Top Banner

of 272

2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

Feb 16, 2018

Download

Documents

Cristian Mejias
Welcome message from author
This document is posted to help you gain knowledge. Please leave a comment to let me know what you think about it! Share it to your friends and learn new things together.
Transcript
  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    1/272

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    2/272

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    3/272

    Constitutions and Religious Freedom

    Many of us take for granted the idea that the right to religious

    freedom should be protected in a free, democratic polity. However,

    this book challenges whether the protection and privilege of

    religious belief and identity should be prioritized over other

    rights. By studying the effects of constitutional promises of

    religious freedom and establishment clauses, Frank B. Cross

    sets the stage for empirical questions that examine the conse-

    quences of such protections. Although the case for broader protec-

    tion is often made as a theoretical matter, constitutions generally

    protect freedom of religion. Allowing people full choice in holding

    religious beliefs or freedom of conscience is central to theirautonomy. Thus, freedom of religion is potentially a very valuable

    aspect of society, at least so long as it respects the freedom of

    individuals to be irreligious. This book tests these associations

    and nds that constitutions provide national religious protection,

    especially when the legal system is more sophisticated.

    Frank B. Cross holds a joint appointment as the Herbert

    D. Kelleher Centennial Professor of Business Law andProfessor of Law at the University of Texas. His scholarship

    traverses several elds, including descriptive and normative

    studies of judicial decision making, the economics of law and

    litigation, and traditional policy and doctrinal issues in admin-

    istrative and environmental law. Since 1998, he has published

    more than twenty articles in various publications, including the

    Yale Law Journal, Cornell Law Review, New York University

    Law Review, andColumbia Law Review.

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    4/272

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    5/272

    Comparative Constitutional Law and Policy

    Series Editors

    T O M G I N S B U R G ,University of Chicago

    Z A C H A R Y E L K I N S ,University of Texas at Austin

    R A N H I R S C H L ,University of Toronto

    Comparative constitutional law is an intellectually vibrant eld

    that encompasses an increasingly broad array of approaches and

    methodologies. This series collects analytically innovative and

    empirically grounded work from scholars of comparative consti-

    tutionalism across academic disciplines. Books in the series

    include theoretically informed studies of single constitutional

    jurisdictions, comparative studies of constitutional law and

    institutions, and edited collections of original essays that

    respond to challenging theoretical and empirical questions in

    the eld.

    Volumes in the Series

    Comparative Constitutional Designedited by T O M G I N S B U R G

    ( 2 0 1 2 )

    Consequential Courts: Judicial Roles in Global Perspective

    edited by D I A N A K A P I S Z E W S K I , G O R D O N S I L V E R S T E I N , A N D

    R O B E RT A . K A G A N ( 2 0 13 )

    Presidential Legislation in India: The Law and Practice of

    Ordinancesby S H U B H A N K A R D A M ( 2 0 1 4 )

    Constitutions in Authoritarian Regimesedited byT O M G I N S B U R G A N D A L B E R T O S I M P S E R ( 2 0 1 4 )

    Social Difference and Constitutionalism in Pan-Asiaedited by

    S U S A N H . W I L L I AM S ( 2 0 1 4 )

    Constitutionalism in Asia in the Early Twenty-First Century

    edited by A L B E R T C H E N ( 2 0 1 4 )

    Constitutions and Religious Freedomby F R A N K B . C R O S S ( 2 0 1 4 )

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    6/272

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    7/272

    Constitutions andReligious Freedom

    F R A N K B . C R O S S

    University of Texas

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    8/272

    32 Avenue of the Americas, New York, NY 10013-2473, USA

    Cambridge University Press is part of the University of Cambridge.It furthers the Universitys mission by disseminating knowledge in the pursuit ofeducation, learning, and research at the highest international levels of excellence.

    www.cambridge.orgInformation on this title:www.cambridge.org/9781107041448

    Frank B. Cross 2015

    This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exceptionand to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements,no reproduction of any part may take place without the written

    permission of Cambridge University Press.

    First published 2015

    Printed in the United States of America

    A catalog record for this publication is available from the British Library.

    Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication DataCross, Frank B., author.Constitutions and religious freedom/Frank B. Cross.

    pages cm. (Comparative constitutional law and policy)ISBN 978-1-107-04144-8 (hardback)1. Freedom of religion. 2. Freedom of religion Socialaspects. 3. Constitutional law. I. Title.K3258.C76 2014342.08052dc23 2014001850

    ISBN 978-1-107-04144-8 Hardback

    Cambridge University Press has no responsibility for the persistence or accuracy ofURLs for external or third-party Internet Web sites referred to in this publicationand does not guarantee that any content on such Web sites is, or will remain,accurate or appropriate.

    http://www.cambridge.org/http://www.cambridge.org/9781107041448http://www.cambridge.org/9781107041448http://www.cambridge.org/
  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    9/272

    Contents

    Foreword by Zachary Elkins pageix

    1 Why Freedom of Religion? 1

    2 Religious Freedom Around the World 34

    3 Measuring Religious Freedom 58

    4 Social Factors and Religious Freedom 78

    5 Constitutions and Religious Freedom 105

    6 The Constitutional Protection of Religious Freedom 153

    7 Religious Freedom and Society 185

    Bibliography 209

    Index 235

    vii

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    10/272

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    11/272

    Foreword

    Frank B. Cross is known for his straightforward and direct approach

    to big questions, and this book is no exception. Indeed, this book

    launches a frontal attack on not one, but a series of weighty questions

    that have likely intimidated less ambitious scholars. In so doing, he

    unsettles conventional wisdom and opens productive avenues into

    the study of constitutions and religion that we will be traversing for

    years to come.

    Many of us take for granted the idea that the right to religious

    freedom should be protected in a free, democratic polity. Not Cross,

    who wonders why we would protect and privilege a religious basis for

    beliefs and identity over any other. Crosss questions startle: Of how

    much social or material value is religious freedom, really? This is a

    provocative and arresting beginning, and it sets the stage for a set of

    empirical questions that he answers clearly and succinctly in subse-quent chapters.

    The empirical chapters unfold in a highly methodical and organ-

    ized fashion as he builds the scaffolding for his core question: Does

    religious freedom, once it is promised in higher law, yield real de facto

    freedom? This question has been at the heart of constitutional anal-

    ysis at least since James Madisons concern about mere parchment

    barriers. Cross is highly adept and resourceful in his analysis of

    relevant data on the question. He leads us through the meaning ofreligious freedom which we may have thought we knew and picks

    ix

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    12/272

    apart its various manifestations and observable attributes. In the

    end, the question is whether constitutional guarantees enhance reli-

    gious freedom over and above a set of other predictors such as the

    countrys prevailing religion, its relative level of democracy, its rule of

    law, and its per capita GDP. I know Crosss answer here, but there is

    no reason to spoil the ending.

    For those new to the intersection of religion and constitutional-

    ism, Crosss book is a comprehensive and discerning guide. The sad

    reality of scholarship is that many authors, because of either impa-

    tience or arrogance, read the existing scholarship with just enough

    attention to launch an idea. Cross, by contrast, seems to have dev-oured the last thirty years of empirical and theoretical work on the

    topic with gusto, and has left behind a beautifully curated tour that is

    anything but narrow and supercial. This is a book that requires a

    pencil for marginalia and, perhaps, a credit card or a library card

    handy: Cross leaves no question about where to go for further reading

    and provides ample inspiration for such.

    Zachary Elkins, co-editorCambridge Comparative Law and Policy series

    x

    Foreword

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    13/272

    1Why Freedom of Religion?

    Although freedom of religion is often presumed, its protection isheavily disputed. Why should freedom of religion be constitution-ally protected when other freedoms are not? Why not protect a

    broader freedom of conscience, which would shelter the religious

    and the nonbelievers? Although the case for broader protection is

    often made as a theoretical matter, constitutions generally protect

    freedom of religion. This book examines the consequences of such

    protections.

    The original U.S. Constitution did not contain a guarantee of

    freedom of religion, but such constitutional protection was soon pro-

    vided in the Bill of Rights. The constitutional protection was placed

    alongside freedom of speech in the very rst amendment, ahead of

    property rights, the rights of criminal defendants, and other matters.

    As such, freedom of religion is considered foundational to Americans.

    Special respect for religious freedom is not unique to Americans.

    Freedom of religion is widely protected by international law

    (Scolnicov2011). The 1976 United Nations International Covenant

    on Civil and Political Rights declared that everyone should have the

    right to freedom of religion. The 1981 United Nations Declaration onthe Elimination of All Forms of Intolerance and of Discrimination

    1

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    14/272

    Based on Religion or Belief proclaimed that religion or belief is

    one of the fundamental elements in . . . [a persons] conception of

    life that should be fully respected and guaranteed. It proceeds to

    lay out particular elements to be protected.

    Few ask why religious freedom should be guaranteed constitu-

    tionally, but the question is a relevant one. It may be that religion is

    undeserving of special constitutional protection. Even if we deem

    freedom of religion to be worthy of such exalted status, the purpose

    of such protection should be relevant to the manner in which such a

    constitutional provision is interpreted and applied.

    At the threshold one might want to dene religion, so as to knowwhat freedoms are protected. The denitional question has proven to

    be a challenge. Neither social science nor law has settled upon a clear

    denition. Many denitions erect a canopy so large that atheism and

    most college sororities would qualify as religions(Grim2004, 78).

    Asad (1993) contends that there can be no universal denition of

    religion.

    Leiter (2010) argues that religion has certain unique characteris-

    tics, such as the issuance of categorical (nonconsequentialist) demandson action and a reliance on faith, rather than reason or evidence,

    for beliefs. Feofanov (1994) employs a similar denition, as do many

    others. The most common denition typically relies upon a belief in the

    sacred or supernatural as fundamental, though some groups, such as

    Buddhists, have an ambiguous belief in the supernatural.

    Koppelman (2010) takes issue with Leiters denition but con-

    cedes that no denition of religion works very well. Much like pornog-

    raphy, he suggests that the denition of religion is simply that [w]e

    know it when we see it (Koppelman2010, 976). If religion is to be

    protected (or limited), though, it must be dened. Some contend that

    prevailing denitions have produced only a mess or a quagmire

    (Feofanov1994). But denition is dangerous. It risks excluding true

    beliefs as not qualifying as religious. Sullivan (2006, 924) contends

    that religion cannot be dened in such a way that it can be legally

    protected and maintained as separate.

    There may be no good denition of religion, but Sullivans view is

    too gloomy, and the difculty need not be a serious problem. Disputestend to arise only at the boundary. Thus, Europeans debate whether

    2

    Constitutions and Religious Freedom

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    15/272

    Scientology should be considered a religion or a cult. While this may

    be important very important to some the vast majority of religious

    freedom issues are not such boundary problems, so a precise deni-

    tion is unnecessary for a general assessment of global freedom of

    religion. Lupu (1996, 358) notes that the combination of cultural

    pluralism, pragmatism, and experience suggests that the deni-

    tional problem is not great, as we have conventional understandings

    of what constitutes religion.

    The Justication for Protecting Religious Freedom

    The right to choose ones religion is a constitutional protection not

    offered to other individual choices. There is no constitutional right

    to choose what one eats, for example, though that is undeniably

    important to people. Religion is an important area of individual

    autonomy, but so are choices of dress or vocation or countless other

    areas of personal autonomy. The privileged status of religion in

    constitutions may fairly be questioned. This is especially truewhen religious freedom appears to conict with other freedoms,

    such as gender rights.

    Brian Leiter is a legal philosopher and academic who has ques-

    tioned the reason for privileging religion. He claims that no one has

    offered a credible principled argument for tolerating religion itself, as

    opposed to other personal choices. While there are ample philosoph-

    ical justications for tolerating personal differences, he says that

    religion may not be so special as to warrant a specic constitutional

    protection. He suggests that there is no principled reason for consti-

    tutions to single out religion for special legal protection.

    While Leiter is especially vigorous in pursuing the point, he is

    not alone in the theory. Ronald Dworkin (1986) basically agrees.

    Christopher Eisgruber and Lawrence Sager (2007, 6) argue for

    equal liberty which denies that religion is a category of human

    experience that demands special benets and/or necessitates special

    restrictions. They suggest that any deeply held concern of persons

    should be given equal regard, though they recognize that the historyof religious violence might cause constitutions to single it out.

    3

    Why Freedom of Religion?

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    16/272

    Religion may be no more important to a person s conception of

    who she is than other terms based on such diverse factors as personal

    relationships (mother, sister) profession (engineer, lawyer), race

    (Hispanic, Native American), political afliation (Republican,

    Libertarian), special skills (violinist, gardner), socioeconomic status

    (yuppie, homeless), residence (New Yorker, Westerner), or individual

    habits, tastes activities, interests, or loyalties (vegetarian, Cubs fan)

    (Smith1991, 203). Religion would not be the primary identier for

    many and does not plainly merit special status. Some argue that

    religious belief cannot be qualitatively distinguished from other

    belief systems in a way that justies special constitutional consider-ation (Marshall1991, 320321). Yet others arguing to the contrary

    contend that religion is of unique importance to people (Greenawalt

    2008).

    Leiter would not deny all legal recognition to religion. But he

    suggests that it merits tolerance rather than respect. As a conse-

    quence, religious freedom should be more readily compromised

    when it conicts with other societal interests. Hamilton (2005), mak-

    ing a similar argument, notes that religion is not a particular goodand that religious groups should not be generally exempted from

    secular laws. This notion is related to a concept known asproportion-

    ality, which will be discussed later in the book.

    Some disagree with Leiter. They contend that religion is special

    and more than simply a peculiarly form of freedom of speech and

    assembly, privacy, and autonomy (Witte 2005, 250). Perhaps reli-

    gion is a uniquely important aspect of human autonomy. It has been

    called a dening feature of the human personality(Boyle & Sheen

    1997, 11). For many, religion is simply more important than other

    aspects of personal life (Greenawalt 2008). Traditionally, religious

    beliefs have been considered important enough to die for, to suffer

    for, to rebel for, to emigrate for, toght to control the government for

    (Laycock1996, 317). Other choices have not seen this response.

    Religion could thus be justied as a matter of degree if not of kind.

    The choice of a theoretically organizing principle for ones life may

    transcend ones choice of food or clothing or other common individual

    daily choices (Eisgruber & Sager1994). Thomas Jefferson declaredthat the constitutional freedom of religion was the most inalienable

    4

    Constitutions and Religious Freedom

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    17/272

    and sacred of all human rights(Smith1991). Beliefs about religion

    are often of extraordinary importance to the individual (Laycock

    2011, 951). Religious goods may be distinctive ones, more important

    than other material matters.

    Finnis (2009) contends that religion is special in its direction of

    truths about humanity and the world. Religious freedom has long

    been justied a sa unique source of individual and personal identity

    (Witte2005, 250). But religion itself is not truly so unique as such a

    source of personal identity. Many people have no religious belief, but

    they are not without individual and personal identities; they simply

    nd their identities in other sources, which may be constitutionallyprotected. Secularists have their own moral beliefs. One may nd

    ones personal identity in a theory such as Marxism or even racism,

    for example, which is not generally considered a religion. Leiter notes

    that religion is not grounded in reason so much as in faith, and that

    religion has certainly been a source of societal bads throughout

    history. Desmond Tutu (1996, xv) has declared that religion should

    produce peace, reconciliation, tolerance, and respect for human rights

    but it has often promoted the opposite conditions.

    As such, religionmight not merit special protection.

    The Historical Case for Freedom of Religion

    The historical case for singling out religion for constitutional protec-

    tion may be simply a pragmatic one. History has shown that religion

    has been a powerful force in the broad oppression of individuals,

    singling them out for death, among other sanctions. Perhaps we

    protect religious freedom merely because religious oppression has

    historically been a force of great harm and strife (Garvey 1996a).

    Throughout history, governmental attempts to suppress religious

    views had caused vast human suffering (Laycock 1996, 317).

    Because religious beliefs are so deeply felt, they lead to a particular

    risk of conict (Lupu1996). It is not accidental that religion is the

    oldest human right to be internationally recognized (Venter 2010).

    Historically, religion is more likely to be a ground of persecution(Nussbaum2008, 165). Over two hundred million persons have been

    5

    Why Freedom of Religion?

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    18/272

    killed due to their religious afliations throughout recorded history

    (Barrett & Johnson 2001). The same cannot be said about other

    personal choices, such as food and clothing. Most people are familiar

    with this history, and it is beyond the scope of this book to engage in a

    historical tour de force of oppression in the name of religion, but I will

    undertake a brief review.

    The classic case of religious oppression is probably that of the

    Spanish Inquisition of the fteenth century. At the outset, the

    Inquisition was an attempt to drive out Christian heretics, but it

    soon turned to the Jews, among others. Jews were arrested and

    tried, and hundreds or thousands were burned at the stake. Somewere tortured. Many had their wealth conscated, and large numbers

    ed Europe to avoid oppression. The Inquisition is a dramatic story of

    the consequences of a lack of religious freedom, but there are others.

    Pogroms against the Jewish religion are unfortunately common

    throughout the history of the Middle East and Europe. Russia has

    seen a series of anti-Jewish pogroms over the past two centuries.

    Religious oppression arguably came to a head with Nazi

    Germany. The Holocaust saw the execution of millions of Jews, forno reason other than their religious faith. Before the killings, though,

    there was a steady pattern of persecution. The Nuremberg laws of

    1935 prohibited, among other things, intermarriage among Jews and

    Christians. Jews were denied the right to vote and hold ofce. Jews

    were required to wear yellow badges when out and were conned to

    ghettoes. The oppression steadily escalated, of course, ultimately

    leading to death camps.

    Historic religious oppression continues to this day, often unrecog-

    nized. In 19992001, inter-religious violence in Indonesia caused

    thousands of deaths and hundreds of thousands of internally dis-

    placed persons (Sidel2006). The nation of India has seen spasms of

    violence directed at Muslims and Sikhs. Hindus, in turn, have suf-

    fered at the hands of Islamists. The former nation of Yugoslavia

    saw a civil war resulting from violence among Catholics, the

    Orthodox Christians, and Muslims. Islamic nations today engage in

    various acts to repress the beliefs of Christians, Jews, and disfavored

    Islamic sects. Various nations in Africa are seeing a struggle betweenMuslims and Christians.

    6

    Constitutions and Religious Freedom

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    19/272

    Marty (1996, 2) suggests that the monstrous totalitarian systems

    of the twentieth century, be they Fascist, Nazi, Communist, Maoist, or

    whatever, set out to suppress rights, beginning with those of religious

    people. If in earlier times, it was more typical for one religion to

    repress others, a more recent phenomenon is that of irreligious

    autocrats repressing religious believers. Because of the strong inuence

    of religion on people and the potentially subversive organizing role of

    churches, the suppression of religious freedom may be particularly vital

    for would-be autocrats. Thus, religious freedom may be uniquely impor-

    tant to humans. One suspects that few would have suffered torture and

    death in order to continue their eating habits, unlike their religiousbeliefs. The Pilgrims ed across a dangerous North Atlantic to a dan-

    gerous American wilderness to avoid an ofcial church and religious

    persecution. It has been said that tolerance has been particularly

    difcult to achieve in the sphere of religion (McClosky & Brill 1983,

    103). Laycock (2011, 951) suggests that it was uncontroversial to claim

    that attempts to suppress dissenting religious views had caused vast

    human suffering and social conict.

    Historically, the struggle for religious freedom has also been partof the ght for freedom more generally. There is a reason why free-

    dom of religion, along with speech, is found in the very rst amend-

    ment to the U.S. Constitution. In the eighteenth century, as in

    preceding centuries, the efforts to gain religious liberty were central

    to the struggles for freedom of belief, paving the way, by argument

    and physical resistance, for the later struggles for democratic rights

    in general (McClosky & Brill 1983, 103). Religious freedom was

    central to Enlightenment recognition of individual freedom

    (Scolnicov2011).

    In addition, religious disagreement has been a common source of

    conict and death. Muslims and Christians today battle in Nigeria

    and other African nations. Conict has occurred even within broadly

    dened religions. Protestants and Catholics fought a virtual civil war

    within Ireland. And, as I write this book, Sunnis and Shiites are

    engaged in a similar conict in the Middle East. Can freedom of

    religious belief can help prevent such conict?

    Indeed, empirical evidence reveals that religious freedom pro-motes peace. The restriction of religious freedom correlates positively

    7

    Why Freedom of Religion?

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    20/272

    with involvement in armed conict (Grim 2004). Religion is tradition-

    ally a source of conict, which obviously continues in the present era.

    And religious conicts may be more intractable, given the devoutness

    of believers. McClosky and Brill (1983, 103) suggest that tolerance

    has been particularly difcult to achieve in the sphere of religion.

    The historical case of freedom of religion depends on contingency,

    however. While religion has been used as a source of severe oppres-

    sion in the past, this need not be so in the future. Some nations

    (though certainly not all) appear to have transcended religious

    oppression. Constitutional rights are not generally grounded in

    historical accidents. And it may be, as later evidence in this bookwill show, that legal protection of religion is unnecessary to protect

    against such oppression of individuals. Such oppression has typically

    occurred in autocracies. Perhaps democratic governance provides

    sufcient shelter for religious freedom, so constitutional protections

    are simply superuous. In addition, the historical case does not

    counsel universal religious freedom. A very small minority group

    does not likely threaten strife, and fear of violence does not necessa-

    rily argue against its oppression.

    Is Religion a Particular Good?

    Religion might be specially singled out for protection simply because

    it is uniquely important (Engel2011). Smith (1991, 149) argues that

    the religious justication is also the most satisfying, and

    perhaps the only adequate justication for a special constitutional

    commitment to religious liberty. Conkle (2011) suggests that

    religious belief may be the only truly robust foundation for religious

    libertys protection. For a believer, religion is quite important,

    probably the most important choice of his or her life. For many,

    eternity is at stake, which places religious choice considerably

    above other individual preferences in terms of importance.

    The importance of religion can be a double-edged sword,

    however. If religious belief is such an enormous transcendental

    decision, it becomes all too easy for a person to want to impose hisor her particular beliefs on others, to save their souls. The strong

    8

    Constitutions and Religious Freedom

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    21/272

    moral belief that slavery is wrong commonly prevents people from

    choosing to practice human slavery. Likewise, a strong moral belief in

    the truth of ones religion, and the falsity of others, can readily lead to

    a decision prohibiting the following of the beliefs perceived to be false,

    which could condemn a soul to eternal damnation. Thus, the extreme

    importance of religious belief to many could easily form an argument

    against religious freedom, so that the true religion might be

    imposed on the people. History shows this tendency to be the case,

    from the Catholic Church of centuries past to Islam in some contem-

    porary societies.

    A separate case for religious freedom might be found in the claimthat religious belief in general is pragmatically an afrmative good to

    be encouraged by the state, without the states embracing any partic-

    ular religious belief. This position does not rely on any intrinsic

    philosophical value of religion; it merely contends that a peoples

    religious faith, in whatever religion, is good for those people and for

    society as a whole. Some have argued that, without religious belief to

    keep them in check, people will regress to a state of immorality.

    Dostoyevsky (1990, 589) warned that . . .

    without god. . .

    everythingis permitted. Garvey (1996b, 49) argues that the best reasons for

    protecting religious freedom rest on the assumption that religion is a

    good thing. Smith (1991) suggests that this was the foundation of

    the First Amendment right. Religious belief, whether true or not,

    could have functional value for a society.

    Some conservative constitutional scholars have argued that the

    American First Amendment should be interpreted only to protect

    against discrimination among religious sects, while allowing govern-

    ment favoritism toward religion generally. Religion in general argu-

    ably should be encouraged. This actually parallels the law of freedom

    of speech. Government is free to encourage speech as a broad matter

    but to prohibit discrimination over the particular content of speech.

    At rst blush, the thesis that religion is good for society might

    argue against religious freedom. It might seem that, rather than

    religious freedom, the best way to promote religious belief in a society

    would be through the adoption of a compulsory and subsidized state

    religion, to which all citizens must belong. King Louis XIV compelledthe inhabitants of Paris to attend mass or go to jail, which might

    9

    Why Freedom of Religion?

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    22/272

    seem an effective way of increasing religiosity. In 1646, Thomas

    Edwards wrote that religious toleration was the greatest of all

    evils because it would bring skepticism in doctrine and looseness of

    life, then atheism (Porter 2000, 105). But this position reects a

    nave vision of the role and power of government in society.

    Greater religious belief may have various practical benets for a

    society, calling for its encouragement. Economists have mused on the

    effects of religion, and Max Weber (1930) famously argued that

    Protestantism brought with it personal characteristics that fostered

    capitalist economic growth. Webers theory is generally not supported

    by research (Iannaccone1998); nevertheless, it is plausible that reli-gious belief could have economic consequences, as certain faiths may

    encourage traits such as honesty, work ethic, and thrift

    (McCleary & Barro2006a). Attitudinal studies have found that reli-

    gion appears to be good for the development of attitudes that are

    conducive to economic growth (Guiso, Sapienza, & Zingales2003).

    Societies with freedom of religion may encourage entrepreneur-

    ship, while [c]losed religious systems foul economic development and

    stunt growth

    (Malloch2008, 51). Conversely, resources devoted toreligion may be drawn from economically more productive activities,

    so greater religiosity might have negative economic effects. Some

    religious practices, such as prohibitions on consumption of certain

    products, cannot help the economy. In addition, the social activities

    common to religions may facilitate networks that are useful for eco-

    nomic purposes.

    McCleary and Barro (2006a) studied the association of religious

    belief and economic well-being. They found that greater levels of

    religious belief were associated with statistically signicant positive

    effects on economic growth, while higher levels of church attendance

    were associated with statistically signicant negative effects on eco-

    nomic growth. Of course, belief and attendance were associated, with

    the results separated out in a multiple regression. So the results

    mean that greater religious attendance was negative when levels of

    belief were held constant, not that greater religious attendance was a

    per se negative. Still, the results suggest that religious belief is good

    for economic growth and that more devout belief (as expressed inmore frequent religious attendance) can undermine this effect. The

    10

    Constitutions and Religious Freedom

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    23/272

    authors took statistical steps to show that they had found an effect of

    religion on growth, not one of growth on religion. The evidence on

    religious belief and economic growth provides at least some mild

    grounds for encouraging religion.

    Durlauf, Kourtellos & Tan (2005) have criticized these results.

    They reestimated the study with different control variables and

    found that none of the religiosity variables were statistically signi-

    cant at the 0.05 level. The authors conceded that religion was poten-

    tially relevant to growth but argued that there was no evidence to

    suggest that any such effect was quantitatively important. The set of

    countries studied by Durlauf et al. was relatively small, though.Various studies have considered the association of particular

    faiths with economic growth, but their results are quite conicted.

    Some research has shown that Islamic belief is associated with eco-

    nomic growth. Others have reached different conclusions for Islam

    while nding a positive effect for Orthodox Christianity. The pre-

    sumed positive effect of Protestantism has generally not appeared.

    A study within the United States found that Judaism and nonfunda-

    mentalist Protestantism were associated with higher income, whileCatholicism and fundamentalist Protestantism were not (Heath,

    Waters, & Waston 1995). The research on religious belief and the

    economy is inconclusive, though there may be some positive effect.

    Beyond the economy, religion may have a variety of positive

    societal effects on the lives of believers. Religion is said to inculcate

    in citizens the moral character necessary to a democratic society

    (Smith1991, 199). Religious belief has been shown to increase altru-

    istic behavior. For a Randian, this might not be such a positive, but

    most Americans consider charitable giving a very good thing. And the

    religious are more charitable. Brooks (2003, 41) found that religious

    people are 25 percent more likely to donate money and 23 percent

    more likely to volunteer their time in charitable work. The differences

    attributable to religion were strong even after using controls on

    ideology and income. Moreover, the religious were much more likely

    to give to nonreligious charities. Grim (2009) found a positive effect of

    religious freedom on numerous measures of social well-being.

    The greater generosity of religious groups may be due to thecommands of their religions to be generous. They may feel a moral

    11

    Why Freedom of Religion?

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    24/272

    obligation to be generous to the needy. Or perhaps this is a character-

    istic of group formation. Because religion is a community of sorts, the

    religious may be more communitarian in orientation and hence more

    likely to give. This is consistent with evidence that the religious are

    more likely to participate in all sorts of voluntary associations (Smidt

    2008). Thus, an atheist has suggested that [m]ore than any other

    institution, religion deserves our appreciation and respect because it

    has persistently encouraged people to care deeply for the self, for

    neighbors, for humanity, and for the natural world and to strive for

    the highest ideals humans are able to envision (Sheiman 2009, ixx).

    The greater civic engagement of the religious may contributevaluable social capital to a society. It is religious life that purportedly

    makes basic forms of civility and social restraint possible (Smidt,

    1999, 176). At least the outwardly oriented religious groups foster

    the growth of bridging social capital by motivating their members to

    give and volunteer beyond their own communities of belief, through

    inclusiveness that brings together socially, economically, and ethni-

    cally diverse communities(Brooks2005, 167). Such social capital is

    generally considered a valuable feature of a society.Social capital is commonly used as a general term for mutual

    trust and cooperation in a society. Putnam (2000, 319) argues that

    when trust and social networks ourish, individuals, rms, neigh-

    borhoods, and even nations prosper. Greater social capital is asso-

    ciated with many goods, including economic growth, social order, and

    health (Cross2005). Religion offers regular opportunities for social

    activity and interaction and so provides fertile terrain for the culti-

    vation of friendships (Sherkat & Ellison 1999, 373). Members of

    religious congregations are also more likely than nonmembers to

    belong to a diverse range of voluntary organizations and to show

    higher levels of social trust (Norris & Inglehart2004).

    By fostering such social connections and contacts and facilitating

    organizational abilities, churches might be expected to enhance

    social participation outside the churches, an effect that has been

    well documented (Peterson 1992). An investigation of the United

    States and Canada found that religious tradition and church

    attendance played an important role in fostering involvement incivil society (Smidt 1999, 176). People develop greater secular

    12

    Constitutions and Religious Freedom

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    25/272

    volunteering activities from religious community sources (Schwadel

    2005). African American churches have been found to be vital sour-

    ces of collective self-help and community development, moral reform,

    social service delivery, community leadership, and political mobiliza-

    tion (Sherkat & Ellison 1999, 375). An international study found

    that for all beliefs, a higher attendance at religious services was

    associated with higher levels of trust (Guiso, Sapienza, & Zingales

    2003). Religion is not a necessary condition for altruism or social

    capital, but it appears to provide a net increase, fostering social

    connectedness. Hence, greater religious belief may offer a broad

    benet to society generally. Smidt (2008) documents how the morereligious seem to have a greater civic morality on matters such as not

    evading taxes.

    Religious belief may also offer benets for individual believers.

    A study of black male youth found that church attendance favorably

    affected their school attendance and work activity and reduced the

    level of socially deviant activity (Freeman1986). Studies show that

    crime rates are negatively associated with religious membership (Lee

    2006, Bainbridge 1989). Iannaccone (1998) summarizes various stud-ies indicating that religion tends to reduce various deviant behaviors,

    including divorce, drug and alcohol abuse, and suicide. It is difcult to

    establish causality here. It may well be that those who are genetically

    predisposed to engage in deviant behaviors are simultaneously pre-

    disposed not to be religious. But still, the association means some-

    thing, as those with positive attributes commonly choose religion.

    Religious belief appears to be positively associated with higher

    levels of personal life satisfaction. A large study in Europe, using

    numerous factors that could affect personal attitudes found that

    greater religiosity had a statistically signicant association with

    greater life satisfaction (Greene & Yoon 2004). An earlier study in

    the United States reached similar conclusions (Ellison1991), report-

    ing that the religious consistently showed higher levels of life satis-

    faction, greater personal happiness, and fewer negative psychosocial

    consequences of traumatic life events. This is generally true for differ-

    ent religions (Cohen2002).

    Elliott and Hayward (2009) studied the interaction of religion,government regulation, and life satisfaction. Both religious belief and

    13

    Why Freedom of Religion?

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    26/272

    personal freedom tend to be associated with greater happiness or

    satisfaction. The study also found that the association between

    church attendance and life satisfaction actually changes from pos-

    itive to negative as government regulation increases (Elliott &

    Hayward 2009, 301). A study in Sweden found that religious belief

    was associated with fewer divorces, fewer children born out of wed-

    lock, and less nonpayment of debt (Berggren1997).

    Religious belief is also positively associated with mental health.

    One study reported that those diagnosed as mentally ill were far less

    likely to attend church (Stark 1971). Religion may be valuable in

    helping humans cope with stress and suffering and may psychologi-cally benet the believer. From a Freudian perspective, religion may

    offer people a tool to control the inherent natural destructiveness of

    their innate impulses. The evidence is not conclusive, and the reli-

    gious may suffer different problems, but it appears that this may

    offers another benet of belief (Ellison1998).

    Religion may also offer benets in physical health. Religious

    belief appears to make alcohol abuse less likely (Koenig, George,

    Meador, & Blazer 1994). Iannaccone (1998) reports that hundredsof epidemiological studies, with precautions taken to avoid spurious

    correlations, have consistently found that religious belief was asso-

    ciated with a variety of health benets, physical and mental. These

    effects may come from discouragement of unhealthy behavior, com-

    munity support, or the enhancement of self-esteem and personal

    efcacy (Sherkat & Ellison 1999). Some caution is required, as the

    research does not use the sort of controlled tests employed in medi-

    cine, but the sheer bulk of the research provides strong evidence that

    religion may be benecial. The evidence generally indicates that

    religion is broadly benecial for the individual, and that this relation-

    ship holds up across a variety of measures both of religion and of well-

    being (Elliott & Hayward 2009, 285). Hummer, Rogers, Nam, &

    Ellison (1999) report that religious belief in the United States is

    associated with lower mortality. Studies throughout the world have

    found that religious participation, including activities such as prayer

    and meditation, are associated with greater human well-being.

    Overall, the research is clear that greater religiosity is generallybenecial for human health and well-being (Lehrer 2004a). Even

    14

    Constitutions and Religious Freedom

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    27/272

    defenders of atheism acknowledge that the research shows religiosity

    to be associated with greater life satisfaction and psychological

    well-being (Zuckerman2009).

    Most of the research on the potential individual benets of reli-

    gion has been conducted in the United States, but the association

    does not appear to be limited to this country. A study of Venezuelan

    evangelicals indicated that religion could be a means to overcome

    addiction, violence, and other personal and social difculties (Smilde

    2005). And the global association of religious belief with greater life

    satisfaction demonstrates that the effect is not one unique to

    America.One difculty with the study of the individual benets of reli-

    gious belief, though, lies in a selection problem. These studies are

    not clinical tests in which individuals are assigned to religious

    beliefs or nonbelief. It may be that those who would benet from

    religion choose religion, while those who do not choose religion

    would draw no benets from faith. Or some unrelated third factor

    might explain the correlations. Perhaps some underlying environ-

    mental or even genetic factor tends to yield both religious belief andcharitable action. If so, religious belief is not a cause of charity.

    These are only possibilities, though, and the general association of

    religious belief and human welfare, for some at least, suggests the

    benets of belief. Freeman (1986, 373) addresses the difculty of

    establishing causality but argues that the pattern of statistical

    results suggests that at least some part of the churchgoing effect is

    the result of actual causal impact.

    Economics of Religion

    There is a growing movement viewing religion in economic terms. In

    this context, competition is productive. A single, state-directed reli-

    gion, by contrast, would be inefcient and ineffective. The state can

    compel attendance at religious functions, but it cannot compel belief.

    A state-controlled religion may cause stagnation such that it produ-

    ces less belief in the state religion than would exist if it were not thestate religion (Iannaccone, Finke, & Stark1997).

    15

    Why Freedom of Religion?

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    28/272

    An ofcial state church is in a monopoly position. Economics

    teaches us that monopolies have a tendency to take excess prots

    and underproduce goods or services, while becoming stagnant due to

    a lack of competition. A state church needs to make fewer efforts to

    appeal to people, and religion becomes intertwined with the state itself,

    causing resentment (Fox 2008a). Gill (1999) reported that the dominant

    Latin American Catholic Church serviced the wealthy and neglected

    the poor. These negatives do not require a formal state church, as any

    market power, such as could come from government favoritism, would

    have a similar, if lesser, effect. Adam Smith thus argued that religious

    freedom would produce religious competition, which would generategreater religious activity and produce higher-quality religious services,

    just as in any other market. The competition generates religious prod-

    uctsthat are high in quality and well-aligned with individual prefer-

    ences(McCleary & Barro2006a, 50).

    In addition, diversity by itself should promote religious belief.

    Just as different people prefer different products, they might be

    expected to prefer different religious beliefs. A creed that is more

    accepting of womens rights might be expected to attract morewomen. Some people are more conservative and traditional and

    would prefer such values in their religious doctrine, whereas others

    might prefer the opposite. A single religion with dened beliefs will be

    less able to adapt to different personal preferences than will a variety

    of different religions with distinct belief systems.

    There is evidence to support this hypothesis. A study of early

    twentieth-century America found that cities with higher rates of

    religious diversity had higher rates of religious afliation and prac-

    tice (Finke & Stark1988). Stark and McCann (1993) found that the

    religious activity of Catholics was greater in regions where they

    represented a smaller fraction of the population. An empirical anal-

    ysis of answers on the World Values Survey found that religious

    pluralism was associated with religious belief (McCleary & Barro

    2006a). It is also positively associated with monthly church attend-

    ance and belief in heaven and hell (Barro & McCleary2003a).

    North and Gwin (2004) used U.S. State Department reports to

    dene the level of religious freedom in various countries. The authorsfound that an ofcial state religion, registration requirements, and

    16

    Constitutions and Religious Freedom

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    29/272

    other scales of restrictions on religious freedom consistently associ-

    ated negatively with religious attendance. This is consistent with the

    nding that greater government entanglement with religion,

    whether aimed positively or negatively, tends to undermine popular

    religiosity.

    The association between pluralism and religious participation

    seems a logical one, but it is still sometimes disputed. Breault

    (1989) reanalyzed some of the results of Finke and Stark and found

    that including consideration of Catholic population made the rela-

    tionship disappear. However, because Catholicism is a religion, the

    ndings do not necessarily refute the hypothesis, absent evidence ofidentical Catholic participation in the presence of greater pluralism.

    Internationally, many nations without pluralism have higher levels

    of faith-based behavior (Norris & Inglehart2004).

    Gill (1999) examined the growth of Protestantism in Latin

    American countries that were traditionally Catholic. He tested the

    theory that religious freedom would be associated with increased

    religious diversity and participation in twenty nations. Using an

    index of state religious regulation for these countries, he consistentlyfound strong statistical associations between religious freedom and

    broader religiosity.

    Some research nds that the existence of a state religion is

    associated with lower rates of church attendance (Chaves & Cann

    1992), though other research reaches the opposite conclusion

    (Barro & McCleary 2003a). Highly regulated religious economies,

    via state religions or subsidies, have been associated with reduced

    religious participation in Western Europe (Stark & Iannaccone

    1994, Barro & McCleary2003a). These studies do not show causa-

    tion, and some evidence suggests that pluralism does not itself

    promote participation (Chaves & Gorski2001). There is some evi-

    dence to support the theory that religious pluralism encourages

    greater religious belief. In general, there is a correlation between

    rates of religious diversity and overall religious participation

    (Iannaccone1998).

    A mathematical problem arose with much of this research, how-

    ever, deriving from the calculation of diversity. For example, Voas,Olson, and Crockett (2002) demonstrated that, depending on the size

    17

    Why Freedom of Religion?

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    30/272

    distributions of religious denominations, there was likely to be a

    statistically signicant positive association, even when pluralism

    has no effect on participation. The authors reviewed several large

    past datasets to show this effect.

    Not all studies have used the pluralism variable that these

    authors found debatable. For example, Fox and Tabory (2008)

    studied the effects of state regulation of religion on religious partic-

    ipation and belief. They found that countries with greater levels of

    separation of church and state tended to have higher levels of reli-

    giosity. Practice was affected relatively more than belief, but the

    results conrmed the preceding economic hypothesis.Less rigorous historical evidence also conrms the economic

    hypothesis. In America the deregulation of religion in the First

    Amendment increased the level of religious competition and mobili-

    zation and produced dramatic increases in church adherence (Finke

    1990, 623). This nations eforescence of religious pluralism and

    belief may thus be traceable to the constitutional guarantee. The

    previously established religions (Episcopalian, Congregationalist,

    and Presbyterian) saw their

    market share

    decline dramaticallyunder constitutional religious freedom (McConnell & Posner1989).

    In addition, a state religion is by denition state as well as

    religion. The decisions made will be motivated by the interests of

    the state as well as those of religious groups. The interplay between

    popes and kings in feudal Europe reveals that pragmatic negotiation

    required when state and religion overlap. Hirschl (2010) notes that

    the effect of a state religion is to co-opt religion on behalf of the

    interests of the state. With state recognition and funding come

    state regulation and monitoring(Hirschl2010, 51). Thus, state sup-

    port for religion may incidentally undermine religion itself.

    There is ample reason to believe that religious freedom serves to

    encourage religious belief. If such belief is a good thing, that would

    justify the freedom. Leiter (2008) has suggested that religion may

    more systematically produce harms, because it may contain catego-

    rical commands that are divorced from evidence or reason. Religious

    wars have killed many in Africa and Asia and even Western countries

    such as Ireland. These extreme events might suggest that religion notbe encouraged.

    18

    Constitutions and Religious Freedom

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    31/272

    It would be a mistake, however, to extrapolate the generalized

    consequences of religious belief from such extreme cases. One must

    also consider the more typical effects of religious belief, and religious

    freedom by promoting religious diversity might well serve to counter-

    act the religious extremes. Adam Smith claimed that the zeal of

    religious radicals could be dangerous only where religious diversity

    was limited (Iannaccone1991).

    It is the absence of religious freedom that may produce such dan-

    gerous extremism. And government involvement with religion may be

    associated with greater religious violence (Iannaccone & Berman

    2006). Broad religious diversity and religious freedom in the UnitedStates is largely associated with pacic religious practice. The more

    government is involved in religion, the greater the need for believers to

    assume political power on behalf of their faith, which may include

    violence. The violence and terrorism sometimes associated with

    religious belief may be a function of a lack of religious freedom.

    Politics and Religion

    Religion may also serve a useful political function. Religious organ-

    izations are the original nongovernmental organizations (NGOs). As

    such, they can supplement government efforts and possibly resist

    government abuses, even those unrelated to religious liberty. Gill

    and Lundsgaarde (2004, 400) note that religious organizations are

    often the creators and purveyors of important values, beliefs, and

    norms that affect how people behave politically. Religion is a com-

    peting power center. Religions can mobilize people for action, includ-

    ing political protest (Gill 2001). Globally, membership in religious

    associations is signicantly associated with voting, signing petitions,

    attending demonstrations, and joining strikes (Norris & Inglehart

    2004). Of course, some suggest that religion is an opiate for the

    masses that precludes their political activism, but this is not demon-

    strated empirically.

    The 1980s saw a world democratization wave involving

    dozens of countries moving out of autocracy. In many nations, thistransition was led by the religious, in particular the Catholic Church

    19

    Why Freedom of Religion?

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    32/272

    (Philpott 2007). Unsurprisingly, this progressive effect was much

    more profound among religious groups that were not preferred by

    the state. National churches did not oppose authoritarian govern-

    ments, or did so only weakly. The increasing competition that the

    Latin American Catholic Church was receiving from evangelical

    Protestantism may have helped drive them to push for democracy.

    Indeed, it appeared that the greater religiosity of a church commun-

    ity was associated with more pressure for democratization

    (Philpott2007). Religion was central to both the downfall of Soviet

    communism and the development of democracy in former communist

    countries (Richardson2006).Within the United States, religion has played an important role

    in African-American politics. Rather than serving as an opiate, reli-

    gion has inspired the community to activism. Harris (1994) describes

    how religion has served as a political resource for the community and

    as a catalyst for its mobilization. The church provides physical organ-

    izational resources and psychological forces for activism. Greenberg

    (2000) similarly reports that churches can be important networks for

    political activism, especially in the African-American community.Mattis (2001) explores the great importance of religion to black polit-

    ical action in the United States. She notes how biblical passages have

    provided great force in the struggle for racial equality and how black

    churches have strengthened this message.

    The church, and religion generally, is commonly regarded as a

    mediating institution of society. Like other such institutions, it

    countervails against the power of government in society and may

    protect individual liberties of all sorts. James Madison himself rec-

    ognized that independent religions could serve as a check on the

    tyranny of the majority. To repeat, religion may be the original

    NGO (nongovernmental organization) and as such benecial.

    Mediating institutions have various merits. Neuhaus and Berger

    (1977) argued that it was necessary to have such institutions stand-

    ing between individuals and large institutions of public life in order to

    prevent tyrannical abuses. They claimed that their mediating struc-

    tures were essential for a vital democracy and empowered people

    throughout society. The actions of such institutions may supplementor balance governmental interventions.

    20

    Constitutions and Religious Freedom

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    33/272

    All private organizations may serve the function of mediating

    institutions, but religious groups may be especially valuable.

    Churches were the rst major NGOs (Berger 2004). Churches can

    foster diversity and act as a buffer between the individual and the

    state (Marshall1996). Religious afliation can serve as the base for

    group cohesion necessary to successfully challenge established insti-

    tutions and practices(Noland2003, 1).

    Putnam (2000), who has written extensively on the question,

    contends that religious organizations are uniquely important in

    American civil society. Religion is described as the single most

    important repository of social capital in America (Putnam 2000,66). Churches provide numerous social activities unrelated to reli-

    gion and may be an incubator for people developing their participa-

    tory skills. Religiosity is highly correlated to civic engagement, as

    previously discussed.

    In U.S. history, religion was a particularly powerful force in the

    struggle for African American civil rights providing organizational

    and symbolic resources, leadership, a premobilized constituency

    embedded in dense social networks, and an indigenous source offunding (Sherkat & Ellison 1999, 369). President Lincoln was openly

    motivated by religion in his antislavery position. In todays world,

    religious conservatives are quite active on other matters such as

    public policy toward abortion and gay rights, and religious liberals

    on matters such as war and the death penalty.

    Any individuals view of the current political role of religious

    groups probably depends on that individuals ideology, though

    churches can be found on both sides of many major political issues.

    If one believes in individual rights, the political positions of religious

    groups are at best a mixed bag in this nation. Some religious beliefs

    are contrary to freedom and democracy. Historically, however, the

    progressive force of religion on behalf of civil rights probably over-

    whelms other more negative effects. Tocqueville believed that reli-

    gion was necessary to the success of democracy, though it seems more

    likely that religious choice is the key (Fradkin2000).

    Some have argued that the net political role of religious belief is a

    positive one. Habermas (2006, 7) concluded that religion had value instabilizing and advancing a liberal political culture. There is a

    21

    Why Freedom of Religion?

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    34/272

    growing literature which argues that religion can be used to support

    tolerance, reconciliation, and human rights(Fox2008b, 930), though

    religion may at times support the opposite ends. Tocqueville suggested

    that religion may be necessary to sustain (as well as to moderate)

    individualism and material prosperity and thus may be doubly neces-

    sary to the future success of democracy(Fradkin2000, 88).

    Religion has sometimes played a very important political role

    overseas. The Catholic Church played a signicant role in the fall of

    Polish communism. The World Council of Churches had an important

    part in the fall of apartheid (Fox2008b). In the Latin America of the

    1970s, religious diversity played a role in defending human rights,perhaps to help attract followers (Gill 1994). When the state had

    established a religion, it tended to side with the oppressive state.

    But when a religion had to compete for followers, it tended to support

    human rights.

    The net political effect of religion and religious freedom is surely

    uncertain. A strong fundamentalist group might stie democracy and

    oppress opponents, but such a group is unlikely to encourage greater

    religious freedom. In a nation with broad religious diversity, funda-mentalists are less likely to assume such oppressive power. The con-

    temporary extremist tendencies of Islamic fundamentalism appear to

    be tamed by participation in a liberal democracy (Nasr1995).

    Moreover, one must consider why a state would deny its people

    religious freedom. In some cases, it may simply be religious fervor of

    national leaders or people who disrespect other faiths. But this can-

    not explain many cases. China, for example, is an atheist society that

    allows some religion but periodically cracks down on certain religious

    groups. It seems likely that an autocratic state views religious organ-

    izations as competing centers of power that could represent a threat.

    Religion or Freedom

    The identied benets of religion to individuals should not be too

    surprising. In the United States, religious belief is an individual

    choice. Although people certainly make bad choices at times,we presume that their choices are more often than not in their

    22

    Constitutions and Religious Freedom

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    35/272

    self-interest. This is a presumption of freedom of all sorts. As such, it

    is reasonable to presume that individual choices tend to produce a net

    benet to those individuals. In these circumstances, the religious

    beliefs of people should generally be a good thing. And what is best

    for individuals presumably will be best for the general society as well.

    The case for protecting religion as an innate good is much shakier

    than the evidence might suggest, however. As already noted, religion

    has occasionally been the source of some very bad things historically.

    While the studies of individuals have shown benets from religious

    belief, the evidence is much weaker on a state level, and many

    nonreligious people can attain these benets.The Gallup polling service has conducted measures of religiosity

    throughout the world and within this country. Individuals were

    asked: Is religion an important part of your daily life? The ve

    countries with the highest rate of yes answers were Egypt,

    Bangladesh, Sri Lanka, Indonesia, and the Congo. Those with the

    fewest positive answers were Estonia, Sweden, Denmark, Norway,

    and the Czech Republic. The latter group had 21 percent of individ-

    uals or fewer answering yes. The highest rate of atheism is reportedlyfound in Sweden, which has a high standard of life by international

    standards. The more secular countries typically show higher levels of

    happiness, less crime, greater equality, and better health and educa-

    tion (Zuckerman2009). They tend to have more freedom and be more

    prosperous.

    Looking at the relatively more and less religious countries, one

    would be hard pressed to claim the societal benets of religious belief.

    The less religious countries appear to be more functional and protec-

    tive of the rights and interests of their people. They certainly are

    wealthier. Perhaps it is the greater wealth of the nations that makes

    them less religious, a prospect that will be discussed shortly.

    Regardless, it is clear that countries with high levels of religious

    belief may show considerable pathologies, including terrorism,

    while countries with low levels may be ne and healthy places to

    live. The international comparison makes it difcult to make the case

    that greater belief in religion makes societies better. Indeed, Paul

    (2005) performed this comparison for developed countries and foundthat greater religion actually correlated with higher rates of

    23

    Why Freedom of Religion?

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    36/272

    homicide, STD infection rates, teen pregnancy, and abortion.

    Homicide is highest among highly religious nations (Fajnzylber,

    Lederman, & Loatza2002). Any claim that atheists are more likely

    to be immoral has long been disproven by systematic studies(Beit-

    Hallahmi2007, 306).

    Sundry studies have suggested that religious belief increases

    personal happiness, on average. Opnger (2010, 8) conducted an

    international study that found the association was one of a U shaped

    pattern. While especially high levels of national religiosity were

    associated with high levels of happiness, so were especially low

    levels of national religiosity. Relatively secular nations may besuccessful and happy. Of course, this study was based on national

    averages and not individuals. The author theorized that a common

    culture (whether religious or secular) was a key factor.

    It is important to note that the studies showing the benets of

    religious belief for individuals and communities generally exist in a

    climate of religious freedom. They may simply display the value of

    individual choice, not religion qua religion. Those who chose religious

    belief may simply have bene

    ted because they perceived, perhapsimplicitly, that it would be valuable to them. Others, who perceived

    no such benets from belief, may have beneted from nonbelief, but

    this has not been studied. So even if religion itself is not a per se good,

    religious choice may be. Of course, it is this choice that is generally

    protected by freedom of religion, as addressed in the following seg-

    ment of the book.

    The positive effects of religious belief may simply be the effect of

    religious freedom. At the time of the drafting of the Constitution,

    many believed that religious belief and practice are efcacious only

    when voluntary(Laycock1996, 324). While religion has been much

    studied, the effect of freedom with religion has not. One clear appa-

    rent benet of religious belief lies in social capital. A recent study of

    European nations found that state support of religion did not increase

    its effect but signicantly decreased the value of religion to society,

    whether measured in religious membership, volunteering, or dona-

    tions (Traunmuller & Freitag 2011). While researchers have

    struggled to nd an effect of religious belief on economic growth,one study found that religious freedom was positively associated

    24

    Constitutions and Religious Freedom

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    37/272

    with growth, even after controlling for economic freedom and other

    relevant variables (Alon & Chase 2005). And Elliott and Hayward

    (2009) found that it was religious freedom, not religion itself, that

    was associated with happiness. When religious activity is

    voluntarily chosen, people will be more likely to adopt self- and

    other-stereotyping that enhance their psychological well-being

    (Elliott & Hayward2009, 290).

    Fukayamas(2011, 37) world history declares that religion has

    been a source of social cohesion that permits human beings to coop-

    erate far more widely and securely than they would if they were the

    simple rational and self-interested agents posited by the economists.All historic societies, to our knowledge, have been religious. Pinker

    (1997) suggests that religion is built into the brain through evolution

    because of the cooperative benets it supplies. Gioso, Sapienza, and

    Zingales (2003) report that religious afliation and participation

    were associated with more cooperative attitudes.

    Religion clearly has a great benet for many people, and reli-

    gious belief appears to offer certain societal benets as well, over

    and above what intrinsic libertarian value is offered by religiousfreedom. The advantages of religious belief may only occur in soci-

    eties that offer their citizens freedom of religion. If religion is forced

    on the people, or oppressed, those benets may not arise. It is the

    virtue of freely chosen religious beliefs that is the value to be pro-

    tected. Moreover, it is possible that freedom of religion may be of

    benet to nonbelievers, addressed in the following section of this

    chapter.

    Religious Freedom and the Irreligious

    Leiters argument seems grounded in opposition to the conservative

    constitutional position that religion is to be encouraged as special and

    greatly privileged. But this interpretation is not how the law has

    generally developed. Religious freedom has been used to protect the

    rights of nonbelievers against the demands of the religious. Under

    the U.S. Constitution, at least, secularism is often protected fromreligion, much as if it were a religion. Laycock (1996) contends that

    25

    Why Freedom of Religion?

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    38/272

    any coherent concept of freedom of religion must also protect the

    atheists, agnostics, and secularists.

    Indeed, atheists may be particularly in need of constitutional

    protection. In the United States, a negative view of atheism is perva-

    sive, and atheists may be at the top of the list of groups Americans

    dislike (Zuckerman2009). The constitutions of South Carolina and

    Arkansas ban atheists from holding public ofce. There is evidence

    that the American people disfavor atheists and agnostics more than

    any other material minority group (Edgell, Gerteis, & Hartmann

    2006). A majority of Americans reportedly would not vote for an

    atheist for president. None of this is apparently constitutionallybased.

    The U.S. Supreme Court has frequently used national constitu-

    tional religious provisions to advance the rights of atheists. Free

    exercise may be interpreted as the right not to exercise a religious

    belief. In Torcaso v. Watkins (1961, 495, n.11), Justice Hugo Black

    listed secular humanism as a First Amendment religion. The Court

    has held that the First Amendment protects the conscience of the

    in

    del or the atheist

    (Wallace v. Jaffree 1985). In the salient decisionin United States v. Seeger (1965), the Court reversed a conviction of a

    party who refused induction into the military services because of his

    conscientious objection, which was not grounded in traditional reli-

    gious beliefs. While the case involved a statute and not the

    Constitution, the court held that religion simply meant a mans

    devotion to the highest ideal that he can conceive (United States

    v. Seeger 1965, 862). Belief in a supreme being or deity was not

    required, just a belief and devotion to goodness and virtue for their

    own sakes (United States v. Seeger1965, 854).

    The U.S. Constitution is said to neither advance nor inhibit

    religion(Board of Education of Kiryas Joel v. Grumet1994, 719). It

    merely ensures each individual the right of conscience, to follow a

    faith or not. The constitutional provision provides some additional

    protection for religion, though, as only beliefs rooted in religion are

    protected by the free exercise clause (Frazee v. Illinois Dept.

    Employment Sec. 1989). Thus, a Jew may have a right to wear

    a yarmulke, where an atheist may not have a right to particularheadgear. For central, conscience-centered matters, though, the

    26

    Constitutions and Religious Freedom

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    39/272

    irreligious are protected. An atheist can object to the constitutionality

    of a compulsory school prayer.

    Some have thus argued that the U.S. Constitution protects free-

    dom from religion as much as freedom of religion. The right to free

    exercise of religion implies the right to free exercise of non-religion

    (Sullivan1992, 197). This effect is not limited to the United States.

    Gey (2007, 251) reports that the religious liberty jurisprudence in

    most constitutional democracies recognizes the need to protect athe-

    ists and agnostics, though he recognizes it may at times marginalize

    them. However, before the development of modern conceptions of

    religious liberty, atheists had no effective legal protection (Gey2007,252). The United Nations standards for freedom of religion are

    explicit in the protection of atheist beliefs as well.

    Miner (1998, 624) thus argues that religious freedom provides

    one of the most vital elements that go to make up the identity of

    believers and their conception of life, but it is also a precious asset for

    atheists, agnostics, skeptics, and the unconcerned. The European

    Court of Human Rights has written that its expression of religious

    freedom was

    a precious asset for atheists, agnostics, skeptics, andthe unconcerned (Kokkinakis v. Greece 1993). Interestingly, the

    study on the association of religion, government regulation, and

    personal satisfaction found that less government regulation of reli-

    gion also increased life satisfaction among those who were not reli-

    gious (Elliott & Hayward2009).

    Smith (1991) argues that the constitutional protection of the rule

    of law in America has become self-negating. He contends that the

    nations commitment to religious freedom had a religious rationale

    borne of a religious world view. Yet the interpretation of the First

    Amendment, he suggests, has come to forbid governmental reliance

    on religious justications, with a secularizing effect. Thus, in its

    development, religious freedom has come to have a secularizing con-

    sequence. While he is critical of this, others might nd it benecial.

    There are three primary types of constitutional provisions rele-

    vant to religious freedom: (i) provisions creating or banning a state

    religion; (ii) provisions prohibiting the establishment of religion or

    calling for separation of church and state; and (iii) provisionsguaranteeing individuals freedom of religious belief. Plainly, a

    27

    Why Freedom of Religion?

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    40/272

    constitutional provision barring a state religion benets atheists and

    agnostics, who need not be subjected to contrary religious beliefs. A

    constitutional provision requiring the separation of church and state

    would have much the same effect. Theoretically, a constitutional

    provision guaranteeing the free exercise of religion could privilege

    religion, but it has been interpreted to guarantee the free exercise of

    nonreligious beliefs, so it too should benet the irreligious. Thus,

    freedom of religion is not intrinsically pro-religion; it is fundamen-

    tally pro-choice for individual decisions of conscience. Freedom of

    secular belief is important (Boyle & Sheen1997).

    The irreligious are not equally protected by the Constitution,though, with one example being the ministerial exception to general

    legislation. Religious organizations are free to hire and re clergy,

    without respect to antidiscrimination laws, for example, and courts

    generally do not even consider the possible presence of a contrary

    compelling state interest (Tebbe2011). This is true even for decisions

    made for nontheological reasons. No comparable protection extends

    to the irreligious. Historically, there are various other decisions in

    which courts have allowed some discrimination against the irreli-gious (Tebbe 2011, 11501151). When the Supreme Court allowed

    the Amish the right to remove their children from school, it expressly

    said that this right would not extend to someone driven by purely

    secularmotivations (Wisconsin v. Yoder1972, 215216). The consti-

    tutional protections for freedom of religion have provided material

    support to nonbelievers, but the protection is not fully as strong as for

    the religious. In other areas, though, such as government funding,

    the religious are more constrained by the Constitution than the

    irreligious.

    John Rawls (1996) focuses on religion as a core freedom. He

    argues that such freedom is as important as respect for quality and

    notes that religion represents a comprehensive doctrine regarding

    the meaning of life, in which individuals typically engage. He argues

    for a doctrine of liberty of conscience, whether or not this involves a

    belief in an established religion. This is consistent with those who

    question the need for special protection of religion itself.

    Nussbaum (2008) expands upon this Rawlsian interpretation.She notes that Americas constitutional protection speaks of religion,

    28

    Constitutions and Religious Freedom

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    41/272

    not conscience, and that religion is thus legally privileged over some

    other personal beliefs. The American Constitution was written at a

    time when religious persecution was apparent, but nearly everyone

    ascribed to some sort of religious belief. Atheists and agnostics have

    grown in numbers and have suffered their own repression over more

    recent years. Nussbaum believes that the concept of religion, as

    protected by the constitutional freedom, should be viewed as extend-

    ing to any matters of fundamental conscience. This approach is not

    dramatically unlike the result reached by the U.S. Supreme Court.

    There is even an argument that constitutional freedom of religion

    favors the irreligious, in that it implies secularism(Engel2011, 9).It precludes the state from imposing religious beliefs on its people. By

    its nature, religion governs the lives of believers, and it is a small step

    to using the government to govern the lives of all. Religious groups

    commonly involve themselves in politics, trying to make their values

    ofcial ones, such as seen by Americas religious right (arguing

    against abortion) and left (arguing for equality of rights). Freedom

    of religion necessarily allows such efforts, but it more fundamentally

    limits them, at least in the imposition of religious beliefs on others.Religious liberty puts political importance on nonreligious justica-

    tions for policy positions. The religious justication for the freedom

    may have been dominant in the creation of the First Amendment, but

    it is seldom heard by contemporary courts, which have secularized

    the right (Smith1991).

    The traditional liberalism associated with free-exercise guaran-

    tees arguably is secularist in nature (Liviatan 2011). Religion argu-

    ably contradicts the commitment to total human freedom of choice.

    Most religions favor some sort of social control that runs up against

    the tenets of classical liberalism. By fully embracing individual free-

    dom of choice, even religious freedom limits religion.

    The establishment clause surely respects the beliefs of those

    without religion. It essentially prevents religious values from being

    written into the nations laws. Even seemingly neutral policies, such

    as a compulsory moment of silence in schools, may be invalidated, if

    adopted for a religious purpose (Wallace v. Jaffree 1985). The primary

    standard for applying the clause requires that to be constitutional astatute have a secular purpose and must not have a primary effect of

    29

    Why Freedom of Religion?

  • 7/23/2019 2015. Frank B. Cross-Constitutions and Religious Freedom-Cambridge University Press.pdf

    42/272

    advancing or inhibiting religion (Lemon v. Kurtzman 1971). The

    government has been stripped of all power to tax, to support, or

    otherwise to assist any or all religions (Everson v. Board of

    Education 1947, 11). The First Amendment not only protects religion

    from the state, it also exists to protect the state from religion. The

    establishment clause has been applied with some inconsistency, and

    it allows some actions seemingly favorable to religious beliefs, but it

    has frequently been used to protect the irreligious. Moreover, it gives

    the courts a path to protect the irreligious if the courts so choose.

    Indeed, the establishment clause might not be considered free-

    dom of religion, insofar as it prevents help given to religions. Ofcourse, such a clause promotes freedom because it prevents a state

    religion. But by barring nondiscriminatory assistance to religion

    more broadly, while not constraining assistance to the irreligious,

    the clause is in some ways essentially antireligious. Thus, McConnell

    (2000) suggests that constitutional religious freedom is a necessary

    provision to balance out the antireligious effect of an establishment

    clause. In any event, such a provision should benet the irreligious.

    Hirschl (2010, 13) examines the application of constitutionalprotections of religion in various countries and concludes that con-

    stitutional law and courts in virtually all such polities have become

    bastions of relative secularism, pragmatism, and moderation,

    thereby emerging as effective shields against the spread of religiosity

    and increased popular support for principles of theocratic gover-

    nance. Raday (2009) argues that constitutionalism is intrinsically

    secular and that this is vital to the protection of human rights.

    Constitutions themselves become objects of worship, perhaps

    competing with relig