Top Banner
2.3 Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we beg in a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such an argument is valid. Consider the implication (p 1 p 2 p 3 p n )→q. The statements p 1 , p 2 , p 3 , … , p n are call ed the premises( 前前of the argument, and t he statement q is the conclusion for the arg ument.
69

2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Jan 03, 2016

Download

Documents

Arabella Watts
Welcome message from author
This document is posted to help you gain knowledge. Please leave a comment to let me know what you think about it! Share it to your friends and learn new things together.
Transcript
Page 1: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

2.3 Logical Implication: Rules of Inference

• From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such an argument is valid.

• Consider the implication

(p1p2p3 … pn)→q.

The statements p1, p2, p3, … , pn are called the premises( 前提) of the argument, and the statement q is the conclusion for the argument.

Page 2: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

推論證明

Page 3: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example 2.19: page 69.

Page 4: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.
Page 5: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example 2.20: page 70. • (we know that (p1p2)→q is a valid argument, and we may say

that the truth of the conclusion q is deduced or inferred from the truth of the premises p1, p2.)

Page 6: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Definition 2.4:

• If p, q are arbitrary statements such that p→q is a tautology, then we say that p logically implies q and we write pq to denote this situation. Note:

• 1) if p q, we have p q and q p. • 2) if p q and q p, then we have p q. • 3) p ≠> q is used to indicate that p→q is not a taut

ology – so the given implication (namely, p→q) is not a logical implication. (See the paragraphs from the bottom of page 70 to the top of page 71.)

Page 7: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example 2.21: page 71.

Page 8: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

• To prove the correctness of a statement, a great deal of the effort must put into constructing the truth tables. And since we want to avoid even larger tables, we are persuaded to develop a list of techniques called rules of inference that help us. (See the top paragraph of page 72.)

Page 9: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example 2.22: page 72. (the Rule of Detachment)

Page 10: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example 2.23: page 73. (the Law of the Syllogism)

Page 11: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example 2.24: page 74.

Page 12: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example 2.25: page 75. (Modus Tollens: method of denying)

Page 13: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.
Page 14: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example 2.26: page 76~77. (the Rule of Conjunction)

Page 15: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example 2.27: page 77

Page 16: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example 2.28: page 77~78. (the Rule of Contradiction)

Page 17: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Table 2.19: page 79. (Rules of Inference)

Page 18: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.
Page 19: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example 2.29: page 80

Page 20: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.
Page 21: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example 2.30

Page 22: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.
Page 23: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example 2.31: page 81~82.

Page 24: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.
Page 25: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example 2.32:page 82 反證法

Page 26: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

(p(q r)) ((p^q) r)

Page 27: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Note:

• [(p1p2p3 … pn) → (q→r)] [(p1p2p3 … pnq)→r]. (page 83)

Page 28: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example 2.33: page 84.

Page 29: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.
Page 30: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

2.4 The Use of Quantifiers

Page 31: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Open statement• Sentences that involve a variable, such as x, need not be

statements. • For example, the sentence "The number x + 2 is an even

integer" is not necessarily true or false unless we know what value is substituted for x.

• If we restrict our choices to integers, then when x is replaced by ‑5, ‑1, or 3, for instance, the resulting statement is false.

• In fact, it is false whenever x is replaced by an odd integer. • When an even integer is substituted for x, however, the

resulting statement is true.• We refer to the sentence "The number x + 2 is an even

integer" as an open statement, which we formally define as follows.

Page 32: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Definition 2.5:

• A declarative sentence is an open statement if – it contains one or more variables, and– it is not a statement, but– it becomes a statement when the variables in it are

replaced by certain allowable choices.

Page 33: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example:

• “The number x + 2 is an even integer” is an open statement and is denoted by p(x). The allowable choices for x is called the universe (set) for p(x). If x = 3, p(3) is a false statement.

Page 34: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example:

• “q(x,y): The numbers y + 2, x – y, and x + 2y are even integers.”, then q(4,2) is true.

• From the above examples, we can say for some x, p(x) (TRUE), for some x, y, q(x,y) (TRUE), or for all x, p(x) (FALSE).

Page 35: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Quantifiers

• Two types of quantifiers, which are called the existential and the universal quantifiers, can quantify the open statements p(x) and q(x,y).

• the existential quantifier (means “for some x”, “for at least one x”, or “there exists an x such that”): “for some x, p(x)” is denoted as “ x, p(x)”.

• the universal quantifier (means “for all x”, “for any x”, “for each x”, or “for every x”): “for all x, all y” is denoted by “x y”.

Page 36: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example 2.36: page 91.

Page 37: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

• Note: x p(x) x p(x), but x p(x) does not logically imply x p(x).

Page 38: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example 2.38: page 93

• (the truth value of a quantified statement may depend on the universe prescribed).

Page 39: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example 2.39: page 94.

Page 40: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Table 2.21 summarize and extend some results for quantifiers.

Page 41: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Definition 2.6:

• Let p(x), q(x) be open statements defined for a given universe. The open statements p(x) and q(x) are called (logically) equivalent, and we write x [p(x) q(x)] when the biconditional p(a) q(a) is true for each replacement a from the universe (that is, p(a) q(a) for each a in the universe).

• If the implication p(a) q(a) is true for each a in the universe (that is, p(a) q(a) for each a in the universe), then we write x [p(x) q(x)] and say that p(x) logically implies q(x).

Page 42: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Definition 2.7:

• For open statements p(x), q(x) – defined for a prescribed universe – and the universally quantified statement x [p(x) q(x)] we define:– The contrapositive of x [p(x) q(x)] to be x [q(x)

p(x)]. – The converse of x [p(x) q(x)] to be x [q(x) p

(x)]. – The inverse of x [p(x) q(x)] to be x [p(x) q

(x)].

Page 43: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example 2.40: page 95~96.

Page 44: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example 2.41: page 96~97.

Page 45: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.
Page 46: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example 2.42: page 97

Page 47: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

• (the existential quantifier x does not distribute over the logical connective ).

Page 48: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Table 2.22:

• Logical equivalences and logical implications for quantified statements in one variable.

Page 49: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example 2.43: page 98.

Page 50: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.
Page 51: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Table 2.23: Rules for negating statements with one quantifier.

Page 52: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example 2.45: page 100.

Page 53: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example 2.46: page 101.

Page 54: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example 2.47: page 101.

Page 55: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example 2.48: page 101

Page 56: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

2.5 Quantifiers, Definitions, and the Proofs of Theorems

• In this section we shall combine some of the ideas we have already studied in the prior two sections.

• The Rule of Universal Specification: If an open statement becomes true for all replacements by the members in a given universe, then that open statement is true for each specific individual member in that universe.

• (A bit more symbolically – if p(x) is an open statement for a given universe, and if x p(x) is true, then p(a) is true for each a in the universe.)

Page 57: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example 2.53: page 111.

Page 58: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

The Rule of Universal Generalization:

• If an open statement p(x) is proved to be true when x is replaced by any arbitrarily chosen element c from our universe, then the universally quantified statement x p(x) is true.

• Furthermore, the rule extends beyond a single variable. So if, for example, we have an open statement q(x,y) that is proved to be true when x and y are replaced by arbitrarily chosen elements from the same universe, or their own respective universes, then the universally quantified statement x y q(x, y) [or, x, y q(x, y)] is true. Similar results hold for the cases of three or more variables.

Page 59: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example 2.54: page 115.

Page 60: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example 2.55: page 116.

Page 61: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example 2.56: page 116~117.

Page 62: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.
Page 63: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

• The results of Example 2.54 and especially Example 2.56 lead us to believe that we can use universally quantified statements and the rules of inference – including the Rules of Universally Specification and Universal Generalization – to formalize and prove a variety of arguments and, hopefully, theorems.

Page 64: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example:

Page 65: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Definition 2.8,

Page 66: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Example 2.57 

Page 67: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Theorem 2.3

Page 68: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Theorem 2.4

Page 69: 2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.

Theorem 2.5