YOU ARE DOWNLOADING DOCUMENT

Please tick the box to continue:

Transcript
Page 1: Harms & Moral Justification

Rational Engagement, Emotional Response, & the Prospects for Moral Progress

in Animal Use Debates Ethicists have increasingly turned their attention to moral questions about the treatment of non-human animals. Arguments from a range of perspectives have been given for the conclusion that routine uses of animals in agriculture, the fashion industry, and experimentation are morally wrong. Defenses of these practices, however, have been far fewer, and generally less developed, than the cases in favor of animals. My aim in this presentation is to encourage development of stronger arguments in favor of animal use and provide methodological guidance on how to do so.

Nathan Nobis For Animal Research in Theory & Practice,

ed. Jeremy Garrett, Rice, Philosophy

Page 2: Harms & Moral Justification

Harms & Moral Justification• Many fields and occupations involve

harming animals, making them worse off. – ‘Animals’ = for our purposes, mammals &

birds; least controversial cases for discussion.• Typically, people in these fields will agree

that animals are being harmed. • They claim, however, that these harms are

morally justified: not all harms are wrong, and these harms aren’t wrong (indeed, perhaps some are morally obligatory).

Page 3: Harms & Moral Justification

Common experimental procedures include:

• drowning, • suffocating,• starving,• burning,• blinding,• destroying their ability to

hear,• damaging their brains,• severing their limbs,• crushing their organs

• inducing – heart attacks,– cancers– ulcers– paralysis, – Seizures

• forcing them to inhale tobacco smoke, drink alcohol, and ingest various drugs, such as heroine and cocaine.

Page 4: Harms & Moral Justification

A few commonly overlooked observations about harm:

(1) “Painless” killing can be (and often is) harmful for the one who is killed; it is bad for him/her. – Why? They are

deprived of whatever goods they would have experienced. No interests can be satisfied.

Thus, the common “if ‘painlessly killed,’ then ‘humane’, so nothing morally objectionable” views need defense.

(2) Recent ethological research shows that just being in a laboratory, and undergoing routine procedures, is stressful (and thus harmful) for animals.

Page 5: Harms & Moral Justification

Balcombe JP, Barnard ND, Sandusky C, “Laboratory routines cause animal stress,” Contemporary Topics in

Laboratory Animal Science, 2004, Nov, 43 (6):42-51 Abstract: Eighty published studies were appraised to document

the potential stress associated with three routine laboratory procedures commonly performed on animals: handling, blood collection, and orogastric gavage . . .

Significant changes in physiologic parameters correlated with stress . . were associated with all three procedures in multiple species in the studies we examined.

The results of these studies demonstrated that animals responded with rapid, pronounced, and statistically significant elevations in stress-related responses for each of the procedures . . .

We interpret these findings to indicate that laboratory routines are associated with stress, and that animals do not readily habituate to them. The data suggest that significant fear, stress, and possibly distress are predictable consequences of routine laboratory procedures, and that these phenomena have substantial scientific and humane implications for the use of animals in laboratory research.

Page 6: Harms & Moral Justification

Balcombe JP, “Laboratory environments and rodents’ behavioural needs: A review,”

Laboratory Animals (in press)

Abstract: Laboratory housing conditions have significant physiological and psychological effects on rodents, raising both scientific and humane concerns.  Published studies of rats, mice and other rodents were reviewed to document behavioural and psychological problems attributable to predominant laboratory housing conditions.

Studies indicate that rats and mice value opportunities to take cover, build nests, explore, gain social contact, and exercise some control over their social milieu, and that the inability to satisfy these needs is physically and psychologically detrimental, leading to impaired brain development and behavioural anomalies (e.g., stereotypies). To the extent that space is a means to gain access to such resources, spatial confinement likely exacerbates these deficits. Adding environmental “enrichments” to small cages reduces but does not eliminate these problems, and I argue that substantial changes in housing and husbandry conditions would be needed to further reduce them.

Page 7: Harms & Moral Justification

Many ethicists have argued that it’s wrong to use animals these ways; they’ve given reasons for

their views and defended them:• utilitarianism and other consequentialisms,• rights-based deontologies,• ideal contractarianisms (“veil of ignorance,” “Golden

rule” ethics),• virtue ethics, • “common-sense” (“least harm,” “needless harm”)

moralities,• religious moralities, feminist ethics, • and more: indeed almost every major, influential

perspective in moral theory.

Page 8: Harms & Moral Justification

Even Kant’s, Rawls’, and other moral theories have been modified to be friendly to non-rational

moral patients (not moral agents):• Improve the theory so there are direct

duties to baby (& other ‘non-rational’ & powerless humans : she’s of moral value not because others care about her,

despite hernot

being a moral agent,

rational, etc.

Page 9: Harms & Moral Justification

If the theory is now not Bad for Baby (and other vulnerable humans), it is now not Bad for Animals?

Page 10: Harms & Moral Justification

Thus, an abundance of ethical resources in defense of animals.

• However, this hasn’t made much of a difference in thought or deed regarding uses of animals. – Possible explanations:

• big changes are always slow; trickle-down is slow…• philosophers (and other thinkers and authors)

typically just aren’t very influential,• personal, financial, legal, political, institutional

barriers to doing the right thing,• ???

Page 11: Harms & Moral Justification

A competing explanation:• There are strong arguments that morally

justify (much of) the current treatment of animals. – Since these arguments are strong / sound / very

reasonable to accept, the defenses of animals are weak / unsound / unreasonable.

• I’m going to suggest that this explanation is unlikely, because these arguments are weak.– I encourage development of more and stronger arguments in favor

of, defending, animal use and provide methodological guidance on doing so.

Page 12: Harms & Moral Justification

Emotional responses to moral issues:

“It sometimes appears that the quality of our thought on a topic is inversely proportional to the intensity of our emotions concerning that topic.”

-- Fred Feldman, Confrontations With the Reaper: A Philosophical Study of the Nature and Value of Death (Oxford, 1994).

Page 13: Harms & Moral Justification

Rational engagement of moral issues:

• Identify some past instances of “moral progress” in thought, attitude, & deed:– Hopefully, rational evaluation of arguments contributed

to this, somewhat!• We can identify some basic “logical skills” that

can help us improve the quality of our thought.– Apply these “skills” to some recent arguments made by

scientists and philosophers regarding animals. – This is important because it seems that not enough

people consistently use these skills; this is not good.

Page 14: Harms & Moral Justification

Formerly “controversial” issues and simple arguments:

• “Women shouldn’t be allowed to go to university because women are so emotional that abstract thought is so difficult for them.”

• "Slavery is morally right because we slave-owners benefit greatly from slavery."

• "Since animals are not rational, it's morally ok to raise them to be killed and eaten."

These are arguments; what are their faults?

Page 15: Harms & Moral Justification

Women (1) • Conclusion:

– “Women shouldn’t be allowed to go to university.”• Why think that?

– “Women are such emotional beings that abstract thought is difficult for them.”

• Imprecise! ‘SOME’? or ‘ALL’? – “Some women are so emotional that abstract thought is

difficult.” [True, and true for some men!]– “All women are so emotional …” [False, empirically

indefensible claim, so unsound argument]

Page 16: Harms & Moral Justification

Women (2)

(1) “Some women are so emotional that abstract thought is difficult.” [True, and true for some men!]

(2) “Therefore, [no] women should be allowed to go to university.”

But how do you get from (1) to (2)? What’s the missing linking premise?

A question: How would some women’s “emotionality” justify restricting educational opportunities from all women? Not clear.

Page 17: Harms & Moral Justification

Women (3)

• However, even if some or even all women are so “emotional” and have difficulty with “abstract thought” why would that justify denying any women the opportunity to “improve themselves” through education?

• “If my cup won't hold but a pint, and yours holds a quart, wouldn't you be mean not to let me have my little half measure full?”

• Sojourner Truth, “Ain't I A Woman?” 1851

Page 18: Harms & Moral Justification

Slavery"Slavery is morally right because we slave-owners

benefit greatly from slavery.“(1) Slave-owners benefit from slavery. [True](C) Therefore, slavery is morally right. [?]--------------------------------------------------------------How do you get from (1) to (2)? What’s the missing, assumed linking premise? (1) Slave-owners benefit from slavery. [True](2) If some group benefits from some arrangement,

then that arrangement is right. ?(3) Therefore, slavery is morally right.

Page 19: Harms & Moral Justification

Animals"Since animals are not rational, it's morally ok to

raise them to be killed and eaten.”(1) “Animals are not rational.”(2) Therefore, it’s OK to kill them…Observations and questions:

(A) (1) is imprecise: some, or all, animals are not rational? Which animals?

(B) Ambiguity, lack of clarity: what is meant by ‘rational’?

(C) ‘Missing-link’ premise needed to make argument logically valid: ‘If a being is not ‘rational’, then it’s ok to kill it.’ [False?]

Page 20: Harms & Moral Justification

“Logical skills”: The (moral) value of basic predicate logic

• Attending to the intended meanings of unclear or ambiguous words: – what do you mean?– ‘animal,’ ‘human’, ‘being human’, ‘human

being’, ‘person’, ‘human person’, ‘humanity’• Precision regarding #, quantity: some, all?• Assumed, unstated premises that link stated

reason(s) to conclusion. (Logical validity).

Page 21: Harms & Moral Justification

It seems these “logical skills” are generally useful.

A bioethicist disagrees about the value of these skills for professional ethics:“Frankly, science students would have very

little patience for the abstract argumentation and reasoning that one finds in your paper and is standard fare in philosophy journals.”

Page 22: Harms & Moral Justification

Apply these (& other) logical skills to some recent arguments:

• Scientists– Stuart Derbyshire, Ph.D., U

Birmingham UK (used to be at Pitt); pain researcher.

– Mark Mattfield, Ph.D., Research Defense Society, UK

– Colin Blakemore, Ph.D., Medical Research Council, UK

– Adrian Morrison, Ph.D., DVM, U Penn, sleep disorders

• Philosophers– Carl Cohen– Neil Levy, “Cohen &

Kinds: A Response to Nathan Nobis,” JoAP)

– Tibor Machan, Putting Human’s First

– Matthew Liao, “Virtually All Human Beings as Rightholders: A Non-Speciesist Approach”

Page 23: Harms & Moral Justification

The issue needn’t be whether animals have ‘rights’:

• Moral or legal rights?• Which moral rights? (be specific)• ‘Rights’ conflicts: ‘right’ to smoke, ‘right’ to a smoke-free

environment– ‘Rights’ appeals can conceal details.

• Common invalid argument: – ‘If animals have rights, then serious change is needed.

But they don’t have rights, so change isn’t needed.’– Logically invalid – conclusion doesn’t follow – and

avoids the concrete questions.

Page 24: Harms & Moral Justification

The issue needn’t be whether animals have ‘rights’:

• Better to consider – (1) whether various (specific) uses of animals

are morally permissible or not, whether any ways of treatment are morally obligatory and

– (2) why or why not.• Keep this the focus on these ‘deontic’ categories

is helpful for many practical and theoretical reasons.

Page 25: Harms & Moral Justification

The issue also needn’t be whether animals are “equal” to humans:

• Are any animals “equal” to humans? Are all humans “equal”? Hard to answer:– What is meant by “equal”? Not obvious. – Which humans, which animals? (What is meant by ‘humans’

and ‘animals’?). (fetus, baby, adult, 100 y/o?)• Common invalid argument; avoids the concrete

questions. – ‘If animals are ‘equal’ to humans, then serious change is

needed. But they aren’t equal, so change isn’t needed.’– “Equal consid.” vs.“No consid.”vs. “mid-level” consid?

• Again, ideal Q’s are about moral permissibility.

Page 26: Harms & Moral Justification

Objection: An abundance of resources is a philosophical embarrassment?

• “Many philosophers argue that animals are treated wrongly, but disagree on why (e.g., Peter Singer ‘demolishes’ Tom Regan and Regan ‘demolishes’ Singer). Therefore, there is no justification for thinking that animals are treated wrongly.”

– Adrian Morrison; Richard Vance, JAMA

Page 27: Harms & Moral Justification

A parallel argument:

• Many thinkers argue that animals are not treated wrongly, but disagree on why (e.g., Carl Cohen ‘demolishes’ Jan Narveson & Narveson ‘demolishes’ Cohen). Therefore, there is no justification for thinking that animals are not treated wrongly.”

Page 28: Harms & Moral Justification

The false, unstated assumption:

• If you believe p, and for reasons X, Y, & Z, but others believe p for reasons A, B, C, etc. and these reasons are logically incompatible (and you recognize this), then either you have no (good) reason to believe p or there is no good reason to believe p. – At the very least, this principle isn’t one

typically accepted or universally applied (e.g., global warming is bad).

Page 29: Harms & Moral Justification

Appeals to evolution / “biological perspectives”

• Morrison: “to refrain from exploring nature in every possible way would be an arrogant rejection of evolutionary forces.”

• “Evolution has endowed us with a need to know as much as we can.” (Nicoll, Russell).– “Humans evolved; therefore, morally we

should ….” Does not follow. – Constraints on using other humans to advance

our own genetic line, when it’s in our interest?

Page 30: Harms & Moral Justification

Benefits Arguments / Arguments from “Necessity”

• “animal experiments are vital to the future well-being of humans and, as long as they are conducted to high ethical standards, they are entirely justifiable.” – Mark Matfield– The argument: Benefits for humans justify

animal experimentation (and other uses)– The are “necessary.”

Page 31: Harms & Moral Justification

Is animal use ‘necessary’? (1)

• Depends on what you mean by necessary.• In one sense, yes!

– To do animal experiments, it is necessary to do animal experiments. To make these exact scientific discoveries using animals, it is essential to use animals: if animals weren’t used, the experiments would be different.

Page 32: Harms & Moral Justification

Is animal use ‘necessary’? (2)• In other senses, perhaps not. Is animal necessary for

making medical progress and for, more generally, bettering human welfare?– “Necessary for the well-being of humans,” but which

humans? A few? (Maybe!). Everyone? Doubtful that every human benefits from (every) animal experiment.

– There are other ways of bringing about goods for humans:• clinical research, epidemiology, in vitro research, uses of

technology, autopsies, prevention, etc.; • feeding people, getting existing medical care to them, etc.. It’s

been argued that these would yield greater human utility.

Page 33: Harms & Moral Justification

Defenses of the low (human) utility of animal experimentation

• RC Greek & N Shanks, Animal Research in Light of Science (2006? Rodopi)

• N Shanks & LaFollette, Brute Science (Routledge 1997)

• RC Greek & J Greek [DVM], Sacred Cows & Golden Geese (Continuum 2000), Specious Science (2002), What Will We Do if We Don’t Experiment on Animals? (2004)

• They argue that other methods of research are more effective at addressing human needs.

Page 34: Harms & Moral Justification

Benefits argument:

1. Animal experiment yields [some] benefits. 2. If some action benefits someone (or some

group), then that action is right. [false; needs refinement and serious defense]

3. Therefore, animal experimentation (and other uses) are right.

What about direct harms (to animals, to humans, esp. indirect harms from opportunity costs)? How are these weighed? A careful methodology would be nice, at least; is necessary for serious defense.

Page 35: Harms & Moral Justification

Want benefits?

“Whatever benefits animal experimentation is thought to hold in store for us, those very same benefits could be obtained through experimenting on humans [esp. vulnerable ones] instead of animals. Indeed, given that problems exist because scientists must extrapolate from animal models to humans, one might think there are good scientific reasons for preferring human subjects.”

– Philosopher Ray Frey

Page 36: Harms & Moral Justification

Why not use these humans?Blakemore’s answer

• “The only firm line [to make moral distinctions] on genetic and morphological grounds is between our own species and other species.”– Suggested: if something is of our species, then it is

more morally valuable than any animals. • But he says a human “embryo, certainly before the nervous

system begins to develop, is just a bundle of cells.” – Suggested : being of our species does not necessarily

confer moral value. • “We should have a special attitude toward other humans,

so crucial to this argument is how we define a person.” He did not do this.

Page 37: Harms & Moral Justification

Why not use these humans?Derbyshire’s answer

• “Animals lack the capacity for reflection (and therefore an inner world) and the capacity for reasoning” (So do many humans!!)

• “It’s remarkable that we have to consider the question.”– Not remarkable if someone suggests that what’s required

for a presumption against harm are properties that many, many human beings lack.

• “Society cares about vulnerable humans.”– All of them? What about secret experiments? What if they

could be re-educated? Why do they care? (Harms)

Page 38: Harms & Moral Justification

Avoiding objections from non-rational human beings.

• A common claim:– It’s wrong to seriously harm a being only if

that being is rational, autonomous, makes moral choices, is creative, intelligent, contributes to society, etc.

• OK, animals aren’t like that, but neither are lots of (conscious, feeling) humans. This principle suggests it’s not seriously wrong to harm them. Is this principle correct?

Page 39: Harms & Moral Justification

Some odd inferences:Cohen, Levy & Kinds

• Cohen [NEJM]: Moral “rights” depend on moral agency, the ability to respond to “moral claims.” A being has rights only if it’s a of a kind characterized by moral agency. – Finnis: “to be a person is to belong to a kind of being

characterized by rational (self-conscious, intelligent) nature.”

– Scanlon: “the class of beings whom it is possible to wrong will include at least all those beings who are of a kind that is normally capable of judgment-sensitive attitudes.”

Page 40: Harms & Moral Justification

Cohen, Levy & Kinds

• Cohen: All humans are of a kind capable of moral agency, but– “[animals] are not beings of a kind capable

of exercising or responding to moral claims. Animals therefore have no rights, and they can have none.”

• What kind are animals? How are humans who are not moral agents of the kind “moral agent”? Cohen doesn’t explain.

Page 41: Harms & Moral Justification

Cohen’s possible answer?

• Humans who are non-moral agents are of this kind because they are members of a set – e.g., the kind, a species – some of which are moral agents. – Response: But animals are also members of a set – e.g.,

the kind, sentient beings – some of whom are moral agents also! They have rights too, on Cohen’s account!

• Humans and animals are of many kinds, some overlapping, some not. Inconsistent conclusions follow from Cohen-esque reasoning.

Page 42: Harms & Moral Justification

Levy’s attempt to find the right kind: the “narrowest” natural kind

If (1) an individual A is a member of some species S and (2) some, most or all of the other members of that species have some property C and (3), on the basis of having property C, they have moral property R, then individual A has moral property R as well, even though A lacks property C.

Page 43: Harms & Moral Justification

If (1) an individual A is a member of some species S and (2) some, most or all of the other members of that species have some property C and (3), on the basis of having property C,

they have moral property R, then individual A has moral property R as well, even though A lacks property C.

C = non-moral property of "having doneno serious crimes”;

R= "not deserving lifeimprisonment."

Implications for lone criminal?

C= "intelligent" and "aware“;

R= "being such that one ought to be allowed to make decisions to direct one's own life."

Implications for young children and others?

Page 44: Harms & Moral Justification

Machan’s Arguments from What’s “Normal”

• A being has “moral rights” (presumably making it wrong to harm it) only if it a “moral nature,” a “capacity” to see the difference between right and wrong and choose accordingly.”

• “It is this moral capacity that establishes a basis for rights, not the fact that animals, like us, have interests or can feel pain.”

• Humans are of the “kind” of being that have such a moral nature and animals are not; thus humans have rights and animals do not.

Page 45: Harms & Moral Justification

What about humans who seem to lack this moral “capacity”?

• We must consider humans as they exist “normally, not abnormally” and focus on the “healthy cases, not the special or exceptional [or “borderline”] ones.”

• “We do need to deal with borderline cases. But we can do so only by applying and adapting the knowledge we acquire from the normal case. We can’t start with the exception and infer the rule.”

Page 46: Harms & Moral Justification

The suggested argument:

1. Humans who lack “moral capacities” are human.[T!]

2. If someone is human, then they have all the (moral) properties that ‘normal’, ‘healthy’, typical humans have.

3. Therefore, these humans have moral capacities, and so they have “rights.”

Reply: 2 is, at least, unsupported, and is an instance of a generally false principle for moral & non-moral properties. (e.g., 4 limbs; Ted Bundy)

Page 47: Harms & Moral Justification

Matthew Liao, “Virtually All Human Beings as Rightholders: The Species-Norm Account”

• to be a rightholder (“a being with the highest moral status”), something need not:– be a moral agent– have the potential to be a moral agent– be of the kind (species) that normally is a moral

agent – be actually sentient, conscious, etc. or even

have the potential, i.e., that it’s “possible” in some sense

• Could be tinkered into a pro-animal exper. view.

Page 48: Harms & Moral Justification

The correct answer is…A being has “rights” iff the entity has incorporated

into it the “genetic basis for the species capacity for moral agency” (i.e. the relevant bits of DNA that normally allow for moral agency) or the functional equivalent thereof (e.g. software and/or hardware that would normally allow for moral agency in an artificial being). The “intrinsic value” that resides in the relevant genetic bits “grounds” rightholding even when that genetic material is blocked from developing and cannot allow for moral agency.

If X is like that, then X has “moral rights.”

Page 49: Harms & Moral Justification

Liao’s reasoning in favor of the view, it seems:

(1) There are moral duties only if there are moral agents. [T]

(2) There are moral agents only if there are beings with the “genetic basis” for moral agency. [OK; accept this for sake of argument]

(3) Therefore, there are moral duties only if there are beings with the “genetic basis” for moral agency.

(4) Therefore (?), any being with the “genetic basis” for moral agency is a ‘rightholder.’

Page 50: Harms & Moral Justification

A parallel argument:

(1) There are moral duties only if there are living beings, or beings that can perceive, or …. [T]

(2) There are living beings, or beings that can perceive only if there are beings with the “genetic basis” for life, perception, etc. [OK]

(3) Therefore, there are moral duties only if there are beings with the “genetic basis” for life, perception, etc.

(4) Therefore (?), any being with the “genetic basis” for life, perception, is a ‘rightholder.’

Page 51: Harms & Moral Justification

Objections [from Chris Grau, FIU]• If the species-norm account is true, then:

– A cabbage that has "integrated" the relevant genetic bits but is damaged such that the capacity for moral agency is permanently blocked. (this cabbage has rights even though it lacks moral agency and the potential for it.)

– A (future) computer with the relevant hardware. software "integrated" but blocked. This computer has rights even though it would lack both moral agency and the potential for moral agency.

• Cabbage or computer vs. sentient animals and sentient humans lacking the relevant genetic material for moral agency?

• The species norm account seems entirely ad hoc.

Page 52: Harms & Moral Justification

Conclusions / Summary• Presented a basic method for thinking about moral

issues; demonstrated its use; applied it to some recent arguments defending current animal use and/or criticizing pro-animal arguments.

• Suggested that these arguments are weak. • My hope: since these methods are generally useful,

perhaps future defenders of current uses of animals will utilize them for better arguments.

To make moral progress and contribute to reasonable debate it is important that this is done.

Page 53: Harms & Moral Justification

For an overview of the recent literature on ethics and animals issues, see Angus Taylor’s Ethics & Animals: An Overview of the Philosophical Debate (Broadview, 2003). For arguments from utilitarianism, see, among other sources, Peter Singer’s Practical Ethics, 2nd Edition (Cambridge UP, 1993) and his Animal Liberation, 3rd Edition (Harper, 2001) although the former is, strictly speaking, not an argument from utilitarianism. From rights-based deontology, see, among other sources, Tom Regan’s The Case for Animal Rights, 2nd Edition (U California Press, 2004), as well as his more accessible Empty Cages: Facing the Challenge of Animal Rights (Rowman & Littlefield, 2004); for Rawlsian-style ideal contractarianism, see among other sources, Mark Rowlands’ Animals Like Us (Verso, 2002); from virtue ethics, see among other sources, Rosalind Hursthouse’s Ethics, Humans and Other Animals (Routledge, 2000), from common-sense morality, see, among other sources, Mark Bernstein’s Without a Tear: Our Tragic Relationship With Animals (U Illinois Press, 2004) and David DeGrazia’s Animal Rights: A Very Short Introduction (Oxford, 2002); for religious moralities, see, among other sources, Matthew Scully’s Dominion: The Power of Man, the Suffering of Animals, and the Call to Mercy (St. Martin’s, 2003); from feminism, see Carol Adams and Josephine Donavan (eds.) Beyond Animal Rights: A Feminist Caring Ethic for the Treatment of Animals (Continuum, 1996).

Page 54: Harms & Moral Justification

Stuart Derbyshire,an animal experimentation advocate:

• “It is not possible to advocate animal welfare and at the same time give animals untested drugs or diseases, or slice them open to test a new surgical procedure. . .”

– The Scientist, 3/06, “Time to Abandon the Three Rs: Submitting to ‘refinement, reduction, and replacement’ risks the future of animal research”

• “Once the perspective of the animal is adopted, it is inevitable that all experimentation will be seen negatively, as no animal experiments are in the interest of the animal”

- “Why Animals’ Rights Are Wrong” (p. 39)


Related Documents