Discourse   on   Language,   as   in   L’   ordre   du   discours   with   respect   to   the   literary  

authors.  

As  of  an  analysis  of  language  is  occupied  with  studying  and  clarifying  grammar  rules  in  the  language  that  we  

speach  daily,  it  is  precisely  this  function  that  Foucault  recognizes  in  Wittgenstein's  thought.  In  fact,  with  the  

enquiry  of  daily  speech  we  discover  not  only  the  rules  of  language  but  also  the  way  in  which  those  rules  are  

practiced  when  we  speach,  write  and  communicate  as  effects  of  expression;  so  in  this  way,  they  are  a  process  

of   subjectivation.   This   essential   recomendation   brings   the   Wittgenstein’s   conception   near   Foucault’s  

perspective  of  subjectivity,  wich  he  elaborated  over  the  mid  Seventies  of  Twentieh  Century,   that   is  no  more  

linked   to   the   individual   identity,   but,   as   on   Nietzsche,   to   certain   discoursive   regimes,   produced   in   the  

relationship  beetwen  differents  areas  of  knowledge  and  of  power.  So  the  public   faculty  of   language,   that   is  

valorized  in  this  post-­‐fordist  era,  after  decline  of     industrial  capitalism  and  the  rise  of  “net  society”  and  the  

financial  power,  now  shows  its  structure  in  which  history  (as  individual,  contingent  daily  praxis)  and  meta-­‐

history  (as  a  set  of  conditions  of  life  and  of  agency)  are  strictly  intertwined.  So  the  relevance  of  subjectivation  

as  an  activity  of  human  beings  leaves  the  general  processes  of  “secolarization”  and  the  generic  issue  of  total  

dominance   of   the   state   over   the   individuals   in   the   background,   and   marks   the   role   of   individuality   as   a  

voluntary   assumption   of   values,   as   a   form   of   subordination   to   the   state   power,   but   in   the  meantime   as   a  

“counter-­‐behavior”,  there  is  a  possibility  of  resistence,  and  also  a  possibility  to  build  spaces  of  freedom.  

 

At   the   cross   point   of   the   processes   of   subjectivation   and   of   an   ontology   of   the   self   we   find   a  

miracoulous   meeting:   Foucault   looks   at   Wittgenstein,   as   a   philosopher   of   the   rules   of   the  

language,  because  he  pays  attention  to  the  forms  in  which  language  is  used.  In  fact,  the  position  of  

Wittgenstein  on  the  logic  of  language  is  different  from  others  such  Russell  or  Frege,  who  think  of    

language  in  terms  of  applications  of  formal  logic.  From  this  point  the  language  testifys  to  the  way  

Page 2: A sharp way of thinking, a productive way of living. When Foucault meets Wittgenstein

in  which  we  live,  therefore  it  is  an  index  of  an  ethic,  considered  as  an  effect  of  our  existence,  not  

as  a  prescriptive  form  of  agency.  

But  not  only.  

As   of   an   analysis   of   language   is   occupied   with   studying   and   clarifying   grammar   rules   in   the    

language   that   we   speach   daily,   it   is   precisely   this   function   that   Foucault   recognizes   in    

Wittgenstein's  thought.  In  fact,  with  the  enquiry  of  daily  speech  we  discover  not  only  the  rules  of  

language   but   also   the   way   in   which   those   rules   are   practiced   when   we   speach,   write   and  

communicate  as  effects  of  expression;  so  in  this  way,  they  are  a  process  of  subjectivation.  

If   we  mark   this   consideration   of   the   language   as   the  most   extended   important   human   faculty  

among  others,   the  explanation   is   in   the   first   lines  of  Wittgenstein’s  Philosophical  Investigations.  

Here  the  obstensive  way  to  consider  the  language  of  Augustin,  is  revoked.  In  fact,  the  denotative  

function   of   language   in  which   the   noun   is   the   indication   of   a   named   object,  when  we   need   to  

indicate   something   or   someone,   seems   to   be   the   primary   function  with   respect   to   a   simmetry  

between   words   and   things,   ordinary   used   for   certain   education   of   the   language,   for   instance  

between  a  child  and  his  mother.  This  funcion,  as  Wittgenstein  shows  us  with  the  example  of  the  

commands  given  to  the  workers  in  a  construction  yard,  isn’t  the  same  as  the  obstensive  one.    

We   can   suppose   ‘a   primitive   language’   formed   only   by   adverbs   and   adjectives:   For   example:    

“(put)  this  (sheet),  here!”.  In  this  case  we  simply  use  another  linguistic  game  that  derives  from  a  

specific  situation.  This  use  of  language  demonstrates  that  the  denotative  function  isn’t  the  most  

relevant  and  that  the  reference  to  words  and  facts  is  arbitrary  and  isn’t  simmetrical  at  all.  

This  essential  recomendation  brings  the  Wittgenstein’s  conception  near  Foucault’s  perspective  of  

subjectivity,    wich   he   elaborated   over   the  mid   Seventies   of   Twentieh  Century,   that   is   no  more  

linked  to  the  individual  identity,  but,  as  on  Nietzsche,  to  certain  discoursive  regimes,  produced  in  

the  relationship  beetwen  differents  areas  of  knowledge  and  of  power.  

In   this   way   of   thinking   we   have   a   common   field   of   research,   as   the   French   Congress   on  

Wittgenstein   and   Foucault   highlighted   in   2007,   and   how   reaffirmed   during   the   Convention  

“Wittgenstein/Foucault”  at  the  Sorbona  University,  in  last  June.  

In  fact  the  singular  thing  that  today  we  don't  cease  to  remark  upon,  is  this  common  field  in  which  

the  analytical  perspective  on  language  and  the  archeological  method  of  inquiring  are  interlaced.  

This  fact,  that  Foucault  noticed  in  1978  at  the  Tokio  Conferences,  cancels  much  of  the  polemics  

between   the   improperly  named   "continental   philosophy"   and   the   analytical   one;   polemics   that  

Page 3: A sharp way of thinking, a productive way of living. When Foucault meets Wittgenstein

have   been   generated   via   postmodernism   from   Chomsky’s   generative   theory   of   language   that  

contrast  the  logic  of  the  analysis  of  language  with  an  onthology  of  historical  languages,  based  on  

the  Heidegger’s  foundation  of  Being.  

Considering  this  history  of  conflicts,  in  which  we  put  the  contrast  between  phenomenology  and  

analytical  thought,  developped  in  an  angloamerican  context  and  which  will  be  used  in  genetic  and  

biological  applications,  the  position  of  Foucault  in  favour  of  the  analytical  philosophy,  conceived  

for  knowing  different  forms  of  power,  mark  this  new  ground  and  outline  it’s  limitations;  it  builds  

boundaries   that   separate   the   space   of   discoursive   subjectivity   from   other   human   institutions  

(state,  religion,  nation),  other  systems  of  constraint  (family,  church,  hospital,  school),  and  other  

regimes  of  knowledge  (science,  history,  literature,  arts).  

According  to  Wittgenstein,  a  private  language  doesn’t  exist,  just  as  Foucault  assert  that  individual  

identity   from  which   it’s  possible   to   infer  our  own  subjectivity  doesn’t   exist,   as  he   remarked   in    

The  Archaeology  of  Knowledge  and  in  The  Discourse  on  Language,  as   in  L’  ordre  du  discours  with  

respect  to  the  literary  authors.  

But  every   set  of  different   forms  of  power  and  knoweledge,   accomplishes  a  mobile   subjectivity,  

fragmented  and  definitly  not  identitarian.  

In   this   case   the   cartesian   subject   of   the   Cogito   is   achieved   by   the   history   of     thought,   and   it  

became   an   archeological   profile   of   the  western  way   of   life   (the   capitalistic   one   in   the   last   two  

Centuries),  which   is   the  prerequisite   understanding   for   the   correspondence   of   the   subject   and    

individuality.  This  identity,  as  Marx  has  written,  is  based  on  the  false  conception  of  the  political  

economy   that   tells   about  an   isolated  human  being  as  owner,   so   that   the   common  mental  habit    

that  is  hidden  in  the  personal  identity  of  the  men  in  the  free  market.  

This   means,   on   the   one   hand   the   subject   is   subordinated   to   the   powers,   in   every   form   they  

present   themselves  and   they  have  effects  on   the  public   sphere;  but,  on  other  hand,   this  means  

that   the  subjects,  because  they  are   free,  have  the  possibility   to  resist   the  dispositives  of  power,  

building   their  proper   form  of   life,  practicing   the  care  of   the  self  and  trying   to  define  himself  as  

responsible  for  the  self.  We  know  that  the  powers,  in  the  form  of  the  national  state  or  today  the  

E.U.,   or   the   transnational   economic   institutions,     such   as   BCE,   or   FMI,   or   simple  aggregates   of  

nations,  such  as  the  French-­‐Dutch  axes  in  economic  government  of  Europe,  exercises  their  power  

in  the  form  of  governmentality.    

But  we  are  aware  that  this  configuration  of  powers,  plus  the  multiple  systems  of  knowledges  that  

Page 4: A sharp way of thinking, a productive way of living. When Foucault meets Wittgenstein

engine   the   financial   course,   and   that   are   responsible   for   the   crisis   of   the   sovereign   debt   in  

Europe,   is   created   also   because   of   the   absence   of   a   popular   answer   to   the   problem   of   the  

economy’s  “financialization”...Excluding  the  social  movement  against  the  precarity  of  life,  spread  

in  the  present  time  to  large  layers  of  populations,  it  seems  that  the  absence  of  a  generalized  form  

of  resistance  to  this  banker’s  and  trader’s  power  depends   less  on  a  systemic  condition  of  crisis  

than  on  systematic  discourses  and  for  a  counter-­‐agency  triggering  discoursive  regimes  that  are  

different  from  those  superimposed  by  neoliberal  ideology.  

So,  in  this  time  an  archaeological  reconstruction  of  the  subjectivity  as  a  set  of  relations  between  

powers,   knowledge   and   subjects   based   on   language's   faculty,   is   on   the   agenda.   This   means,  

according   to  Foucault,  who  points   to   an   ethic,   based  on   giving   an   account   of   oneself,   as   Judith  

Butler  has  written.  But  it's  also  important  to  say,  in  addiction  to  this  profile  of  human  praxis,  that  

the  subjectivity   in  question   is  not  only  a   construct  of   the  personal   identity  but   it   concerns  any  

possible   large   collectivities,   above   all   if  we   take   seriously   the   assertion   of  Wittgenstein   that   a  

private  language  doesn't  exist.  

Even   if  we  may  above  all  clarify   the  complexities   that   intertwine   linguistic  games  and   forms  of  

life,  in  order  to  build  an  ethic  of  the  self  that  backs  out  of  social  imperatives  and  impositions,    we  

need  to  remember  that  the  set  of  relations  in  which  the  subjectivity  is  constitute  are  effects  of  an  

exteriority.  An  individual  exteriority  (that  Nietzsche  has  described  as  continous  disappointment  

of   the  Humanism);   an   environmental   exteriority;   a  moral,   religious,   familiar   exteriority   (in   the  

way   in   which   traditions,   habits   and   norms   are   accepted   by   the   subject);   finally   a   social  

exteriority,  (of  the  power  of  the  State,  of  the  administration  of  the  economy,  of  the  impositions  of  

chasteness   in  a  time  of  crisis).  Therefore,  Foucault  determines  the  subjectivities  as  the  effect  of  

education   or   of   the   familiar  morality   or   of   the   individual   structure   of   thinking   assumed   to   be  

outside.    

On  the  surface  we  can  suppose  some  differences  between  Wittegenstein’s  and  Foucault’s  concept  

of  the  self.  These  differencies  are  schematically  represented  as  follow:  

 

1)   While   Wittgenstein   elaborate   a   first   person   subjectivity   founded   in   the   sector   in   which  

linguistic  games  and  form  of  life  are  situated,  in  contrast  Foucault  asserts  that  this  subjectivity  is,  

as   Nietzsche   does,   fragmented   and   covered   by   a   will   of   potence,   that   is   specified   as   will   of  

knowledge,  relations  of  power  and  practices  of  subjectivation.  

Page 5: A sharp way of thinking, a productive way of living. When Foucault meets Wittgenstein

 

2)   While   the   ethical   ground   in   Wittgenstein   is   determined   by   the   right   application   of   the  

language's  rules  to  the  praxis,  even  if  this  issue  is  problematic  and  finally  not  solved,  according  to  

there  for  Foucault  is  a  question  of  method,  maybe  the  major  ethical  question,  in  which  habits  are  

interlaced  with  games  of  truth,  and  certain  possibilities  of  subjectivation  and  paths  to  knowledge,  

are  linked  to  historical  contingencies.  

 

3)   This   determines   different   positions   in   order   to   consider   the   history   and   the   relationships  

between   history   and   biographical   history.   While   for   Wittgenstein   the   historical   time   is  

determined  in  part  by  the  continous  personal  search  for  the  foundations  of  reason,  and  in  part  for  

different   linguistic   games   that   the   men   initiate   in   different   situations   in   life;   for   Foucault   the  

history  is  an  optical  effect  of  a  cronological  way  of  thinking  that  doesn’t  correspond  at  all  to  the  

reality,   whether   it   is   the   reality   of   the   self,   or   the   social   reality,   or   the   reality   of   different  

discoursive  regimes  of  knowledge.  

 

Therefore,   the  genealogical  method  destroys   the  historicism  and  replaces   it,   after   the   lesson  of  

the   historical   school   of   the   Annales   and   the   teachings   of   Canguilhem,   with   a   research   into    

statements   of   culture,   social   habits,   and   power's   dispositives.   But   these   differences,   that  

inaugurate   a   zone   of   separation   don’t   prevent   compatibilities   between   Wittgenstein's   and  

Foucault's  thought,  even  if  those  need  to  be  discovered  on  the  implicit  refinement  of  the  issues.  In  

fact   it   is'n  a  matter  of  static  and  absolute  differences,  and,  on  the  other  hand,   these  differences  

need  to  be  noted  in  order  to  avoid  some  genericity  and  consider  the  common  ground  of  ordinary  

and  useful  linguistic  habits.    

For  example,  where  Foucault  writes  about  approaching  the  true  nature  of  language  by  searching  

into  the  perifery,  where  the  daily  use  of  language  permit  us  to  make  sense  of  a  word,  and  where  

the  enunciation  neutralizes  the  single  word  in  a  total  regime  of  discourse,  here  we  can  see  some  

similarity   (an   “air   of   family”   as  Wittgenstein   states)   with   the   reflection  made   in   Philosophical  

Investigations  about  the  meaning  of  words  depending  on  the  linguistic  games  that  we  play.  

So,    it  is  a  matter  of  conceiving  and  assigning  boundaries  to  the  zone  of  intersection  in  which  the  

reflection  on  the  language  in  Wittgenstein  meets  the  urgent  issues  of  subjectivation,  so  essential  

in  Foucault  and    so  productive  today.  In  fact,  at  the  beginning  of  the  XXI  Century  we  didn’t  need  to  

Page 6: A sharp way of thinking, a productive way of living. When Foucault meets Wittgenstein

start  again  with  the  question  of  wheter  or  not  the  human  faculty  of  language  is  more  or  less  at  the  

origin  of  the  human  being;  or  if  it's  for  education  or  it’s  acquired  by  the  environment,  or  society.  

In   the   same  way,   it   isn't   a  matter  of  knowing   if   and  how   the  power  builds   the   constraints  and  

dominates  the  mass  of  people  in  a  state,  or  in  the  world,  because  we  don't  know  wath  the  origins  

of  these  powers  are;  or  better,  we  know  that  these  origins  are  a  part  of  the  classical  european  era,  

but  not  the  reason,  although  we  feel  their  effects.    

Moreover  we  are  not  totally  dominates  by  the  state,  nor  by  an  economic  power  that  obstructs  the  

free   individual   enterprise,   as   Adorno   and  Horkheimer   asserted   for   the   consumption   of  mass’s  

society   in  the  Nineteen  Sixties.  The  contrary,  we  live  today  in  a   free  expanded  market   in  which  

power  is  largely  caused  by  our  praxis,  our  multiple  relations  with  others,  and  finally  by  the  kind  

of  relations  of  power  that  we  manage  and  we  can  manage  with  other  people.  In  these  processes  

marked   by   complexity,   we   find   the   governmentality   as   an   administrative   power   exercised   on  

ourselves,   also   through  ourselves;   a   kind  of  power   that  determines   the   government  of   the   self  

and  of  others.  

So   the   public   faculty   of   language,   that   is   valorized   in   this   post-­‐fordist   era,   after   decline   of    

industrial   capitalism   and   the   rise   of   “net   society”   and   the   financial   power,   now   shows   its  

structure   in  which  history  (as   individual,   contingent  daily  praxis)  and  meta-­‐history  (as  a  set  of  

conditions  of  life  and  of  agency)  are  strictly  intertwined,  as  Paolo  Virno  has  written  and  affirmed.  

So   in   this   present,   singular   intellect,   affections   and   sentiments   are   valued.   This   technical,  

scientific,  and  dispositional  framework  of  our  late  societies,  that  preside  to  the  creation  of  value  

(plusvalue)  was  cold  by  Marx  General  Intellect.    

These  post-­‐industrial  conditions  has  generated  precarity,  joblessness  and  social  discriminations  

in  which  a  small  quantity  of  rich  possess  the  largest  quantity  of  goods;  this  present  condition  is    

an  effect  of  a  multiplicity  of  governmental  dispositives,  and  it  depends  on  the  financial  power  of    

banks,  as  well  as  on  the  administrative  power  of   the  state,   linked  with  the   financial  powers;  as  

with  the  individual  ideology  of  a  free  market  that  is  now  a  personal  knowledge  that  overcomes  

the   personal  way   of   life,   preferences,   and   every   form   of   the   inner   relations   that   humans   have  

among  themselves.  Therefore,   the  zone  of   intersection  between  an  individual  and  social  way  of  

following  rules  of  language,  that  produces  the  praxis,  all  human  habits  of  life,  this  zone,  is  a  fresh    

ground  of  existence  and  of  knowledge  (as  well  as  of  research),  to  wich  we  are  constantly  exposed  

and  we  experience.  

Page 7: A sharp way of thinking, a productive way of living. When Foucault meets Wittgenstein

This   field,   that  Foucault  with   the  analysis  of  dispositives  and  Wittgenstein  with  his  highlighted  

sentences   about   "following   a   rule",   has   elaborated,   delimits   at   the   same   time   a   zone   of  

neutralization  of   the  differencies  between  nature  and  culture,   innate  and  acquired,  original  and  

derivative,   istincts  and  behaviour,  and  a  zone  of  differentiation  with  respect   to  other  zones   that  

form   the   human   praxis   (e.g.:   follow   an   ideology,   believe   in   something,   fight   for   something,  

manage  a  friendship).    

So,   here   it   isn't   a   matter   of   world-­‐of-­‐life,   as   a   separate   rational   region   of   the   existence,   as  

Habermas   has   sustained,   to   be   able   to  manage   reality  with   a   transparent   communication;   and  

isn’t   a  matter  of   autonomy  of  discoursive  practices,  wich  are  ables   to  build   a  public   sphere,   to  

oppose  to  the  power  of  money,  or  to  the  political  power  of  the  state;  but   it  regards  the  zone  of  

intersection   in  which   linguistic   games  are   structurally   connected  with   forms  of   life.  This   is   the  

place  of  singularity,  the  place  of  embodiment  of  the  rules,  the  zone  in  which  the  differentiation  of      

individual   differences   happens;   the   zone   of   separation   of   all   singular   intensities   of   individual  

profiles,   singular   shapes  of   character,   and  particular  ways  of  practicing  ethical  norms,  because  

they  are  inside  different  social  and  discoursive  regimes  of  language,  but,  because  they  are  inside    

an  individual  praxis  of  subjectivation.  

So,  this  delimitation  of  the  problem,  and  this  clarification  of  the  limits  of  this  zone  of  existence  (in  

which   we   recognize   the   intersection   of   relational   and   individual   life),   constitutes   both   the  

articulation   of   the   subject   and   the   use   of   the   language   in   an   ethical   context.   This   effect   isn’t  

expected  because  a  similarity  of  Wittgenstein  with  Foucault   in  approching  language  is  centered  

on  a  productive  and  new  escape  from  metaphisics  and  psychology.    

This  result  has  been  obtained  by  Wittgenstein  trough  the  requestionnning  of  the  reasons  for  the  

logic   of   language,   first   about   the   form   of   the   sentence   (proposition),   and,   after   the   Tractatus  

Logico-­‐Philosophicus,  reflecting  on  the  sliding  relations  between  affects,  emotions  and  their  way  

of   expression,   in   Philosophical   Investigations;   while   from   the   Foucault’s   immense   research   on  

subjectivity,  resulting  in  relationships  of  a  subject  to  an  ethic  as  an  onthology  of  the  self,  censured  

by  modernity  and  useful  as  a  form  of  interpretation  of  the  self  and  others.  

For  example,  in  the  definition  of  the  modern  human  being  as  “allothrope  empiric-­‐trascendental”,  

that  we  found  in  The  order  of  Things  ,  that  Foucault  mark  as  description  of  the  new  conception  of  

the   human   being   in   modernity,   with   the   centrality   of     the   notion   of   “life”,   and   of   “man”,   this  

definition  underline  an  archaeological  profile  of  the  concept  of  the  humans  in  which  we  are  at  the  

Page 8: A sharp way of thinking, a productive way of living. When Foucault meets Wittgenstein

end   of   the   illuminist   explaination   of   human   nature   and   the   “organicistic”   and   romantic   (see  

idealistic)  reaction  to  the  spirit  of  classification  in  the  XVIII  Century.  But  if  we  can  recognize  the  

layers   of   the   historical   concepts   of   mankind,   so   we   can   also   see   more   clearly   the   critical  

distinction  between  positivism  and  escatology  of  the  history  in  both  versions  of  Comte  and  Marx  

and   a   new   direction   of   philosophy,   in  which   historicity   is   the   source   of   finitude.   On   the   other  

hand,   this   is   not   a   termination   of   a   critical   function   of   philosophy   that   Foucault   has   specially  

described  in  the  Preface  to  Kant’s  Pragmatic  Anthropology  and  in  another  context  in  the  course  

on  The  Hermeneutics  of  the  Subject.  

Now,  the  operation  because  Foucault  removes  the  methaphysical  kantian  frame  from  the  critic,  is  

very   complex  whereas   the  Pragmatic  Anthropology   delimits   the   zone   that   differs   from   that   in  

which   the   thought   becomes   praxis   and   the   behaviour   emerges   as   an   effect   of   innate   human  

faculties  through  categories  in  the  a-­‐priori  knowledge.  

This  zone  moves  the  “I  think”  from  the  trascendental  place  that  it  has  in  the  Critic  of  Pure  Reason  

to   a   place   marked   by   an   uncertain   intersection   between   trascendental   and   empirical,   and   in  

which  we  seem  to  view  a  hybrid  constitution  of  the  subject  of  knowledge.  The  radical  operation  

of   Foucault,   in   his   last   courses,   consist   of   tracking   the   critical   function   of   philosophy.   This   is  

retraced  in  an  anti-­‐methaphysical  dimension  of  ancient  thought:  the  “pahrresia”,  so  the  function  

of   “talking   frankly”,   or   “saying   the   truth”.   In   this   way   the   subject   of   the   cartesian   tradition   is  

evicted  in  favour  of  a  subject  of  relationships,  constitued  in  empirical  experience  and  as  an  effect  

of  an  exteriority  and  doesn’t  coincide  with  some  “inner  identity”,  or  with  an  “interiority”  as  in  the  

later  christian  era.  On  the  other  hand,  and  this  is  a  very  important  gain,  the  remains  of  classical  

subjectivity,  and  of  duality  of  subject  ond  object,  do  not  eliminate  the  trascendental  issue  and  the  

human  requirement  of  the  will  of  knowledge,   in  which  modernity  trasformed  the  trascendental  

issues.    

This   process   works   within   the   formalized   development   of   science’s   languages   in   which   we  

identifiyed  modernity,  beacause,  with  Kant,    the  trascendental  form  of  thought  is  derived  from  an  

analytical  approach   to   the  subject  and  objects.  So,  we  have  a  complex   framework  composed  of  

different   and   opposite   requests:   those   of   a   trascendental   reason   that   don’t   accomplishes   their    

metaphysical   tasks   but   exist   in   the   empirical   struggle   of   the   present.   Those   of   a   dispersion   of    

knowledges   as  Husserl   has   indicated   and  demonstrated,   and   that   Foucault   has   affirmed  as   the  

historical  evidence  using  the  archeological  method  in  Archaeology  of  Knowledge.  But  also  those  of    

Page 9: A sharp way of thinking, a productive way of living. When Foucault meets Wittgenstein

empirical   experience   of   the   world   with   the   passage   from   general   grammar   to   linguistic,   from  

analysis  of  wealth  to  political  economy  and  from  natural  history  to  biology;  and  finally  those  of  

governmentality  in  which  the  power  of  the  state  becomes  an  administrative  government  of  every  

individual  life.  

As  we   see,   the   field  of  philosophical   reflection  and  of   the  praxis  has  been   completely   changed,  

starting   from   the  Eighteenth  Century,   and   the   role  of  discursive   regimes  of   truth   (in  which  we  

find   the  concept  of  human  nature),   instead  of   the  conception  of   truth  as  a  simple  and  absolute  

correspondence  between  words  and  thing,  introduces  a  meaning  of  rules  that  are  generated  from  

praxis  that   is  no  longer  naturally  subordinated  to  these.  This  concept  can  be  synthesized  in  the  

affirmation  that  the  discourses  are  artificial  products  of  human  praxis  –  made  through  arbitrarys  

rules  of   language.  Therefore  we  have  a  natural   institution,  or  the   language’s   faculty,   that  works  

with  artificial  rules.  

In  this  point  we  recognize  the  Wittgenstein’s  reflection  on    “following  the  rules”.  In  Philosophical  

Investigations   the   question   about   following   a   rule   is   described   pinpointing   different   linguistic  

games,  for  instance  the  rules  of  chess,  the  rules  of  languages  and  the  rules  of  traffic  signals.  The  

first  two  have  a  similar  but  not  identical  way  of  operating,    following  a  prohibition  signal  on  the  

street  is  something  different,  more  similar  to  an  “instinct”,  learned  with  the  practice  of  driving.        

From  this  observation,  we  must  consider  the  following:  

1)  Following   rules   in   a   game   means   to   know   these   rules   as   common,   not   private   facts.    

(referred  as   “common  human  habits   ”,   as  Wittgenstein   sustaines).  We  observe,   as  Paolo  

Virno  has  affirmed  while  commenting  on  Gilbert  Simondon’s  biological  theory,  that  there  

is  a  pre-­‐individual  dimension  in  which  is  constituted  every  individual  life,  that  grants  the  

praxis,   every   single   our   act,   and   ,   that  mantains   personal   individuation.   This   field,   this  

condition   of   our   existence,   this   context   of   our   life,   that   seems   to   be   a   meta-­‐historical  

structure  of  the  nature  of  living  beings,  in  which  works  the  rules  that  are  contained  within,  

testify   to   the   autonomy   of   these   rules,   so   their   differences   are   related   to   every   field   of  

knowledge.   In   this  case,   for  Wittgenstein  the   fact   that  a  private   language  doesn’t  exist   is  

determinated  by  the  particular  rules  of  language,  different  from  every  other  “game”  (that  

will  have  its  own  rules).  

2) Secondly,  as  the  rules  are  conventions  and  historically  situated,  our  “instinct”  in  following  

the  rules   (as   to  knowing   the  meaning  of   the  rules)   is  not  a  natural   fact,  but  a  continous  

Page 10: A sharp way of thinking, a productive way of living. When Foucault meets Wittgenstein

effect   of   modifications,   due   to   learning,   exercises   and   practicing   the   game.   Indeed,   an  

historical   fact.   A   convention   that   allows   sense   and   comprehension.   But   this,   with   a  

warning   that   comprehension   and   communication   aren’t   stable   at   all,   and   what   we  

consider  a  proper  quality  of  language,  the  transparency  of  communcations,    simply  doesn’t  

exist.  This  is  beacuse  we  discover  every  day,  in  every  act  of  speech,  that  a  supposed  link  to  

an  absolute  truth  is  at  least  problematic;  the  relationship  between  noun  and  nominate  is  

something   largely   asymmetric,   as   demonstrated   in   the   case   of   a   word   referring   to   an  

object’s  quality  (“red”,  “large”),  or  on  conventional  notation,  abstract  terms,  or  commands,  

or  interrogations,  (see  Philosophical  Investigations).  

Finally,   in  Wittgenstein   it   seems   that   rules   are   generated   by   human   praxis,   holding   their   pre-­‐

individual  character,  in  a  strange,  but  “naturally  historic”  way.  This  interlacing  of  pre-­‐individual  

rules   of   knowledge   and   individual   character   of   praxis,   in   other   words,   the   way   in   wich   we  

perform   singles   acts   of   speech,   generate   a   blurred   zone   between   rules   and   facts,   visibile   only  

when  we   separate   them   in   an   analytical   research   on   the   faculty   of   language.  On   this   the   rules  

depart   from   their   absolute   essence   and  a   single   speech   act   leaves   its   ordinary  profile   of   a   fact    

which   is   similar   to   all   others   and   gains   a   unique   and   unreplicated   quality,   that   constituts   its    

singularity.  So  we  live  in  this  zone,  mainly  without  been  aware  of  the  fact  that  every  speech  act  is  

different  from  all  other  acts  of  language  (even  if  we  use  the  same  terms  and  sentences);  but  at  the  

same   time,   comprehension   and   finally   knowledge   is   possibile   beacause  we   use   these   common  

rules.  

Therefore,   this  naturally  historical  behaviour   implies   the  evaluation  of  contingency  as  Foucault  

recognizes   in   the   modern   era.   In   present   time   the   understanding   of   rules   and   in   general   the  

criteria   of   knowledge,   the  moral   rules   and  principles   of   power,   becomes  ways   of   life,   forms  of    

existence,  are  no  longer  linked  to  an  imperative  law,  or  religious  commandment,  or  classification  

of  genres  and  living  species.  

In   the  meantime,   we   can   recognize   a   common   inclination   in  Wittgenstein’s   reflections   on   the  

ethic,    in  Bemerkungen  über  die  Philosophie  der  Psychologie,  and  in  Foucault’s  The  Order  of  Things  

that  outlines  differences  between  the  interpretation  of  modernity  in  terms  of  ethic  relativization  

of   values,   (secolarization)   after  Weber’s   thought,   and   the   processes   of   subjectivation   of  moral  

values.  This  occurs  because   in  Foucault  we  have  a  precise  evaluation  of    modernity   in  which   it  

isn’t   a   matter   of   secolarization   of   the   religious   values,   but   of   the   intersection   between   social  

Page 11: A sharp way of thinking, a productive way of living. When Foucault meets Wittgenstein

praxis  (such  as  systems  of  governmentality,  burocratic  rules,  economic  regimes  of  accumulation,  

etc)  and  forms  of  “internalization”  of  values  that  are  used  in    human  relationships  and  that  implie  

an  “exteriority”  in  which  humans  are  involved.  On  the  other  hand  the  modernity  is  marked  by  a  

dominance  of  the  state  that  conflicts  with  the  free  market  as    an  expression  of  individual  freedom,  

as  is  clarified  in  1978-­‐‘79  course  Birth  of  Biopolitic.    

This  incidentally  means  that  the  state  as  a  set  of  social  relationships  (we  would  like  to  add  that  

they  are  related  to  certain  relations  of  production)  isn’t  reductible  to  total  dominance,  in  which  

Adorno  and  Horkeheimer    identified  the  essence  of  the  state  in  late  industrial  capitalism.  So,  from  

The  Order  of  Things  to  the  course  on  the  Hermeneutics  of  the  Subject  we  interprete  modernity  as    

a  complex  set  of  practices  that  is  active  in  singular  daily  life  and  determined  by  subjectivations,  

that   is   the  way   in  which  moral   values   are   assumed   by   the   individual.   Indeed,   and   this   is   very  

important  to  point  to  the  differencies  between  Weber’s  and  critical  theory  of  Frankfurt’s  School,    

in   Foucault’s   elaboration   of   subjectivity   the   subject   can   resist   those   rules   and   norms   of  

behaviour.  

So  the  relevance  of  subjectivation  as  an  activity  of  human  beings  leaves  the  general  processes  of  

“secolarization”  and  the  generic  issue  of  total  dominance  of  the  state  over  the  individuals  in  the  

background,  and  marks  the  role  of  individuality  as  a  voluntary  assumption  of  values,  as  a  form  of  

subordination   to   the   state   power,   but   in   the   meantime   as   a   “counter-­‐behavior”,   there   is   a  

possibility  of  resistence,  and  also  a  possibility  to  build  spaces  of   freedom.  This  process  is   less  a  

matter   of   a   dialectical   relationships   between   powers   and   indivuduals   or   a   codified   system   of  

subjectivation,  than  of  a  singular  way  in  which  the  individual  manages  his  relations  to  the  State  

and    to  a  set  of  powers.  

In   this  way  we  outline  another  conceptual  element  of   this  zone  of   intersection  of  Foucault  and  

Wittgenstein’s  thought,  useful  for  interpreting  the  so  called  “post-­‐fordist  era”,  characterized  by  a  

multiplicity   of   forms   of   subjectivation   interlaced   with   forms   of   domination   of   individuals  

(assujettissement).    This  element,  that  is  also  an  idea  for  a  possible  new  field  in  philosophy,  is  to  

apply  an  analythics  of  forms  of  the  expression  of  the  self  in  the  present  regime  of  production,    in  

order  to  realize  both  forms  of  resistence  and  an  ethic  of  a  “good  life”.  

In  Wittgenstein  this  idea  of  individual  orientation  to  the  values,  and  to  the  activity  of  the  self  as  

an   ethical   search,   is   expressed   in   Tractatus   Logico-­‐Philosophicus   in   a   continous   interrogation  

about   the   individual   limits   of   language.   As   previously   stated,   the   problematic   and   difficult  

Page 12: A sharp way of thinking, a productive way of living. When Foucault meets Wittgenstein

relationship   between   language   and   the   world   pushes  Wittgenstein   to   affirm   the   priority   of   a  

logical  framework  of  language  that  reflects  a  framework  of  the  world  (therefore  logical  too).  This  

disposition  is  represented  into  the  form  of  proposition  but  this  first  and  last  theorical  gain  isn’t  

secure  at  all.  In  the  Tractatus  a  field  of  relationships  between  propositions  and  “state  of  things”  is  

described  in  wich  every  time  a  “state  of  things”  can’t  be  expressed  by  language,  this  state,  as  well  

as   the  philosophical   statements  about   the   the  world,   aren’t   real.  This  means   that   the   reality  of  

proposition   doesn’t   correspond   to   the   reality   of   the   world.   Secondly,   the   criterium   of   truth  

applied  by   language   to   the  world    has  an  asymmetrical   correspondence   to  each  element  of   the  

language  and  each  element  of  the  world.  So,  with  respect  to  the  traditional  result  of    metaphisics,  

here   we   have   a   productive   twist   caused   by   taking   the   impossible   reduction   of   the   world’s  

framework   into   the   form   of   proposition   seriously.   When   in   fact   the   criterium   of   truth   as   a  

correspondence  (adequatio)  between  words  and  things  is  dissolved,  we  can  suppose  on  one  hand  

an   infinite  world,   and   on   the   other   a   language   that   expresses   all   that   can   be   express,  whitout    

anything  remaining,  but  limited  in  expressing  the  world.  This  signifies  the  attempt  of  language  to  

reach   the   sense  of   the  world,   starting   from   its   limits,   and   seems,  maybe  different  with   respect  

other  interpretations  of  Wittgenstein’s  thought,  not  proof  of  an  impossibility  but  a  challenge  for  

knowledge  in  order  for  individual  to  change  life,  trasforming  his  way  of  thinking.  

But  this  continous  comparison  between  facts  and  words  also  means  that  all  that  is  appearing  in  

the  world  is  thinkable  and  expressible  by  the  language.  

Now,  with   this  we  must’n   think   that   the  mere  perception  of   things   is   simple  and  and   that   it   is  

resolved  in  the  act  of  speeching;  on  the  contrary,  this  attempt,  in  the  Wittgenstein’s  approach,  is    

a   struggle   of   thought,   as   a   sort   of   “mystic   pilgrimage”   to   purify   oneself   from   all   the   ordinary  

casualties   of   common   speech.   So,   for   the  moment,   it   is   a  matter   of   regenerating   our   habits   of  

expression,  discovering  a  world  with  another  view,  or  better,  with  an  “other”  view,  and  it  isn’t    a  

matter  of  recognizing  a   form  of   life  based  on  the  way   in  wich  we  use   language.   In   this  point  of  

discontinuity,   but   not   of   fracture   in  Wittgenstein’s   thought,   Pierre  Hadot   ponts   out   the   role   of    

linguistic  practice.  

As  he  writes  in  his  collection  of  essays  on  Wittgenstein,  Wittgenstein  et  les  limites  du  langage,    to  

recognize   things   in   an   immediate   linguistic   peception  doesn’t  mean   that   this   operation   simply  

connects   every   object   to   a   name;   on   the   other   hand,   this   inevitable   discontinuity   allows   us   to  

recognize  the  expression  of  things  as  limited  and  marked  by  contingency.  The  common  faculties  

Page 13: A sharp way of thinking, a productive way of living. When Foucault meets Wittgenstein

of  mankind  can’t  express  the   illimited  world,  so  “the   limits  of  my  language  are  the   limits  of  my  

world”.  As  Hadot  affirms,  the  main  problem  with  Wittgenstein’s  conception  of  language  revolves    

around   the   insurmountable   limits   of   expression,   because   we   have   been   experiencing   the  

language   since   our   birth   and  we   are   its   thereshold.   For  Wittgenstein   because   rules   that   have  

value  only  for  me  aren’t  rules  at  all,  the  subject  is  at  the  outer  limits  of    language,  so  this  eccentric  

position  of  subjectivity  traces  the  infinite  boundaries  of  an  impossibility.  

With  regards  to  the  limits  of  expression  some  of  the  examples  in  Philosophical  Investigations  are  

about  pain  and  the  expressions  of  pain.  These  aren’t  the  same  thing,  as  Wittgenstein  has  writing,  

because  to  cry  out  in  pain  is  different  than  to  feel  pain.  Here  the  language  let  us  discover  our  own  

limits,   that   are   useful   both   for   the   expression   of   pain,   and   for   expressing   this   pain   using   our  

language.      

As  Wittgenstein  has  pointed  out,  the  nature  of  the  language  rests  in  this  fracture  between  feeling  

and  it’s  expression,  because  to  account  for  a  symmetry  between  things  and  their  expression  we  

should  be  exterior  to  language  and  the  world.  In  any  ordinary  situation  every  explanation  of  our  

state  of  mind,  or  sentiments,  or  affects  is  a  linguistic  expression,  and  this  expression  needs  to  be  

explained  by  another   linguistic  expression,  and  so  on…  We  are   forever   inside  the   language  and  

paradoxally,  a  metalinguistic  task  with  which  we  explain  the  language  –  object,  should  be  exterior  

to  language,  and  this  is  contradictory.  

Since  we  use  the  same  rules  of  language  and  the  assurance  of  comprehension  of  our  speech  is  due  

to  this  “natural  human  habit”  that  permits  us  to  express  the  expressible,  the  problem  is  that  the  

prior  limit  of  expression  accompanies  any  single  speech  act;   it  constitutes  our  language  faculty,  

so  we  can’t  ever  separate  it  from  a  speech  act.  So  every  statement  contains  whithin  inside  itself  

the  inexspressible  aspect  of  language,  and  this  is  the  threshold  of  the  expressible,  the  ineffable  of  

the  world  as  demonstrate  by  the  expression  of  feelings  and  the  expressions  of  abstract  things.    

Hadot  insist  on  the  insurmountable  nature  of  language  and,  for  him,  this  limit  gives  an  account  of    

“the  mystic”  that  Wittgenstein  conceives.  But  we  observe  that  the  sentence  written  at  the  end  of    

Tractatus   is   a   matter   of   affects,   feelings,   emotions.   The   limits   of   language   and   the   will   of  

expression  of  oneself  with  daily  practice,   is  visible  here;  but,   in  contrast  to  Hadot,  this  fact   isn’t  

matter  of  an  isolated  person  who  has  choosen  to  remove  himself  from  the  world,  but  with  only  

this  limitation,  so  that  the  contingency  of  every  speech  act,  contitutes  the  faculty  of  language,  and  

within  this  limitation  we  recognize  the  nature  of  language  as  our  nature.    

Page 14: A sharp way of thinking, a productive way of living. When Foucault meets Wittgenstein

Hadot  has  compared  Wittgenstein  to  the  Stoics,  in  which  philosophy  is  a  therapy  that  consists  of    

removing   any   usual   habits   of   using   language   (and   of   thinking)   and   performing   a   continous  

analytical  exercise  on  our  way  of   thinking,  based  on  the  reflection  of  our  speech.  This  strenous  

and  difficult  daily  practice  leads  to  a  transformation  of  the  self  attempts  to  achieve  a  sharpness  

and  to  get  to  the  essential  of  things.  With  this  practice,  at  the  end  of  Tractatus  Wittgenstein  points  

out  the  result  of  philosophy  as  a  therapy:  the  philosophical  ladder  as  outline  in  Tractatus  bring  us  

to  a  new  dimension  of  thought  that  is  also  an  ethical  dimension  of  life.  

Here   we   may   observe   two   points   in   this   syntetic   reconstruction   that   brings   Wittgenstein’s  

thought  close  to  Foucault.  

To  mention  this,  it  is  necessary  to  address  Hegel’s  reflection  on  language  and  referred  to  Giorgio  

Agamben   in   his   book   Il   linguaggio   e   la   morte.   Hegel,   first   in   his   poem   Eleusis   dedicated   to  

Holderlin,  and  later  in  the  first  chapter  of  Phenomenology  of  the  Spirit,  on  the  Sensible  Certainty,  

confronting  the  inexpressible  zone  of  language,  offers  two  solutions  to  the  question  of  meaning.  

In  Eleusis   a  mythical   language  of   the   sacred   is   escaping   and   it   is   dissolved  when   the  divinities  

leave   Earth   and   are   seek   refuge   on   Mount   Olympus.   So,   from   that   moment   every   attempt   to  

restore  speech  in  order  to  interprete  and  explain  this  sacred  lost  language  is  condemned  to  fail.  

As  Agamben  has  written,  this  means  the  unavailability  of  any  language  to  express  things  anything  

but  a  decayed  way.    

In  Phenomenology  of  the  Spirit  Hegel’s   thought  on   language   changes  and   the  question  becomes    

how  daily  language  connects  immediatly  with  Sensible  Certainty  in  order  to  reach  the  true  sense  

that  mankind  strives  to  express.  These  difficulties  of  expression  are  shown  in  the  adjectiv  “this”  

with  which  we  express  the  case  of  Sensible  Certainty:  e.g.,  this  tree,  this  horse,  this  situation.  For  

all   of   these   simple   specifications   of   objects   using   “this”,   that   renders   a   specificity   of   an   object  

through  all  others,  in  that  specific  case  inevitably  we  find  a  universality,  created  by  the  “this”  (all  

“this),   that   doesn’t   have   any   specific   reference   to   the   object   to   which   it   is   associated.   So,   an  

element  of  language  normally  used  to  describe  individuality  instead  referes  to  universality.  And  

universality   is   the  way   in  wich   language  necessarily  expresses   things  and  situations.  For  Hegel  

this  means  that  the  Sensible  Certainty  isn’t  the  true  essence  of  things.  This  truth,  as  we  know,  is  

found   at   the   end   of   a   dialectical   process   in   which   the   Spirit   is   plunged   and,   as   Agamben  

demonstrates,  this  end  is  also  at  the  beginning  of  the  dialectical  process,  for  an  important  reason  

that  we  will  consider  later.  The  dialectic  is  moved  by  the  moment  of  negativity  of  language  that  

Page 15: A sharp way of thinking, a productive way of living. When Foucault meets Wittgenstein

subtracts   the   meaning   at   the   same   moment   in   which   it   extablishes   it.   The   “cast   off”   is   the  

essential  dialectical  movement  of  reality,  without  which  we  don’t  have  any  synthesis  of  “the  real”,  

or  any  knowledge,  so  we  don’t  have  any  progress  of  the  Spirit.  The  agency  of  this  “determinate  

denial”   that  provokes  universality,  builds  the  moment  of  abstraction   in  which  Hegel  recognizes  

the  work  of  language  and    the  identity  between  real  and  rational.  

If  we  attach  Hegel’s  elaboration  to  Wittgenstein’s  writings  about  the  constraints  of  language  we  

obtain   a   vision   of   speech   acts   that   are   referred   to   as   common   human   habits,   privious   of   any  

historical   language,   but   at   the   same   time   produced   by   historical   languages.   In   the   zone   of  

separation  between  any  speech  act  and  the  will  of  expression  we  find  the  rules  of  language,    and  

the   nature   of   these   rules.   These   is   the   contingent   nature   of   these   rules   because   of   their  

metahistorical  nature,  as  well  as  their  transindividual  nature  that  is  primarily  historical.  

So  the  “common  human  behaviour”  that  gives  us  a  certainty  of  comprehension  in  using  language,  

is   founded   on   a   determinate   denial,   that   presides   in   every   speech   act.   So   the   eminent  

characteristic   of   language   is   building  meanings  with   a   negative   imprint   in  wich   is   revealed   its  

nature.   This   historical   negativity,   or   this   historically   determined   denial,   gets   close   to    

Wittgenstein  and  Foucault’s  perspectives  on  the  function  of    language.      

First  of  all,   language  doesn’t   communicate  at  all.   Second,   the  meaning  of  a  word   is   it’s  use   in  a  

linguistic   game.   Third,   the   rules   of   these   games   are   immanents   to   the   game   and   are   known  

through  practice,  a  continous  “exercise”  in  which  consists  common  human  behaviour.  Four,  but  

here  we  are  aligned  with  Foucault’s  analysis  of  “discoursives  regimes”,  research  on  enunciations  

permits   us   to   see   the   complex   relationships   beetwen   knowledges,   powers   and   forms   of  

subjectivation.   Finally,   as   we   can’t   follow   a   rule   “privatim”,   any   science,   as   a   public   fact,   is  

involved  in  common  knowledge  and  find  its  formalization  and  abstraction  in  relation  to  forms  of  

power  as  they  circulate  through  humans  and  as  they  are  accepted  or  refused  by  each  individual.    

At   this   point   of   our   enquiry   Agamben’s   reflection   on   language   assumes   an   eminent   relief.   In  

particular   it’s   important  underline  the  separation  between  the  will  of  expression  and  the  sense  

that   words   can   express.   In   the   case   of   pronoun   “this”,   the   singular   qualification   of  

someone/something  doesn’t  correspond  to   the   true  sense  of   the  word.  So,  an  abstraction  of  all  

possible   individuality   is   used   to   identify   a   single   subject/object.   This   contradiction   between  

language  and  meaning,  is  really  a  contradiction  between  a  will  of  expressing  something  and  the  

expression  itself,  whose  use  is  the  meaning  itself.    

Page 16: A sharp way of thinking, a productive way of living. When Foucault meets Wittgenstein

This  acquisition  has  informed  the  crucial  work  of  Emile  Benveniste,  particularly  on  the  notion  of  

“instance  of  the  enunciation”  attributed  to  a  person  speaking.  In  this  case  we  must  remark  on  the  

real  existence  of  a  subject  who  is  talking,  (even  if  some  critics  have  argued  that  in  Benveniste  isn’t  

a  matter  of  subject,  but  of  a  discursive  instance  in  a  linguistic  framework),  since  the  attention  is  

moved  away  from  the  semantic  to  the  semiotic  field.    

So  that,  only   in  the  “original”  separation  between   language  and  speech,   langue  and  parole  after  

Ferdinand  de  Saussure’s  distinction,  we  may  reconnect   language  and  subject,    and  we  may  talk  

about   an   historical   co-­‐original   source   of   language   and   subject.   This   way   of   considering   the  

language  is  testified  to  the  pronoun  “I”,  and  by  all  the  deictic  adverbs  as  “here”,  “now”,  “this”,  that  

Roman  Jakobson  called  shifters,  beacuse  they  point  to  an  instance  of  enunciation.  They  really  are  

indicators   of   an   instance   of   discourse,   something   exclusively   linguistic   before   assuming   some  

sense,  in  which  the  nature  of  language  is  solved.  

As  Benveniste,  quoted  by  Agamben,  wrote,  «…  “I”  means  “the  person  that  enunciates  the  present  

request  of  discourse   that   includes   “I”.»   (my   translation).  And   the   indicators   like  adjectives  and  

pronouns  (shifters),  such  as  the  “I”  pronoun,  have  the  function  to  operate,  «  the  conversion  of  the  

language   in   discourse».   And   again   with   Agamben,   the   shifters   in   Jakobson’s   theory   have   the  

function  of  passing  from  meaning  to  indication,  from  language  (langue)  to  speech  (parole).    

So  we  don’t  have  an  extralinguistic  origin  of  language  and  of  human  kind,  but,  as  the  shifters  of  

the  “instance  of  the  discourse”  indicate,  we  are  inside  the  language  “all  the  time”  and  “right  now”.  

In   the  second   instance,  verbs   that   indicate   the  act  of   say  something   (e.g.:   “I   say   that…”,)  or   the  

speech  formulas  that  Austin  calls  absolute  performative,  such  as  “I  promise”,  “I  command”,  “I  take  

this   woman   as   my   legitimate   wife”,   “I   baptize   Paul   this   child”   and   all   religious   and   civil  

ceremonies,  indicate  a  “fact  of  speech”,  not  “wath  is  being  talking  about”.  

Therefore,   as   Paolo   Virno   affirm,   this   sentencies   directly   show   faculty   of   language,   here   as  

subjective  instances  of  discourse,  and  not  as  particular  meaning  that  words  have  express.  As  in  

the  speech  formulas  “How  are  you?”,  “See  you  later”,  or  simply  “Hi”,  the  “I  say”:  “(I  say)  how  are  

you”,  “(I  say)  see  you  later”,  “(I  say)  hi!”  are  supposed.  So,  these  expressions  as  speech  acts  are  

referred  to  the  faculty  of  language,  as  potentiality  of  talking,  embodied  in  a  single  subject.  This  is  

the   most   important   aspect   of   language   in   which   we   recognize   a   deep   relationship   between    

general  faculty  and  subjectivity.  As  Wittgenstein  has  written,  “when  the  language  fails”  emerge  its  

quality…  to  be  the  nature  of    the  subject;  so  that,  human  praxis.  

Page 17: A sharp way of thinking, a productive way of living. When Foucault meets Wittgenstein

In   Foucault’s   terms,   modernity   is   carachterized   for   a   will   of   know   struggling   with   reality   of  

language.  The  voluntary  aknowledgment  of  language’s  rules  requires  expressions  of  speech  that  

are  different  respect  to  the  will  of  talk.  So,  as  this  radical  opposition  is  suppressed  in  to  reality  of  

language,  anyway  its  generates  the  space  of  the  language,  the  place  in  which  it’s  becoming  real.  

This  is  the  source  of  every  speech  act.  

 As  Giorgio  Agamben  has  clarified  and  Pierre  Hadot  has  intensively  described  in  his  book  Le  voile  

d'Isis  :  essai  sur  l'histoire  de  l'idée  de  nature,  studying  Goethe’s  concept  of  nature,  need  to  consider  

the   source   of   language   as   an   Urphanomenon,   a   “pre-­‐evenemential”   origin   that   generates   an  

opposition   between   sense   and   speech   willing,   and   at   same   time   a   linguistic   identity   between  

concepts  of  the  particular  and  the  universal.  

But  the  sense  of  Urphanomenon  must  be  know,  as  Agamben  pointed  out,  as  historical  source  of    

language,  not  as  a  pre-­‐historical  and  absolute  origin  of  it,  which  every  form  of  expression  should  

depends.    Contrary,   the  Urphanomenon   is   immanent   to   the  practice  of   language  and   there   isn’t  

any   trascendental   form  able   to  reduce  all   its   functions.   In   this  sense  Urphanomenon  need  to  be  

considered  as  a  set  of  possibilities  of  speech,  and  it’s  strictly  intertwined  with  every  speech  act.  

So,   it   only   exists   as   historical   event   and,   on   the   other   side,   a   single   speech   act   in   his   own  

contingency  expresses  common  human  behaviour  (as  faculty  of  language).  

The  Urphanomenon   so   conceived,   let   to   emerge   the   historical   nature   of   language   and   offer   us,  

differently   from  Kant,   a   conception   of   trascendental   form   less   analythical   (rational),   and  more  

purposeful  in  accounting  for  relationships  between  subject  and  objects.  As  Goethe  has  criticized    

Romantic  poets  because  they  had  an  absolute  concept  of  origin  of  nature  that  he  supposes  they      

employed,   the   historical   view   of   language’s   source,   generating   the   modern   comparative  

linguistics,  is  one  of  the  most  important  gain  in  modernity  era.    

This  point  was  extraordinary  highlighted  by  Gianni  Carchia  in  the  essay  Nome  e  immagine.  Saggio  

su  Walter  Benjamin,   in  wich   he   has   explained   how   the   great   dutch   philosopher  was   conceived  

historical  materialism  after  Marx   in   a  messianic  dimension,   as   source  of   creation  and  as   set  of  

tools  of   artistic   creation.   In   the  preface  of   the   essay  on  Goethe’s  Electives  Affinities   (Kindred  by  

Choice),   Benjamin   wroted   as   differently   from   Romantics   Goethe   has   thought   relationships  

between  Art  and  Nature  as  a  series  of  creative  links  that  derives  from  a  set  of  natural  figures,  no  

more  mythicals  but  historicals.  This   is  a   fundamental  gain   that  brake  off   the   limits  of   idealistic  

conception  of  the  art  in  which  the  progress  of  self-­‐comprehension  of  Spirit  automatically  should  

Page 18: A sharp way of thinking, a productive way of living. When Foucault meets Wittgenstein

allow   to   the   “truth”   of   the   art.   But   the   misunderstand   about   Goethe   consists   in   his   idea   of   a  

natural  mythical  remain  in  activity  of  the  artist,  even  if  Goethe  considers  art  as  historical  product,  

out  of  any  natural  archetype.    

The  conception  of  the  language  in  Benjamin,  as  expression  of  noun  that  need  to  be  rescued  inside  

the   history,   conducts   him   to   the   essential  meaning   of   Goethe’s   aestethics,   while   he   affirm   the  

priority  of  some  “naturally”  historical  source  of  artistic  forms,  and  he  explain  it  with  necessity  to  

avoid    the  complete  ruin  of  prior  nominative  function  of  language,  same  as  Urphanomenon  lost  in  

the  historical  languages.  We  catch  a  glimpse  of  an  eminent  theorical  and  historical  effect  of  this  

lost  in  Gershom  Sholem’s  polemical  mail  addressed  to  Franz  Rosenzweig  about  a  new  language  of  

the  Hebrew,  after  the  world  war  two,   largerly  commented  by  Jacques  Derrida   in  the  essays  Les  

yeux  de  la  langue.  

This   entire   co-­‐relationship   between   Urphanomenon   and   historical   possibilities   of   language  

defines  the  place  of  language  itself  as  metahistorical  source,  not  placed  at  the  beginning  or  at  the  

end  of  the  history,  but  inside  it.  This  seems  to  be  true    in  the  present  time.    

Today   in   every   speech   act,   in   every   daily   action,   in   the   whole   praxis,   we   observe   the  

metahistorical   faculty   of   language   as   historical   one.   And  we   see   also   the  way   in  which   the   so  

called  “past”  and    the  “future”  too  are  both  present  in  same  time.  The  use  of  language  testifies  that  

the   link   between   the   past   and   the   present   is   already   given   whereas   the   past   is   available   as  

threshold  of  the  present.    

So,   the   past   takes   in   the   present   all   possibilities   of   a   radical   transformation   of   things,   a  

revolutionary  change  due  to  messiah  beaking  off  in  daily  life.  So  the  future  becomes  shorten  in  a    

present  considered  as  “time  of  now”,  that  gives  rise  to  occasions  of  revolution.  So,  as  we  see,    the  

messianic   “time  of  now”  has   the   function   to  ricapitulate   the  whole  history  of  mankind  same  as    

the   language  in  every  present  time  has  the  funcion  to  restore  the  act  of  nomination  in  order  to  

align  the  meaning  of  words  and  the  will  of  expression;  so  in  this  way  the  lost  totality  of  relations  

between   nouns   and   things   are   entirely   restored   (restitutio   ad   integrum).   In   this   situation,  

according  to  Benjamin,  we  obtain  happiness  as  unique,  terrestrial  gain  of  humans.  

But  with  a  foundamental  warning:  this  “so  restored”  totality  isn’t  an  absolute  state  of  thinghs,  or  

an   archetypal   condition   accomplished   at   the   end   of   the   history;   or   an   Urphanomenon   that  

precede  the  history  and  it’s  separated  from  it  like  an  originary,  pre-­‐historical  event.  The  integrity  

which  everyone  aims  to  is  an  historical  possibility,  as  a  potentiality  of  human  beings  already  done  

Page 19: A sharp way of thinking, a productive way of living. When Foucault meets Wittgenstein

in   the   present   and   in   every   terrestrial   place.   So,   it’s   a   matter   of   praxis   and   not   of   dialectical  

totality,   or   trascendental   process   of   comprehension   caused   by   some   “a-­‐priori”   separated   from  

history.  

Contrary,  in  this  historical  materialism  of  Benjamin’s  thought,  and  in  his  conception  of  language,    

that  proceedes  from  a  real  movement,  we  see  the  precious  structure  of    an  “historical  a-­‐priori”,    

identified  in  Foucault’s  Words  and  Things  as  the  cypher  of  modernity.  In  this  historical  condition  

of  the  time,  in  which  we  clearly  observe  the  true  relations  between  subjects,  knoledge  and  power  

in  our  modern  era,  the  large  conceptual  definition  able  to  interprete  the  present  time  –  while  the  

historical   a-­‐priori   produces   modernity   at   large   –   determines   subject   as   effect   of   a   tangled  

entertwine.    

So,    the  subject  of  modernity  is  configured  as  an  “empiric-­‐trascendental  allotrope”,  that  is  a  being  

which  his  own  existence  implies  his  essence,  or,  as  in  Marx,  a  being  that  in  addition  to  living  need  

to  produce  conditions  of  his  own  life.  We  can  say  it  because  means  of  production  are  conditions  

that  assure  the  reproduction  of  human  beings.  

As   Foucault   point   out,   this   process   is   spread   in   different   grounds   of   agency,   not   only   in  

economical  field,  but  also  in  the  knowledge  and    in  co-­‐relationship  with  other  men  into  industrial  

way  of  working  (as  cooperation).  

So,   if   we   consider   this   point   of   view   that   join   Marx   with   Foucault’s   thought   of   capitalistic  

modernity,   the   activities   of   manhood,   the   entire   human   praxis,   we   observe   an   entertwine  

between  meta-­‐historical  conditions  of  life  and  historical  one  as  events  of  production,  valorized  by  

capitalism.   As   Paolo   Virno   has   written   in   many   occasions,   the   lead   carachter   of   capitalistic  

modernity  is  the  daily  entertwine  of  meta-­‐historical  reproduction  of  life  and  goods  and  historical  

acts  of  work,  without  whose,  conditions  of  reproduction  of  the  life  simply  aren’t  available  at  all.    

In  this  sense  we  have  a  figure  of  subject  that,  as  Foucault  has  outlined,  is  characterized  at  least  for  

a  double  discoursive  regime,  or  even,  for  a  multiplicity  of  these  regimes  in  a  double  articulation  of  

the  individual  life:  the  production  of  the  “self”  and  “others”  (reproduction)  and  the  production  of    

social  relations  and  goods  (production).  So  that,  subjectivity   is  crushed  in  multiple   identities  as  

the  utterances  are.  This  mean,  ,  according  with  Wittgenstein’s  reflection  on  the  forms  of  life,  that  

the  concept  of  just  one  individual  identity  is  achieved  if  everyday  we  are  playing  more  than  one  

linguistic  game.    

In  second  istance,  we  need  to  consider  subjectivity,  particularly  in  the  late  modernity,  as  marked  

Page 20: A sharp way of thinking, a productive way of living. When Foucault meets Wittgenstein

by   post-­‐fordist’s   production   of   goods,   that   is   an   effect   due   to   valorization   of   linguistical  

structures,  that  consist  in    non-­‐substancial  essence  of  individuality.  

As  we  see,  considering  the  spread  of  post-­‐fordist  regime  of  production  until   the  Eighties  of   the  

last  Century,   in  philosophy  we  are  present  at  the  “linguistic  turn”.  But  this  perspective   in  many  

cases   was   adopted   in   “continental”   philosophy   to   justify   via   Nietzsche   the   so   called   “faible  

thought”,   in  wich   post-­‐modernist   thinkers   declare   “the   end   of   the   history”.   On   the   other   side,  

according   with   interpretation   of   Nietzsche’s   thought   against   the   historism   and   the   excess   of  

historical   culture   in  modernity   era,   besides   against   the   “faible   tought”,  we   prefer   to   tell   about  

history  in  this  post-­‐fordist  era,  whereas  in  the  theatre  of  capitalistic  production  shows  its  meta-­‐

historical  conditions  of  existence;  so,  a  concept  of  subject  fading  his  identity  in  contingencies  of  

multiple   linguistic   games   is   here   elaborated.   In   this   configuration  of   subjectivity,   as   Freud   and  

after  Lacan  have  strongly  affirmed  (taking  serious  the  sentence  of  the  latter:  “the  inconscious  is  

structured   as   a   language”),   we   can   reconstruct   a   shape   of   a   subject   having   many   similarities  

between  Wittgenstein’s  idea  of  man  as  threshold  of  language  and  of  Foucault,  conceiving  human  

being   as   affected   by   processes   of   subjectivation.   So   we   can   reconnect   this   similarity   to   a  

materialistic   philosophy,   adopting   the   Aristote’s   definition   of   man   as   animal   provided   with  

language  (zoon  logon  exxon).  

This   notion   avoid   the   gross   materialism   based   over   a   strict   distinction   between   economical  

structure   of   societies   and   redundant   symbolic   superstructure   of   these,   including   the  

reproduction  of   life,  as   it’s  occured  with  post-­‐structuralism  of   last   fifties,   fortunately  broked  up  

by  feminist’s  teory  of  genres  and  trans-­‐genre  (e.g.  in  Teresa  de  Lauretis’s  thought).  

Along  this  lines  we  attempted  to  clarify  an  aspect  of  the  radical  stance  on  subjectivity  in  which  it’s  

possible  to  recognize  a  point  of  departure  of  Wittgenstein’s  and  Foucault’s  reflection,   indirectly  

confirmed  by  a  materialist  and  non-­‐dialectical  thought.  This  concept  of  subjectivity  as  eminently  

clarified   in   the   volumes  on  History  of  Sexuality   (as  The  Will  of  Know,  L’usage  des  plaisirs,   really  

published,  and   in   the  project  of  Les  aveu  de  la  chair),  but  above  all   in   the  courses  at  Collège  de  

France,  from  1979  to  1984,  and  in  the  conferences  in  U.S.  and  Canada  in  the  last  Seventies.  Here  

we  know  how  Foucault  has   considered   the   classical   greek  philosophy  and  Ellenistic   schools  of  

thought  (Stoics,  Epicureans,  Cinics  and  Latin  stoicism)  as  models  of  the  “technologies  of  the  self”,  

spreading   a   concept   of   subjectivity   not   primarily   caused   by   economical   or   social   condition   of  

existence,   but   which   it’s   covered   by   the   sphere   of   knowledge   and   of   sciences,   as   well   as   by    

Page 21: A sharp way of thinking, a productive way of living. When Foucault meets Wittgenstein

power’s  relationships,  and  truth  itself.  

In  this  case  we  can  reconnect  different  regimes  of  truth  to  a  different  dispositives  of  power  (the  

disciplinary   institutions   as  psychiatric   clinics,   hospitals,   schools,   jails,   barracks)   and   today   to   a  

different  dispositives  of  control,  both  burocratic  and  digital,  indeed  to  a  different  way  to  govern    

humans    (governmentality).  So  the  attention  of  Foucault  to  simply  avoid  such  reduction  of  subject  

to  an  affair  of  domination  (because  of  the  state  or  the  economics),  and  his  precious  insistence  in  

outline  different  kinds  of  determinations  in  building  relations  of  power  and  submission,  definitly  

has   detached   his   thought   as   from   Adorno   and   Horkheimer’s   critical   theory   (see   Birth   of  

biopolitics   course   of   1979),   as   from   Habermas’s   theory   of   transparent   relationships   between  

humans   in  communication;  but  also   from  Husserl’s  phenomenology,  and  Sartre’s  existentialism  

based  on  a  free  action  choosed  by  the  “I”  oneself;  as,  at  least,  from  all  “faible”  theories  of  subject  

that   have   misunderstood   the   real   meaning   of   multiple   regimes   of   utterances   in   composing  

different   layers  of   subjectivity,  and  are  given   this  effect  as  a  definitive   “end  of   the  history”  and  

complete  dissolution  of  material  conditions  of  existence  of  subjects.  

So,  we  have  a   large   field  of  enquiry  of  subjectivity,  simply  drafted  here,   in  which  philosophy  of  

language,  natural  history  and  social  sciences,  all  considered  in  an  archaeology  of  knowledge,  are  

intertwined   to   scketching   up,   after   Nietzsche’s   end   of   the   man,   a   new   shape   of   subjectivity.  

Moreover   this  approach   to   the  human  being  constitutes  a  genealogy  of  present  time   that  seems  

useful  in  this  present  where  government  of  livings  is  the  core  production  of  economical  values.    

The  question  of  the  subjectivity  glimpsed  in  Wittgenstein’s  notion  of  humans,  which  are  placed  at  

the   limit   of   the   language   and   are   playing   different   linguistical   games   as   they   are   inhabitant   of    

forms  of   life,   is  so  related  to  an  ethical  transformation  of  the  self  no  more  based  on  an  abstract  

moral  duty  but  on  a  historical  presence  on  earth.  The  emerge  of  subjectivity  affected  by  intrinsic  

flexibility   of   attitudes   as   it’s   wanted   by   capitalism   is   already   an   evidence   in   Wittgenstein’s  

conception  of  language  in  order  to  the  public  rules  of    behaviour.  

This   fact   implies   to  ask  oneself   if   it’s  possible   to  build  a   form  of   life   in  which   safeguard  of  our  

historical  nature  it  allows  to  deactivate  dispositives  of  capture;  and  how  is  possibile  to  avoid  anti-­‐

historical   turn   constitued   by   fictitious,   closed   and   dangerous   ghetto-­‐communities.   In   the  

meantime,  we  need   to   ask   ourself   how  avoid   an   out-­‐of-­‐time  decrease   in   technologies   that  will  

damage  the  attempts  to  escape  the  logic  of  profit.    

In   this   last   years  many   configurations   of   subjectivity   has   attempted   to   get   out   from  neoliberal  

Page 22: A sharp way of thinking, a productive way of living. When Foucault meets Wittgenstein

form  of  societies:  protests,  occupying,  riots,  but  a  question  is  remaining:  how,  after  the  end  of  the  

man,  some  subjectivity  as  complex  between  singular  and  common   is  possible.  And  we  suppose  

it’s  done  if  we  are  able  to  manage  relationships  between  language,  power  and  freedom.    

 

                    _____________________________  

 

 

Bibliography  

 

 

GIORGIO  AGAMBEN,  Il  linguaggio  e  la  morte.  Un  seminario  sul  luogo  della  negatività,  Einaudi,                  

                           Torino,  1982,  2008.  

                           Infanzia  e  storia.  Distruzione  dell’esperienza  e  origine  della  storia,  Einaudi,              

                         Torino  1978,  2001.  

Quel   che   resta   di   Auschwitz.   L’archivio   e   il   testimone,   Bollati   Boringhieri,                            

Einaudi,  Torino,  1998,  2010.  

 

WALTER  BENJAMIN,  “Sulla  lingua  in  generale  e  sulla  lingua  degli  uomini”,  in  Angelus  Novus.  Saggi          

                                                                                     e    frammenti,  trad.  it:,  Einaudi,  Torino,  1976.  

 

GIANNI  CARCHIA,     Nome  e  immagine.  Saggio  su  Walter  Benjamin,  Quodlibet,  Macerata,  2009  

 

NOAM  CHOMSKY,    

MICHEL  FOUCAULT,  Della  natura  umana.  Invariante  biologico  e  potere  politico,          

                    trad.it.,  DeriveApprodi,  Roma,  2005,  2008  

 

JACQUES  DERRIDA,    Gli  occhi  della  lingua,  trad.it.,  Mimesis,  Milano,  2011  

 

PIERRE  HADOT,                 Il  velo  di  Iside,  trad.it.,  Einaudi,  Torino,  2006.  

P.  HADOT,                                      Wittgenstein   e   i   limiti   del   linguaggio,   trad.it.,   Bollati   Boringhieri,   Torino,  

2007.  

Page 23: A sharp way of thinking, a productive way of living. When Foucault meets Wittgenstein

MICHEL  FOUCAULT,  Le  parole  e  le  cose,  trad.it.,  Rizzoli,  Milano,  1967  

                                                                               L’archeologia  del  sapere,  trad.  it,  Rizzoli,    Milano,  1971  

                                                                             L’ordine  del  discorso,  trad.it.,  Einaudi  Editore,  Torino  1972  

                                                                             La  volontà  di  sapere,  trad.it.,  Feltrinelli,  Milano  1978  

                                                                             “Subjectivity  and  Truth”,  “Christianity  and  Confession”,  in  Sull’origine                    

                                                                             dell’ermeneutica  del  sé,  Cronopio,  Napoli,  2012.  

                                                                             Tecnologie  del  sé.  Un  seminario  con  Michel  Foucault,  Bollati  Boringhieri,      

                                                                             Torino,  1992                      

                                                                             Discorso  e  verità  nella  Grecia  Antica,  Donzelli,  Roma,  1996  

                                                                             Il  discorso,  la  verità,  la  storia,    Einaudi,  Torino,  2001  

                                                 Nascita  della  biopolitica  (1978-­‐1979),    trad.it.,  Feltrinelli,  Milano  2005  

                                                                             L'ermeneutica  del  soggetto  (1981-­‐1982),  trad.it.,  Feltrinelli,  Milano  2003  

                                                                             Il  governo  di  sé  e  degli  altri  (1982-­‐1983),  trad.it.,  Feltrinelli,  Milano,  2009  

                                                                             Il  coraggio  della  verità,  (1984),  trad.it.,  Feltrinelli,  Milano,  2011  

 

PAOLO  VIRNO,             Scienze   sociali   e   “natura  umana”.  Facoltà  di   linguaggio,   invariante  biologico,      

rapporti  di  produzione,  Rubettino,  Soveria  Mannelli,  2002.  

                                                                           Quando  il  verbo  si  fa  carne.  Linguaggio  e  natura  umana,  Bollati  Boringhieri,                    

                                                                           Torino,  2003  

 

LUDWIG  WITTGENSTEIN,  Tractatus  Logico-­‐Philosophicus.  Quaderni  1914-­‐1916,  trad.  it.,  Einaudi,    

                                                                                     Torino,  1979  

                                                                                                   Ricerche  filosofiche,  trad.it.,  Einaudi,  Torino,  1974