Top Banner

of 28

Modal Would in Police Interrogations

Apr 03, 2018

Download

Documents

Sorin Ciutacu
Welcome message from author
This document is posted to help you gain knowledge. Please leave a comment to let me know what you think about it! Share it to your friends and learn new things together.
Transcript
  • 7/28/2019 Modal Would in Police Interrogations

    1/28

    http://dis.sagepub.com

    Discourse Studies

    DOI: 10.1177/1461445606064830

    2006; 8; 475Discourse StudiesDerek Edwards

    in police interrogationswouldFacts, norms and dispositions: practical uses of the modal verb

    http://dis.sagepub.com/cgi/content/abstract/8/4/475The online version of this article can be found at:

    Published by:

    http://www.sagepublications.com

    can be found at:Discourse StudiesAdditional services and information for

    http://dis.sagepub.com/cgi/alertsEmail Alerts:

    http://dis.sagepub.com/subscriptionsSubscriptions:

    http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navReprints:

    http://www.sagepub.co.uk/journalsPermissions.navPermissions:

    http://dis.sagepub.com/cgi/content/refs/8/4/475Citations

    by Sorin Ciutacu on October 31, 2009http://dis.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://dis.sagepub.com/cgi/alertshttp://dis.sagepub.com/cgi/alertshttp://dis.sagepub.com/subscriptionshttp://dis.sagepub.com/subscriptionshttp://dis.sagepub.com/subscriptionshttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navhttp://www.sagepub.co.uk/journalsPermissions.navhttp://www.sagepub.co.uk/journalsPermissions.navhttp://dis.sagepub.com/cgi/content/refs/8/4/475http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/cgi/content/refs/8/4/475http://www.sagepub.co.uk/journalsPermissions.navhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navhttp://dis.sagepub.com/subscriptionshttp://dis.sagepub.com/cgi/alerts
  • 7/28/2019 Modal Would in Police Interrogations

    2/28

    Facts, norms and dispositions:practical uses of the modal verbwould in police interrogations

    D E R E K E D WA R D SL O U G H BO R OU G H U N I V E RS I T Y

    A B S T R A C T Two uses of the modal verb wouldin police interrogation are

    examined. First, suspects use it to claim a disposition to act in ways

    inconsistent with whatever offence they are accused of. Second, police of ficers

    use it in challenging the suspects testimony, asking why a witness would lie.

    Both uses deploy a form of practical inferential reasoning from norms to facts,

    in the face of disputed testimony. The value ofwouldis that its semantics

    provide for a sense of back-dated predictability with regard to the actions in

    question. Further, although police off icers provide minimal acknowledgement

    of suspects uses of the term, suspects tend to provide a response when police

    officers use it. This difference is explained by the dif ferent actions being done in

    each case normative self assessments by suspects, and challenges by police

    officers and their interactional and institutional relevance in and for police

    pursuit of factual testimony.

    K E Y W O R D S : conversation analysis, dispositions, modality, moral character, police

    interrogation, would

    Introduction

    Our topic is a specific, recurrent use of the modal verb would in police

    interrogations. These are cases where a speaker formulates an actors

    dispositions (in this case, what they generally would or would not do), in the

    context of disputed testimony about having done something specific. The focus ison recorded interactional practices in which wouldregularly occurs, rather than

    on the formal semantics and pragmatics ofwouldas a type of modal verb. That is

    to say, there are other terms that may serve similar interactional practices

    (including specific uses of should, will, and going to), and other uses of wouldthan

    those explored here (e.g. Would you pass the salt?). The prime concern is with

    how would is recurrently used in handling accountability, in and for police

    interrogation. The relevance of police interrogation is not that these practices are

    A RT I C L E 475

    Discourse StudiesCopyright 2006

    SAGE Publications.(London, Thousand Oaks,

    CA and New Delhi)www.sagepublications.com

    Vol 8(4): 475501.10.1177/1461445606064830

    by Sorin Ciutacu on October 31, 2009http://dis.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/
  • 7/28/2019 Modal Would in Police Interrogations

    3/28

    restricted to that environment; indeed, they may also occur in mundane talk,and in settings such as court rooms and family therapy, which are fertile

    environments for disputation about personal actions, events, and responsibility

    for those events. But police interrogation appears to be a particularly relevant

    setting, given the prime orientation of participants toward eliciting, offering,

    examining and defending accounts of actions and their intentionality.

    The basic practice is exemplified in the following data segment, which is

    examined in more detail later in the article. S is a suspect being interrogated for

    his involvement in the theft of cigarettes from a shop.

    S: I didn push the woman or nothin, (0.5) I really

    did not do that.= Im not that type of person

    yknow what I me:an. .h Fair enough I stole the

    ciggies, (0.9) I wouldn hurt an old lady.

    The target expression I wouldn hurt an old lady occurs in the context of a

    dispute about Ss testimony. Ss deployment of would(in this case wouldnt) not

    only formulates something about his general disposition to act one way or another,

    but does so as a way of saying that he did not do the specific action of which he is

    accused that is, pushing (and in fact wounding) the woman in question. This is

    the essence of the practice: a generalized, normative and dispositional use of the

    modal would that provides a basis for asserting or denying a specific, disputed

    action.

    The analysis that follows focuses on two versions of the practice, the first

    generally deployed by S, the second by P (the police officer).

    1) Exemplified by I wouldnt hurt an old lady, this is the use by S of ageneralized dispositional formulation, a form of normative or moral self-

    assessment, in denying a specific accusation. This example takes the

    grammatical form of a negative-declarative use of I wouldnt; as such, it is

    designed for denial. Another form of the practice uses a rhetorical question,

    for example, What would I want to head butt an old bloke for? implying

    that he would not, and therefore did not. The notion that this is a rhetorical

    question relies on its understandability as such, and also the absence in all of

    our examples of any direct answer to it.

    2) The police officer P also has available a similar practice, typically something

    like Why would she say that you did?, where she (or whoever) is the

    producer of the testimony that S is denying. The grammar is an

    interrogative-affirmative use of the modal would, designed to counter (or

    question) a prior statement or implication. When used by police

    interrogators, it counters the suggestion or implication that a witness may

    have given false testimony against the accused. The suspect S generally

    provides an answer.

    Examining these interactional practices contributes to several broad fields of

    study. First, it throws specific light on how police interrogations work, both as a

    476 Discourse Studies 8(4)

    by Sorin Ciutacu on October 31, 2009http://dis.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/
  • 7/28/2019 Modal Would in Police Interrogations

    4/28

    domain of mundane reasoning and social interaction, and also as a domainwhere the specific business of the institutional setting gets done that is, eliciting

    and exploring testimony and counter-testimony, their factual basis, and their

    relevance to whatever crime category S is accused of. For example, Ss denial of

    having pushed and hurt the shopkeeper, supported by his assertion of a

    disposition not to do so, is a key feature in resisting the accusation of robbery in

    favour of the less severe offence to which he confesses, which is theft. Second,

    the study extends discursive-psychological studies of the importance of

    managing stake and interest in factual disputes (Edwards and Potter, 1992),

    and related studies of how scripts and dispositions feature in everyday

    reasoning about factual narratives and their accountability (Edwards, 1995,

    1997). Would is one of a range of scripting devices (Edwards, 1994) that

    formulate a persons recurrent actions and tendencies, as a basis for inferring orimplying their character. Examining situated uses of wouldis therefore part of a

    general interest in how mundane practical reasoning invokes a range of

    psychological states and characteristics of persons, often tied to the central,

    defining business of whatever everyday or institutional setting they occur in

    (Edwards and Potter, 2001; Sneijder and te Molder, 2005). Third, the study is

    located with regard to ethnomethodological and conversation-analytic studies of

    mundane reasoning, particularly in legal settings (e.g. Atkinson and Drew,

    1979; Komter, 1995, 1997; Lynch and Bogen, 2005; Pollner, 1987; Travers and

    Manzo, 1997; Watson, 1997), exploring in particular the ways in which people

    use norms to locate or decide facts. In that regard, this is a case study of the use

    of normative inferences in linking factual reality to psychological states, motives

    and dispositions, as part of an understandable, inference-rich, expectable world.In conversation-analytic mode, talk is examined here as a domain of interaction-

    ally and sequentially performed and occasioned social practices.

    A fourth domain, less directly relevant to the analysis offered here, is

    linguistic studies of modality. Linguistic treatments (e.g. Bybee and Fleischman,

    1995; Palmer, 2001) focus mainly on classifying and distinguishing the range of

    modal expressions within and across languages, and describing their

    grammatical functions. Modal expressions include a range of auxiliary verbs in

    English, such as ought, will, would, could, can, might, should, and may. Standard

    classifications of modal meanings include epistemic (factual, what we can know),

    logical (what must be the case), and deontic uses of ought, should, must, etc., that

    express concepts such as obligation and necessity. Palmer (2001) provides a

    finer-grained distinction between two kinds of event modality, deontic (externalto the person: constraints, permission, etc.) and dynamic (internal to the person:

    ability, willingness, etc.). In those terms, it is practices using dynamic event

    modality that we are mostly examining here, although when it comes to

    analysing actual, situated practices of accountability there is typically a range of

    epistemic, deontic and/or dispositional considerations at stake at any one time.1

    Whereas linguistic studies present examples in the form of single-sentence

    instances, invented or selected as good exemplars of the logical type they

    Edwards: Facts, norms and dispositions 477

    by Sorin Ciutacu on October 31, 2009http://dis.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/
  • 7/28/2019 Modal Would in Police Interrogations

    5/28

    illustrate, studies of talk-in-interaction of the kind presented here focus on thesocial actions performed, and the interactional relevancies managed by their use.

    Although it has not been explicitly picked out for systematic analysis, there

    are various useful observations and data segments in the literature on courtroom

    and police interrogations, on participants uses of would. It occurs as a way of

    formulating actors dispositions, in a suspects or witnesss defence of what they

    did or did not do. Lynch and Bogen (2005) make relevant observations on Oliver

    Norths answers to questions in the Iran-Contra hearings, where North avoided

    providing factual answers about what he did, which would lay those factual

    descriptions open to cross-examination, in favour of what he generally does, or

    would do. Also Benneworth (2004) notes, in a study of police interviews with

    suspected paedophile offenders, examples where rather than claiming the

    offence didnt happen because I was doing this . . . the suspect is contesting theaccount with the allegation is implausible because the incident would not have

    happened (p. 127). The research literature also contains examples such as the

    following, in a police officers courtroom response to a lawyers suggestion that

    he failed to take action against an incipiently violent crowd (Atkinson and Drew,

    1979: 150):

    C: You were in a position to observe that?

    W: Yes, but not in a position to carry out the action

    I would have liked.

    Komter (1995: 1189) notes that;

    the device of corroborating ones version of the events by pointing out discrepancies

    between the accusation and what is generally held to be true is very common in the

    courtroom. This is often presented by way of conditional clauses:

    If I had wanted to rob her, I would have been able to just take the money then.

    If I had wanted to kill him, I wouldnt have asked everybody where he lived. If I had needed the money, I would have asked my mother.

    As in the present study, Komters examples are normative-dispositional uses of

    would, used in making plausible the suspects claims about the specific actions of

    which s/he is accused by appealing to what is generally held to be true.

    The following analysis examines two sequentially organized practices

    involving use of the modal would, in which normative-dispositional appeals are

    made, both by suspects and by officers during police interrogation. The aim is to

    examine the interactional contexts in which these uses occur, the kinds ofpractical reasoning they do, their combination with other features of talk at

    those junctures, and the nature and bases of any differences between suspects

    and police officers practices. The analysis is divided into two main sections: first,

    suspects self-assessments, where they formulate their own character within a

    moral or normative order; and second, police officers use of the term with regard

    to the normative-dispositional basis of contrary witness testimony. The data

    come from a British corpus of 142 police interrogations, sampling a range of

    478 Discourse Studies 8(4)

    by Sorin Ciutacu on October 31, 2009http://dis.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/
  • 7/28/2019 Modal Would in Police Interrogations

    6/28

    crimes, suspects and police officers, recorded by the police themselves as aroutine part of interrogation, and subsequently made available to a research

    project into neighbour and community conflict.2 Data are transcribed according

    to Jeffersons (2004) conventions for conversation analysis. Names, places and

    other identifying details have been altered to preserve the anonymity of all

    participants.

    Suspects uses of first person would

    The data for this first section are examples of Ss first-person (that is, I rather

    than second-person you or third-person he, she, they, etc.) uses of would

    and wouldnt. These are occasions where S proposes for him/herself a

    generalized, dispositional principle or tendency that counters the accusation thatS did some specific action. The item I wouldn hurt an old lady, that was used for

    illustration in the Introduction, was taken from extract 1. I will first examine this

    extract in some detail, and then pursue various generic features of it across a

    further set of extracts across a range of suspects and interviewers.

    (1) PW:1:15

    1 P: But she said (0.2) that she was pushed backwards

    2 by yourself.= Now Ive been to see this lady

    3 yesterday. .hhh And at the (.) bottom: r:ight hand

    4 side of her back (0.4) shes got a (.) brui:se

    5 about the size about a fifty pence piece.=

    6 S: =Well then somebody else has done that mate.

    7 I wouldnI wouldnt do that. No Ill admit to8 stealin the ciggies, right .hh but they were on the

    9 counter, .h I did not jump over no counter for them.

    10 (0.3)

    11 P: NO I [DIDnt say you jumped over a count[er.

    12 S: [I- [I didn

    13 even go behind the counter for them.= I didn push

    14 the woman or nothin, (0.5) I really did not do

    15 that.= Im not that type of person yknow what I

    16 me:an. .h Fair enough I stole the ciggies, (0.9)

    17 I wouldn hurt an old lady.

    18 (0.5)

    19 P: [Right. ]

    20 S: [ No. ] (.) Not a chance.=

    Let us first note various components of the extract, considered as a sequence

    of actions. At line 1, P states a but-prefaced objection to Ss prior account of his

    actions (omitted here for the sake of brevity, but see lines 47). P says that Ss

    accuser, this lady (the female shopkeeper), has claimed (she said) that S pushed

    her, this being the action that caused a bruise (lines 45) that P himself has seen

    (lines 2 and 3). Let us say, then, that in lines 15 P presents contradictory

    testimony, and some related evidence, against Ss story. At line 6, S immediately

    Edwards: Facts, norms and dispositions 479

    by Sorin Ciutacu on October 31, 2009http://dis.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/
  • 7/28/2019 Modal Would in Police Interrogations

    7/28

    (in a latched turn) denies his accusers account, by invoking some other unknownperpetrator. Note how S selects the womans testimony (that S pushed her) as

    deniable, rather than Ps observation of the bruise. That leaves the matter as Ss

    word against hers: a matter of contrary testimony. At line 7, S produces the first-

    person generalized dispositional expression I wouldnt do that, where the

    significance for S of wouldnt is marked by its repetition with raised pitch (a type

    of self-initiated self-repair: Schegloff et al., 1977). So the use of wouldnt is a

    displayed feature of Ss account (cf. Komter, 1997, on the accused persons

    orientations to their own character within a moral order, in the very different

    action of expressing remorse in a courtroom).

    In lines 714, S reiterates his testimony that he stole the cigarettes, along

    with the factual denial that he went behind the counter and pushed the shop-

    keeper. They were on the counter specifies that he was able to pick the cigarettesup without either going behind the counter, or assaulting the woman. S

    formulates (cf. Heritage and Watson, 1979), as a gist of what he is saying, I

    really did not do that (lines 1415). That is, he emphatically denies the specific

    offence that he is accused of. At line 15, S makes a first-person generalized self

    assessment: Im not that type of person, where the sense is of a general

    disposition on his part not to do the kind of action of which he is accused. At line

    17, having again conceded that he stole the cigarettes, S reiterates his

    generalized dispositional wouldnt. This time S specifies just what he wouldnt do,

    in the form of a generalized version of the offence of which he is accused, hurt

    an old lady.

    These features of Ss uses ofwouldcombine with other features of the extract.

    For example, what makes his action-formulation generalized is not only the itemwouldnt rather than didnt, but also the generalized membership category old lady

    (rather than the specific shopkeeper herself), the indefinite article an old lady

    (i.e. any old lady, rather than the old lady), and the semantically open verb hurt

    rather than the more specific descriptions already in play (push, bruise, etc.).

    Clearly S is at pains to provide a generalized, dispositional, normatively under-

    standable basis for his version of his actions (cf. Jayyusi, 1984, on how member-

    ship categories are used in the production of moral accountability).

    Another feature of the extract is how, at lines 1819, P provides a minimal

    acknowledgement of Ss dispositional claim at 17, and does not directly pursue

    it. This is a recurring feature in the data under examination, which I will return

    to later. Yet P does offer a challenge to something else, at line 11. Notably, this is

    not a challenge to Ss dispositional would-based self-assessments but, rather, to aformulation that S offers, of what he is accused of doing, that he did not jump

    over no counter. P offers a correction: jump over is not the witnesss actual

    description, such that S is denying something of which he is not accused. The

    significance of this sequence is that it displays on Ps part an orientation to

    establishing the facts of what happened, including making direct, explicit

    challenges to Ssfactual testimony. In police terms, the bases for that are material

    evidence (lines 35) and witness testimony about witnessable events. In contrast

    480 Discourse Studies 8(4)

    by Sorin Ciutacu on October 31, 2009http://dis.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/
  • 7/28/2019 Modal Would in Police Interrogations

    8/28

    to that, P offers no challenge to Ss generalized, normative self-assessments, atthose junctures where they are produced at line 7 following the possibly

    complete TCU I Iwouldnt do that.3 and following the self-assessments in lines

    1517.

    The central observation about extract 1, then, around which the rest of the

    analysis hinges, is Ss use of a generalized, dispositional would as a way of

    denying having done some specific action, in the face of contradictory testimony.

    I will return to the theme of Ps responses, and their interactional import, in the

    course of examining further examples.

    Extract 2 comes from a different interrogation with a different S and P. Before

    the extract begins, S has persistently denied accusations of threatening and

    verbally abusing a neighbour. In the extract itself, S denies head-butting the man,

    and in making that denial, deploys a first-person dispositional would(wha wd I. . . in line 14).

    (2) PN:33:7

    1 P: Hes sayin that when youve walked towar:ds

    2 im youve leaned forward and head butted im

    3 on is nose.

    4 (0.5)

    5 P: Has that happen:ed

    6 (0.2)

    7 S: Wha- Ive it im:.

    8 (0.2)

    9 P: Youve head butted im. Youve lunged forward

    10 and [head butted im.11 S: [NO::: no I aint at a:ll.

    12 (0.3)

    13 S: Unless ycn ge any proof then: (1.5) Iv- (.)

    14 headbutted im wha wd I wanna head butt an

    15 old bloke fo:r.

    16 (2.0)

    17 S: Shtu:pi:d.

    18 (9.2)

    Again we can identify a sequence of component actions that bear comparison

    to those of extract 1. P puts to S (line 5) a witnesss accusation (Hes sayin. . .

    lines 13), that S has in fact previously denied. As with most of the extracts we

    are examining, this follows a repeated line of questioning involving contradictorytestimony between the accused S and Ps quotations from an accusing witness,

    who is generally the alleged victim. Ss denial of the specific offence, explicit at line

    11, is prefigured at line 7 by Ss ironic, high-pitched and emphatic formulation of

    what he is accused of. Note how the generalized word hit substitutes in Ss

    formulation for the specific action description previously used by P and the

    witness youve leaned forward and head butted im on is nose. In denying the

    specific offence, therefore, S is already starting to generalize it as a category of

    Edwards: Facts, norms and dispositions 481

    by Sorin Ciutacu on October 31, 2009http://dis.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/
  • 7/28/2019 Modal Would in Police Interrogations

    9/28

    actions. The raised pitch and preceding Wha- (line 7), convey a sense ofsurprise, confusion or incomprehension at being accused of such a thing.4

    At line 13, S implies the absence of definitive evidence to decide the matter; it

    is the witnesss testimony against Ss. At lines 1415, S deploys a first-person

    dispositional would, with regard to the accusation. In this case, it is an

    interrogative why would I? (more precisely, what would I . . . for?) rather than

    declarative I wouldnt. But it performs the same kind of action, of denying he did

    it on the basis that he would not do it. Again, Ss normative-dispositional would

    combines with a generalized membership category formulation an old bloke to

    describe the neighbour. Like with an old lady in extract 1, the indefinite article,

    and general category bloke, provide the sense that he wouldnt head-butt any

    old bloke as such, rather than just this particular one.

    Overall, extracts 1 and 2 contain a sequence of actions that can be typified asfollows.

    1) the establishment of conflicting testimony regarding a specific offence;

    2) Ss use of a first-person normative-dispositional would, which may combine

    with the use of generalized person types or categories;

    3) minimal if any acknowledgement, but no challenge by P of Ss dispositional

    claim.

    It is important to note that these actions are performed and/or oriented to by

    the participants. The conflicting nature of the available testimony is produced as

    such by S and/or P, rather than merely things noticeable by the analyst/reader. It

    is in the context of having produced those things, as a kind of testimonial or

    evidential stand-off, that S deploys the dispositional would. That is what providesfor the items sequential position and relevance, and also the practical logic of its

    use, as a proposal for how Ss version of the facts under dispute can be inferred

    and known. There are other ways available to suspects for dealing with contrary

    witness testimony and evidence, of course, including the use of precisely

    designed alternative descriptions of witnesses versions (Drew, 1992); it is a

    particular practice we are examining here, rather than all and always what S

    may do.

    In the further extracts that follow, I examine how robust these general

    features may be, and how they provide a framework for how S and P deal with

    the specifics of each case. Relevantly to extract 3, S is a teenage boy who, having

    been legally banned from entering a local post office, is now accused of causing

    further harassment there. The extract follows detailed descriptions of Ss allegedactions: stealing sweets, disruptive and abusive behaviour.

    (3) PN:34:6 21:30

    1 P: A:nd ythen put (.) a bungee. (1.0) A ( )

    2 bungee round the doo:r ttry an stop people

    3 [getting in the ] shop. Dyremember that.

    4 S: [N o: : : : . ]

    482 Discourse Studies 8(4)

    by Sorin Ciutacu on October 31, 2009http://dis.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/
  • 7/28/2019 Modal Would in Police Interrogations

    10/28

    5 S: No:.6 (.)

    7 S: W-wa- why would I put bungee on the doo:r.

    8 (5.6) ((S is next to speak))

    Again, at lines 13 we have the initial establishment of a contradiction

    between Ss testimony and Ps quotations from a witnesss statement. P puts to S

    what the shopkeeper claims S did, and S rejects it using an emphatic, elongated

    denial at line 4, in overlap with P, and repeated in the clear at line 5 in answer to

    Dyremember that. As with most of our examples, the accusations made by P

    are based in quotations from a written witness statement, that S has been

    persistently denying for some time prior to where the extract begins. S then

    produces, at line 7, a first-person would in support of his factual denial. Ss

    stuttering start W-wa- why helps convey a sense of puzzlement, of S struggling

    with the sheer implausibility of the idea; why would he, or anyone do such a

    thing? Again, P produces no explicit uptake (line 8), despite having provided a

    possible answer already, at lines 23: ttry an stop people getting in the shop.

    Although there is not space here to explore systematic differences across

    many examples, there is probably a basis, or more than one basis, for the choice

    between the interrogative Why would I? of extracts 2 and 3, and the declarative I

    wouldnt used elsewhere. In the case of the interrogative form, the absence of an

    answer from P reinforces the sense of it as a rhetorical question in other

    words, an implicit assertion, and not as such requiring an answer. The sense of

    these questions as rhetorical is reinforced by their use with ironic repeats of the

    accusation: head butt an old bloke (extract 2, lines 1415, with the additional

    ridiculing of Shtu:pi:d, line 17), and put bungee on the doo:r (extract 3, line 7).

    The choice may also be based on a difference in answerability. For example, in

    extract 2 S is not being accused of butting the man in order to achieve some

    further goal, whereas in extract 1 S is accused of pushing the woman in order to

    rob her of cigarettes. So for S in extract 1 to ask Why would I? might hold

    greater prospect of being answered, by just the accusation he is at pains to refute

    that is, in order to accomplish the robbery. Nevertheless, whatever the grounds

    for choosing one form over the other, both forms assert a normative-dispositional

    basis for denying an accusation of having done some specific thing.

    Extract 4 provides another succinct example of our basic phenomenon.

    (4) PN:38:215

    1 P1: Right (.) so whos lying then.

    2 (0.4)

    3 P1: Cos one o yous lying arent they.=

    4 S: =I haven- (.) I haven said nothing I- (0.3)

    5 I wouldnt. yknow wha I mean.

    6 (0.4)

    7 S: ((sni [ffs))

    8 P1: [Well shes saying yhave.=

    Edwards: Facts, norms and dispositions 483

    by Sorin Ciutacu on October 31, 2009http://dis.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/
  • 7/28/2019 Modal Would in Police Interrogations

    11/28

    9 S: =I- (0.2) cant be doing with (0.2) the trouble.10 I wouldnt say nothing.

    11 P1: HHhhhhhhhhhh[hh.

    In extract 4 the general kinds of actions we are identifying are identifiable as

    follows. First, there is an unresolved testimonial conflict between S and an

    accusing witness, explicitly formulated by P as one o yous lying (line 3). The

    relevance of line 4 I haven said nothing is that S is currently accused of

    witness intimidation, which involves talking to a witness in an upcoming court

    case, in the face of a prior court instruction that he should stay away from her.

    So S denies the specific action of which he is accused (line 4). S then supports his

    denial (again, this extract is the culmination of a series of repeated accusations

    and denials) with an emphatic first-person dispositional I wouldnt, framed as

    normatively recognizable: yknow wha I mean (line 5). In this case P does

    respond to Ss first-person dispositional would, but only to repeat the witnesss

    contradictory testimony (line 8). P specifically does not pursue the dispositional

    claim itself; in other words, there is no attempt by P to unpick or contradict Ss

    dispositional self-assessment as such. S then formulates an accountable basis for

    his dispositional claim (line 9) and re-asserts it (line 10). P responds with,

    literally, some ex-aspiration (line 11), but no pursuit of the topic.

    The further extracts (58) that follow, serve to flesh out the basic action

    sequence identified. There was no clear deviant case in the data sample but,

    rather, a range of specific instantiations and variations in detail, that show how

    the sequence provides a frame for an important and recurrent piece of practical

    reasoning deployed in these interrogations. In extract 5, S is a 17-year-old boyaccused of breaching a court-imposed ASBO (Anti-Social Behaviour Order), by

    assaulting a seven-year-old.

    (5) PN:40:1

    1 P: earlier on today on

    2 suspicion of assaultin (0.4) u::m (.) a seven

    3 year ol::d, (0.8) which is (.) u:h (.) Jeremy.

    4 (0.6)

    5 P: Dyknow (.) who Im talkin bout,

    6 (0.3)

    7 S: Yeh,

    8 (0.2)

    9 P: Okay, (0.7) an do yknow the incident Im

    10 talkin about.

    11 (0.2)

    12 S: Not at a:ll.

    13 (0.6)

    14 P: Not at all.

    15 S: No.

    16 (0.9)

    17 S: Im not gonna beat a seven year old up.=

    484 Discourse Studies 8(4)

    by Sorin Ciutacu on October 31, 2009http://dis.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/
  • 7/28/2019 Modal Would in Police Interrogations

    12/28

    18 yknow what I mean.19 (0.2)

    20 S: I got morals.

    21 (0.2)

    22 S: s little kid.

    23 (0.7)

    24 P: A:lright, (0.8) so:: (...)

    Extract 5 contains the essential ingredients we have identified, that

    contextualize Ss use of the first-person dispositional modal in line 17. In this

    case, we have the variant not gonna rather than wouldnt5 (line 17), but it works

    in essentially the same way: that is, to propose that the specific action being

    denied (assaulting the boy) is an instance of a general category of actions that S

    is not disposed to do. That general disposition is both personal (S would not do it)and normative (it is the kind of thing that nobody should do). The normative

    sense is reinforced, as in extracts 1 and 4, by a contiguous yknow what I mean

    (line 18) which appeals to its recognizability as a claim, and also by Ss

    sequentially next, personal subscription to a moral order (line 20). As in extracts

    1 and 2, Ss dispositions are invoked with regard to a generalized category of

    relevant objects, a seven year old (line 17, again using the indefinite article),

    and little kid (line 22). Note that there are alternatives available for describing

    the boy, including Jeremy, him, the lad, etc., but S is doing generalization.

    Again, P (lines 234) does not at this point attempt to unpick or question Ss

    generalized normative-dispositional avowals.

    The general action sequence is further instantiated in extract 6. Prior to the

    extract, S has been accused of saying to her neighbour, among other insults andthreats, youre fucking dead, which S denies saying. Instead, S admits to

    verbals on both sides, framed as a normal kind of two-sided, reciprocal swearing

    and abuse.

    (6) PN:16:8

    1 P: (...) shes sayin that youve threatened to kill her.

    2 (0.3)

    3 S: N [ o:, ]

    4 P: [an then ] youre dead.

    5 (.)

    6 S: N [o:.

    7 P: [Whatever.

    8 (.)9 S: No. Tha [t is:

    10 P: [Is there any way at all you couldve said

    11 that in the heat [o the moment.=

    12 S: [No::.

    13 P: =[In the heat of an argument

    14 S: =[Not even if I was (fightin) no.

    15 (.)

    Edwards: Facts, norms and dispositions 485

    by Sorin Ciutacu on October 31, 2009http://dis.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/
  • 7/28/2019 Modal Would in Police Interrogations

    13/28

    16 S:

    An I wouldnt (even) say that.17 (0.5)

    18 S: I wouldnt say that.

    19 (0.6)

    20 S: I [ve- Ive never said tha*t to *er

    21 P: [(Okay)

    22 (0.5)

    23 S: when weve had an argument mm:?

    24 (0.8)

    25 S: Ever.

    The action elements that we have identified are exemplified in extract 6 as

    follows:

    1) the production of contrary testimonies regarding the particular offence accusation (lines 1 and 4) and denial (lines 3 and 6).

    2) Ss generalizing, first-person dispositional use ofwouldnt at lines 16 and 18.

    3) minimal receipt/acknowledgement by P at line 21, in a turn following

    straight after Ss repeated clause (and TCU) containing wouldnt, and in

    overlap with As starting a new turn.

    We may also note a range of particular features in extract 6 that enrich that

    bare structure. As in all our examples, it is the interrogations crucial business

    that is being dealt with here the actual criminal offence with which S is being

    charged, in this case, the accusation of having made threats to kill. Note how in

    lines 713 P pursues Ss factual denial that she actually said those things, but

    typically, as noted, does not pursue Ss dispositional wouldclaims starting at line16. A difference is emerging across these extracts, between how P responds to Ss

    factual claims and denials, and how P responds to Ss generalized normative-

    dispositional avowals. Another feature of extract 6 is the way that P, in

    responding to Ss factual denials, starts to generalize his interest in what she may

    have said: the expressions whatever (line 7) and any way at all (line 10) signal

    that the exactness of the witnesss quotation of S is not what requires denial but,

    rather, the kindof thing S may have said, that would make it recognizable as a

    case of threatening to kill. It is a generalizing, categorizing move by P that

    precedes Ss own move to a generalized disposition-based denial she wouldnot

    say such a thing. Another feature of the extract, and one we will encounter in

    other data, is how S moves from the dispositional wouldnt say to the factual Ive

    never said . . . (line 20). In moving from dispositions back to facts, S effectivelymakes the link to which all of our generalized dispositionals are oriented, which

    is the work they do in denying the specific actions with which S is being charged.

    In extract 7, a middle-aged Asian man6 is accused of having opened the boot

    (i.e. trunk) of his neighbours car, and of having deliberately scratched the car

    when walking past it.

    486 Discourse Studies 8(4)

    by Sorin Ciutacu on October 31, 2009http://dis.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/
  • 7/28/2019 Modal Would in Police Interrogations

    14/28

    (7) PN:17:61 S: (...) You know I dont understand this sir.

    2 (0.3)

    3 S: I mean Im (not daft) I mean Ive worked (0.5)

    4 Ive worked what I want to and God has given me

    5 what Ive got.= What I want.

    6 P: Mm.

    7 (0.3)

    8 S: I mean (0.3) opening somebodys boot I mean *u*u

    9 *I *a*a*a *I would feel ashamed of myself.

    10 (0.3)

    11 P: Okay. .hhh What about the scratch.

    Extract 7 begins after a sequence in which P has accused S of the offences,

    based on testimony of Ss neighbour, and S has denied the charges. So again, we

    have a situation involving an unresolved conflict of testimony. S starts the extract

    by expressing incomprehension (line 1) and setting up a dispositional basis (lines

    45) for not doing what he is accused of. At line 8, S quotes the specific action he

    is accused of (cf. the ironic repeats in extract 2, lines 7 and 14, and extract 3, line

    7), and immediately follows it with a first-person dispositional would(line 9). In

    this case, S fuses his personal dispositions with a morally enhanced normative

    sense: I would feel ashamed of myself. Overall, Ss wouldaccount is produced as

    part of trying to understand the sense of what he is accused of, on the basis of

    how anyone in his position, with all that God has provided, along with a sense of

    shame, might be thought capable such a thing. He offers normative notions of

    motive and act, to warrant a factual denial, that he committed the specific action

    of opening his neighbours car boot. Ps response is a slightly delayed, final-

    intonation, softly spoken Okay, followed not by pursuit of whether S opened the

    boot, or would feel ashamed, but by a topical move to the second factual

    accusation, that S also scratched the neighbours car.

    Let us conclude this section with a final example. In extract 8, S has been

    accused of breaching a second harassment order, which is a courts binding

    instruction to stay away from an ex-partner that S has allegedly been pursuing.

    P is referring in line 1 to the accusers statement.

    (8) PN:27:7

    1 P: Basic its got here that .hhh I was at ho:me in my

    2 f lat when I heard a knock at the- (0.3) at my doo:r.

    3 I then heard John shout.hhh Come tthdoor so I can4 see your face.

    5 (0.5)

    6 P: [And do you (say [ )

    7 S: [No thats not- [( ) that thats one thing

    8 that- thats not my- I wouldnt come out with sh-

    9 (0.2) come to the door n show my face thats not-

    10 .hhh Id say (.) Sharon come to the door I wouldnt

    Edwards: Facts, norms and dispositions 487

    by Sorin Ciutacu on October 31, 2009http://dis.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/
  • 7/28/2019 Modal Would in Police Interrogations

    15/28

    11 mention Sharon come to the door and show my face.= .h12 Thats not my words I wouldnt use them wo(h)rd(h)s.

    13 [.hh Ill swear on me mothers life I (>hope me=

    14 P: [(Okay,)

    15 S: =motherd

  • 7/28/2019 Modal Would in Police Interrogations

    16/28

    delay). As we have noted, Ps receipts of Ss would expressions are typicallyminimal acknowledgement tokens rather than direct challenges.

    Extract 9 comes 25 turns after extract 1, in the interrogation concerning the

    robbery/theft of cigarettes from a shop.

    (9) PW:1:17

    1 P: So shes implicated that youve gone (0.3) through

    2 that gap,

    3 S: Wro [ng

    4 P: [an youve pushed her (0.8) right, (.) and

    5 shes gone backwards.

    6 (0.2)

    7 S: Not at [all.

    8 P: [And (0.5) hit against (.)as I said (.)9 the bruise are there Ive seen the bruises Ive

    10 asked her to go tthe doctorn of course hell (0.3)

    11 hell confirm (.) those as well, .hhh I cant see

    12 (0.5) why (0.6) this lady: (0.3) would wanna (0.7)

    13 [lie ]

    14 S: [Nei ]ther can I?

    15 (0.4)

    Ps third-person use of would (line 12), like Ss first-person uses, invokes

    normative and personal dispositions to do or say things. In this case it is

    formulated as a problem for Ps efforts to understand, against a normative

    backdrop of understandable actions, Ss denials: I cant see (0.5) why this lady:

    (0.3) would wanna (0.7) lie (lines 1113). The assertion I cant see whyproposes a problem with, and challenge to, Ss story.8 The prior context is again

    the establishment of contradictory factual testimony (lines 17) along with some

    circumstantial evidence (lines 911). Again, we are finding ways in which

    common sense practical reasoning makes links between norms, dispositions, and

    factual accounts. P uses woulddispositionally and normatively with regard to the

    shopkeeper; why would she invent this story if it were not true? P generates a

    sense of stake or motive what is in it for her to wanna make this stuff up? Ss

    response (line 14) overlaps the end of Ps query. Rather than leaving Ps why

    would she as a knock-down counter to his own story, S treats it as a puzzle for him

    too (echoed in the high-rising, questioning pitch contour of line 14).

    Extract 10 begins just after a sequence in which P has quoted a witness who

    claims to have overheard a telephone call in which S was swearing and makingthreats to kill Ss neighbour.

    (10) PN:11:9

    1 S: (...) but as for- (.) sayin thIm gonna put a

    2 bomb through yr doo:r (1.1) no.

    3 (0.2)

    4 S: I dont do things like that.= I know hes got (0.4)

    Edwards: Facts, norms and dispositions 489

    by Sorin Ciutacu on October 31, 2009http://dis.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/
  • 7/28/2019 Modal Would in Police Interrogations

    17/28

    5 kids himself which stay round there6 (1.8)

    7 S: and look a hes- (0.4) look at the size aim es

    8 six foot fou:r (0.4) Im five foot seven,

    9 (1.2)

    10 P: Bt ydid make more than one phone c[all

    11 S: [Yeh I phoned

    12 im back bu I didnt (0.4) I made n- (1.0) no:

    13 sound on the pho:ne i-it lasted probably: (0.7) a

    14 s:plit second- one to two secon:ds,

    15 (0.2)

    16 P: Why wou [ld this lady say then. that she heard=

    17 S: [An uh

    18 P: =these things?=

    19 S: =U:m (.) because ath- u- I th- theres been a feu:d20 in Becknall Cou:rt f r a long time (...)

    The actions in extract 10, prior to and following Ps use of wouldin line 16,

    are again similar to those in extract 9. There is a sequence of accusation and

    denial, formulated here in Ss first turn (lines 12). Additionally in this extract we

    have S offering a generalized dispositional basis for his denial: I dont do things

    like that (line 4), along with a normatively plausible basis for that denial (lines

    48). Then P presents further non-definitive circumstantial evidence against S

    (line 10), which S acknowledges and re-formulates as irrelevant (lines 1114). It

    is at this juncture that P issues the third-person dispositional challenge: Why

    would this lady say then . . . (lines 1618). As also in extract 9, S provides an

    answer that retains the questionability of the witnesss motives for giving falsetestimony. Here in extract 10, this takes the more substantial form of a long-term

    feud (lines 1920).

    A pattern is emerging across Ps uses of third-person normative-dispositional

    would, in challenging Ss testimony. As with Ss first-person dispositionals, a

    stand-off is first established between S and a quoted witness (who is often but

    may not be the alleged victim), in their contradictory factual testimony con-

    cerning the alleged offence. There may also be some circumstantial, that is,

    inconclusive, evidence against S, which S refutes or minimizes. In response to Ss

    denials, P produces a third-person dispositional would, framed as a normative

    question, or expression of puzzlement, as to why the witness might lie (i.e. it

    invokes the witnesss possible motive, stake or interest in saying something false:

    cf. Komter, 1995). Unlike with Ss own first-position wouldexpressions that wereexamined in section 1, that tended to elicit no direct response from P, Ps third-

    position dispositional question about the witness elicits an attempt by S to deal

    with it. Let us examine some further examples before returning to that point.

    In extract 11, S has been accused of harassing and threatening her

    neighbour and her neighbours children, a charge which S is in the process of

    denying.

    490 Discourse Studies 8(4)

    by Sorin Ciutacu on October 31, 2009http://dis.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/
  • 7/28/2019 Modal Would in Police Interrogations

    18/28

    (11) PN:46:71 S (...) Iv- (.) kept meself tmeself, (0.3) kept in-

    2 .hh when I see them, (.) yes, Im angry at them an

    3 I call them thieves.= bu thats it.

    4 (1.0)

    5 P So (1.2) w-why: the*n l*astly about thi- why: .hh

    6 (0.6) hhh. Probly know your answer.= But Im gon

    7 ask the question anyway. .hhh that

    10 allegedlyve been made by you.

    11 S Because she kno:ws the system. Shes tryina get

    12 me kicked out by the council. cos she wants to

    13 stay cos she gets (cash in hand) down the pub.

    S formulates the actions, for which her neighbour is accusing her of

    harassment, as merely getting angry and calling them thieves (because, she

    elsewhere asserts, that is what they are), but that is all there is to it; as she puts

    it, bu thats it. So again, we have contrary testimony directly concerning the

    offence with which S is charged. In this case, Ps third-person would question

    (lines 710) is interestingly framed as a question he is apparently bound to ask,

    and to which he can anticipate the answer (lines 67). Note that we are some

    way into the interrogation, throughout which P has displayed a close familiarity

    with Ss case. The notion offered by P, that he knows her probable answer but Im

    gon ask the question anyway, orients to the questions normative askability in

    these circumstances, in whatever way those circumstances should be understood.

    I take those circumstances to be some combination of: unresolved conflictingtestimony, inconclusive evidence to decide it, and doing proper police procedure,

    including getting the question and Ss answer into the taped record of the

    interrogation. Additionally, Ps expression l*astly about thi- (line 5)9 orients to it

    as a sequential item, as a possibly final question, or last in a series. In breaking off

    from asking the dispositional why would . . .? question, and inserting this lastly

    . . . phrase before continuing (see the transcriptional detail of line 5), P displays

    an orientation to the would-questions sequential placement as not only

    following, but also at the end of a sequence of factual interrogation and denial.

    Again, note that S does offer an answer to Ps wouldquestion, in the form of a

    dispositional or motivational account (lines 1113) essentially, that the witness

    has a self-interested motive in getting S evicted from her council house.

    Extract 12 is several minutes further into the interrogation from which

    extract 5 was taken, in which a 17-year-old denies assaulting a much younger

    boy.

    (12) PN:40:6

    1 P: So why: should this kid then whos seven

    2 years ol:d, who lives on your roa:d, whos-

    3 lived there: f seven year:s, to my knowledge

    Edwards: Facts, norms and dispositions 491

    by Sorin Ciutacu on October 31, 2009http://dis.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/
  • 7/28/2019 Modal Would in Police Interrogations

    19/28

    4

    .hhh u:m

    why should he suddenly sa:y that5 you: have done- (0.3) well. basically

    6 assaulted im.

    7 S: I dont kno:w.

    8 (0.9)

    9 P: Well theres gotta be a reason [for it

    10 S: [HONestly I

    11 DON- (.) if I knew Id tell yer. Yknow

    12 whaI mea:n.

    13 (0.4)

    14 S: Ive been honest with yer. ( )

    15 Ob [viously theres a reas- ]

    16 P: [Because it turns ] ou*t=

    17 S: =THERE AINT NO REASon yeh because I swear

    18 on my mums fuckin li:fe I didnt do fuck all19 I aint seen that little lad,

    20 (0.8)

    21 S: Alright. (0.3) So I dont care what you thi:nk

    22 (.) whether you say th- (.) theres must be

    23 a reason why es sayin it there aint no

    24 fuckin reason, .h thaint nuthin.

    25 (0.2)

    26 S: That hes a little twat. thats what.

    27 (0.5)

    28 P: Why: dysay that.

    The modal variant in extract 12 is should(lines 1 and 4), but like would, this

    also conveys the sense of a normative-dispositional account being required forwhy this witness might lie. Again, it is Ss testimony being set against that of the

    boy victim/witness. In this case, P works to build the boys status as unmotivated

    to lie; he is a long-time neighbour, who has suddenly (line 4), which is to say in

    no way accounted for by S, accused S of assaulting him. Similarly the category

    this kid . . . whos seven years ol:d (lines 12) formulates the witness in

    categorial and innocent terms devoid of grudge or motive. Ss initial response at

    line 7, I dont kno:w bears comparison to extract 9, line 14 (Neither can I?),

    in which Ss response is to share Ps puzzlement. Effectively, S bats the question

    back, not as a problem for S, but as a puzzle about the witness. So we have two

    different implications in play, concerning the witnesss absent reasons for making

    false accusations. P implies that, having no reason to lie, the witness is telling the

    truth. For S, on the other hand, the absence of any evident reason to lie impliessome unknown reason (extract 12, lines 1012, 15), or else sheer irrationality

    (lines 1724).

    Ss eventual answer formulates the witness dispositionally, as a person whose

    reasons for saying things stem from character: hes a little twat (line 26). The

    coda thats what specifies hes a twat as the answer to the motivation puzzle,

    as to why he may have given false testimony. Formulating the boys nature also

    avoids addressing any notion of reciprocity on the boys part, for anything S may

    492 Discourse Studies 8(4)

    by Sorin Ciutacu on October 31, 2009http://dis.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/
  • 7/28/2019 Modal Would in Police Interrogations

    20/28

    have done to him. As a twat, he would tend to say scurrilous and unreliablethings. Again, Ps pursuit of this particular formulation (line 28) lends some

    credence to the notion that it is specifically the normative self-assessment uses of

    wouldthat are not pursued, rather than it being merely that police officers do not

    generally pursue things that Ss claim or deny.

    Extract 13 comes several minutes after extract 5, in an interrogation about

    alleged damage to a neighbours car, and opens with S making the kind of first-

    person modal-dispositional generalization we have previously examined. In this

    case, the modal term used is should (line 3), and again its normative appeal is

    reinforced with a yknow what I mean (line 6).

    (13) PN:17:9

    1 S: (...) Ive got two cars at home (.) [I mean why=

    2 P: [(I know)

    3 S: =should I be need (to be) open somebody elses car.

    4 (0.4)

    5 P: U [:h

    6 S: [>Yknow what I meanIm not7 saying< nine year olds dont lie because they do.8 (0.3)9 P: Children of all d- ages lie. .hhh But >what Im

    10 saying is< why would she (.) m- (0.5) say this11 about you. .h Its not- (0.2) i-its quite12 specific what shes saying.13 (0.4)

    14 P: Ykno:w, (0.2) shes saying ypu- (0.4) yhand15 downer pyjamas.16 (0.6)17 P: Shes saying you took Amandas nappy of f.18 (1.4)19 P: An felt her between the legs. .h An then shes20 talkin about you takin yr trousers down.=21 Shes quite specific.22 (0.9)23 P: An an why did she make this up about you.24 (0.4)25 S: Don kno:w.

    The sequence of actions in extract 14 is similar to the other extracts we are

    examining, but again the extract has its own interesting and telling details. Thereis, as we are finding generally, an initial presentation and rejection of witness

    testimony against S (lines 13), followed by Ps delivery of the third-person

    normative-dispositional would(lines 6 and 10), and eventually a response from S

    (line 25) that either refutes or, as in this case, leaves the puzzle unresolved. As we

    saw in dont know types of response in extracts 9 and 12, Ss high-rising and

    elongated intonation are important in conveying not merely ignorance or

    unresponsiveness to the question, but a sense of exasperation or puzzlement of

    his own. As in extract 9, P first frames it as a puzzle for P herself: I cant see why

    . . . (line 5), but then re-formulates it as a question, why would she . . . (line 10).

    As in extract 12, P provides some grounds for finding it hard to believe that the

    witness is lying; in this case, as with the boy cited in extract 12, we have the use

    of an age category, a nine year old gir:l (line 5), to characterize the witness(indefinitely a girl, rather than the particular girl Emily whose name they have

    been using). Further, P quotes graphic details from Emilys account (lines

    1420), whose quite specific nature is explicitly offered by P, both before and

    after, as the point of quoting those details (lines 12 and 21). These are specifics

    that, in Ps presentation of them, give Emilys testimony the ring of truth.

    Two additional features of extract 14 are worth noting, although they should

    be understood as adding complexity and options to the basic sequence, rather

    494 Discourse Studies 8(4)

    by Sorin Ciutacu on October 31, 2009http://dis.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/
  • 7/28/2019 Modal Would in Police Interrogations

    22/28

    than being exceptions to it. One feature is Ps insertion in lines 6 to 9, into theproduction of her why would? question, of a possible response to it (nine-year-

    olds lie), and a rejection of that response (but why this lie in particular). This,

    along with Ps citation of the quite specific details on which we have com-

    mented, may help account for Ss lack of room for manoeuvre at line 25.

    Another feature is the specific way the question is re-iterated by P at line 23; why

    did, rather than why would(cf. comments on extract 6, line 20). In fact, given that

    why wouldis an unanswered question still on the table, we can understand why

    didhere as a nice orientation to the whole point of asking why would. Across all

    of the examples we are analyzing, in both sections of this article, the

    dispositional would is deployed as a way of dealing with what did happen,

    actually, on some particular occasion, that being the criminal action that S is

    charged with. Indeed, that is the practical logic of the wouldturns following thefactual and testimonial contradictions of prior turns.

    We end this section with one further extract, but markedly different from the

    others, in that S replies no comment to all questions put to him concerning an

    accusation of assault on his accuser.

    (15) PN:14:4

    1 P: Why would- why would- (0.4) Tony Bla:ke. (.) O:nly

    2 yve not denied anything. (.) Youve noactually3 said no that didnt happen, so youve not denied or4 confirmed anything, .hhh youve said no comment so:5 (.) I Im sortf duty bound to ask you (0.4) further6 questions in relation to this. .hhh7 (7.2)

    8 P: Why would Tony Blake ma- make- make this up as- (.)9 if he is making it up if- (.) if youre all (.)

    10 saying that it didnt happen, which youre no:t. .hh

    11 But (.) why would he say this if i- if it isnt the

    12 case.= Why: (0.2) whats his motive. f comin out

    13 n n accusing you of this assault.

    14 (0.3)

    15 S: No comment,

    16 (18.3)

    The notable feature of extract 15 is how, in the absence of anything but no

    comment from S, P orients to the normative use and sequential relevance of the

    dispositional response, why wouldthe witness lie. We have noted that the normal

    sequential location of these third-person dispositional modals is after a denial, atestimonial stand-off, and perhaps a first-person dispositional I wouldnt by S.

    But here we have P producing the third-person dispositional anyway, despite Ss

    denial not occurring. The thing of interest, of course, is Ps orientation to it as

    something to say next, following such a denial. Note particularly how P formu-

    lates the absence of Ss denial (lines 24) prior to asking the dispositional why

    would . . . (line 8), and in fact breaks off at line 1 from an initial why would-, to

    insert his observations on Ss absent testimony. This shows an orientation by P,

    Edwards: Facts, norms and dispositions 495

    by Sorin Ciutacu on October 31, 2009http://dis.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/
  • 7/28/2019 Modal Would in Police Interrogations

    23/28

    marked by doing a repair involving a break-off, insertion and re-start, towardraising the dispositional why would (he) sequentially following Ss rejection of a

    witnesss testimony. Although P pointedly notes that S has neither denied nor

    confirmed the witnesss testimony, it is only in the event of a denial that the

    challenge why would he say this arises. Indeed, a normative basis for P asking

    this specific question, just here, is formulated P himself: he is sortf duty bound

    (line 5) to ask it.

    Summarizing section 2, we find a sequential orderliness across Ps uses of a

    third-person normative-dispositional modal would(and its variants), that bears

    comparison to Ss first-person uses in section 1. There is an initial, produced-as

    and oriented-to contradiction between the testimonies of S and a witness, with

    regard to the factual status of whatever specific actions S is being accused of. P

    formulates a problem for Ss denials, in the form of a question or puzzle as to whythe witness should lie. This may involve some descriptive building of the witnesss

    independence, innocence, or lack of motive. Unlike with Ss first-person modals,

    Ps third-person modals tend to elicit replies from S, either shared puzzlement or

    a dispositional account of why the witness might lie. In the concluding section of

    the article, that difference is explained in terms of the different action sequences

    being done, and in terms of orientations to normative practices of police

    interrogation with regard to factual testimony.

    Conclusion

    The focus of our analysis has been on a particular kind of discourse practice, or

    interactional practice, using the generic modal wouldor occasional variants suchas going to, will, might or should. Clearly those alternative terms are not

    semantically equivalent, and further work may reveal interactional differences in

    their uses. The point is that they are used sometimes in the same kinds of social

    practices, in constructing a normative, generalized, and dispositional basis for

    claims and challenges concerning some specific disputed action.

    Ss first-person normative-dispositional avowals using wouldoccur in action

    sequences as follows:

    1) the establishment of contradictory testimony between S and a witness;

    2) Ss generalized, normative self-assessment using would;

    3) minimal acknowledgement of 2), but no pursuit, by P.

    Ps third-person invocation of a witnesss disposition to lie occurs in actionsequences as follows:

    1) Ss denials of a witnesss accusatory testimony;

    2) Ps challenge, puzzling over why would the witness lie;

    3) Ss response, in the form of shared puzzlement at 2) or an account for it.

    We are now in a position to consider the difference between the third

    components of the two sequences. The key is that we are dealing with different

    496 Discourse Studies 8(4)

    by Sorin Ciutacu on October 31, 2009http://dis.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/
  • 7/28/2019 Modal Would in Police Interrogations

    24/28

    kinds of adjacency pairs. Ss would-based claims, whether grammaticallydeclarative (I wouldnt) or interrogative (why would I?), propose normative,

    generalized self-assessments. Although assessments in everyday talk normatively

    evoke second assessments (Pomerantz, 1984), our cases are special in being self-

    assessments, and in being produced in the context of police interrogation. The

    absence second assessments from P, whether agreeing or disagreeing with S, may

    partly be due to Ps having no independent grounds for providing a generalized

    assessment of Ss character, outside of the specific allegations being put.

    With regard to the special setting of police interrogation, we have also noted

    a strong orientation on Ps part to pursuing the details of factual evidence and

    quoted testimony. This orientation excludes entering a discussion of Ss gener-

    alized normative appeals. A related feature is Ps recurrent practice of

    questioning S by presenting details of witness testimony and physical evidence.Indeed, Ps own question Why would the witness lie? is a further example of this

    practice, referring back to the testimony rather than expressing Ps own views on

    the matter. This general orientation on Ps part works against P pursuing, or

    objecting to, Ss generalized self-assessments.

    Relevantly, the practice by question-askers, of putting questions in the form of

    quotations from other people, has been noted across other institutional contexts

    such as news interviews (Clayman, 1988; Clayman and Heritage, 2002), where it

    performs a kind of footing (Goffman, 1979) that displays the interviewers

    neutrality while nevertheless being adversarial. Police interrogators are doing

    something closely related to that, but perhaps displaying an orientation to

    evidence-based objectivity rather than neutrality as such, given that they are often

    making the accusation themselves, as the arresting officer, and may (as in extracts1 and 9) be offering some accusatory witnessing of their own. With regard to

    interviewer neutrality and footing, police interrogation appears to be positioned

    normatively somewhere between news interviewing and courtroom cross-

    examination (Atkinson and Drew, 1979). Unlike news interviewers, barristers in

    adversarial courts of law are professionally on one side rather than another, while

    nevertheless also, normatively, in pursuit of the facts. Police officers appear to be

    less strongly positioned than lawyers, displaying an orientation to factual inquiry

    rather than factual rebuttal, yet not so neutrally as news interviewers. Of course,

    these are arenas of interaction requiring close empirical examination, rather than

    normative stipulation, for precisely how they compare and differ.

    The use of would in formulating normative-dispositional claims or assess-

    ments rests on its grammar, being the past tense ofwill. In the context of the dataand analysis provided here, would is used to propose a kind of back-dated

    predictability. It proposes something like going back to a time prior to the

    particular event or action in question, and seeing that it was then predictable it

    was expectably, predictably, going to happen (or, in the case of wouldnt, not going

    to happen). So, I wouldnt hurt an old lady proposes that, if we place ourselves

    prior to the event, then, knowing what we know about this person, and lifes

    normative order, we can see that hurting an old lady was not, then or ever, in

    Edwards: Facts, norms and dispositions 497

    by Sorin Ciutacu on October 31, 2009http://dis.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/
  • 7/28/2019 Modal Would in Police Interrogations

    25/28

    prospect. Similarly, why would she say that you did? proposes the requirementfor some prior state of affairs, some motive or circumstance, that makes her

    saying it predictable. This same semantic of back-dated predictability also

    provides for counter-factual uses of would, as in I would if I could, where what

    one would do is back-datedly or dispositionally predictable, if it were not for

    circumstances preventing it. Hence the rich usefulness of wouldand its variants,

    in handling disputed factuality with regard to motives, norms and character.

    We also found a relationship between deployments of modal reasoning and

    the invocation of membership or identity categories (an old lady; an old bloke; a

    seven-year-old, a little kid, a little twat, a nine-year-old girl, etc.). These categories

    fit with uses of wouldin invoking normative knowledge as a route or criterion for

    the truth of specific, disputed factual claims. Old ladies, old blokes and little kids

    are not only generalized membership categories to which normativeexpectations are inferentially attached (Hester and Eglin, 1997; Sacks, 1992;

    Stokoe, 2003; Watson, 1997), but they are also categories emblematic (along

    with, say, the disabled and infirm) of people that are not to be hit, kicked, robbed,

    or otherwise assaulted. Heydon (2005) refers to the invocation, in police

    interrogation, of the moral or normative (rather than strictly legal) rule, it is

    wrong to hit women and those smaller than you (p. 203). In Heydons analysis,

    this is largely a device that police interrogators can use in questioning Ss

    conduct, and rejecting mitigating accounts. In the examples analysed here, it is

    primarily used by S in constructing a counter-dispositional formulation of Ss

    own conduct in a particular case. The same normative injunction against hitting

    women and children (and old people, etc.), that makes the offence particularly

    heinous, is exactly what is used by S to say that he didnt (because he wouldnt)do it. Other person descriptions may have a different logic, while still arguing that

    a particular offence was not committed because it would not have been (e.g.

    extract 10, lines 78, where the category is that of a man one would be foolish to

    attack: look at the size aim es six foot fou:r (0.4) Im five foot seven).

    Another link was made to analytic work on scripts and dispositions (Edwards,

    1995, 1997). Would, along with invocations of membership categories, are

    among a range of devices by which specific actions or events can be given a

    generalized, timeless quality, and by which the built-in characteristics of persons,

    places and objects can be proposed and implied. Back-dated predictability, the

    semantics of would, lends itself to saying what a person can or could be expected

    to do, in fact or hypothetically, and at any time. It lends itself to characterological

    formulations of persons their tendencies, dispositions, moral nature, desiresand intentions. And it is useful in the production and disputation of factual

    accounts, whether in promoting a version as consistent or consensual, or in

    characterizing that version and its producer as in some way motivated,

    interested, and false (see also Komter, 1995, and Sneijder and te Molder, 2005).10

    Clearly these devices and practices are of special and endemic relevance to police

    interrogation, but they have a common sense practical logic that lends itself to a

    wide range of settings not explored here.

    498 Discourse Studies 8(4)

    by Sorin Ciutacu on October 31, 2009http://dis.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/
  • 7/28/2019 Modal Would in Police Interrogations

    26/28

    N O T E S

    1. In a different but related setting, that of courtroom legal examination, Matoesian

    (2001) notes an expert witnesss use of the perfect tense epistemic modal may have

    as a device for speculating about unwitnessed possible events (cf. Heydon, 2005:

    1423). The work they do in that setting is to cast doubt on a witnesss actual

    testimony by providing alternative, plausible accounts for the same evidential effects

    or events: epistemic modals do more than merely encode alternative possibilities.

    They also index the speakers authority with respect to the truth or falsity of a given

    representation of reality (Matoesian, 2001: 187).

    2. ESRC project RES-148250010 Identities in neighbour discourse: Community,

    conflict and exclusion held by Elizabeth Stokoe and Derek Edwards.

    3. TCU is Turn Constructional Unit the building blocks that make for potentially

    complete turns at talk, in conversation analysis (Sacks et al., 1974). What makes this

    a possibly complete TCU is its potential grammatical completeness as a clause orsentence, its final intonation contour (marked by the full stop or period), and its

    hearable completeness as accomplishing an action (self-assessment), such that P is,

    at just this point, in a position to respond.

    4. It is not appropriate to assign a specific emotional description to Ss prosody, but

    clearly some such epistemically relevant reaction is conveyed, in aid of Ss rejection of

    the idea that he hit the man.

    5. Gonna, or going to, is an alternative to the modal will in English, for expressing a

    future and/or intended event or action. Wouldis, grammatically, the past tense of will

    (Oxford English Dictionary, 2002). Accordingly, we also find in the data similarly

    dispositional uses of will and wont such as this, from the same interrogation as

    extract 1 (with will/wont italicized):

    S: I wont do it if its if th- dy wont pu- they wont

    put the ciggies on the counter, (0.2) Ill say oh

    Ive left me money in the car or Ive left me moneyin ours an Ill walk out the shop an Ill leave it.

    6. These details are provided as possibly relevant to Ss unusually polite address form

    sir (line 1), and perhaps also the grammatical glitch in line 4.

    7. These are my own observations about the status of that evidence, but they reflect

    orientations to it by S and P themselves, in that S may offer alternative interpretations

    or dismissals of the evidences significance, and P does not insist on the matter. See

    extract 1, line 6; extract 2, line 13; and extract 10, lines 1114.

    8. There is something in the manner of Ps delivery at line 12, including the pauses, that

    conveys a sense of significance, deliberation and/or puzzlement. Ss overlap at 14

    comes just where Ps objection is projectable, reinforcing the sense of Ps objection as

    somewhat expectable; see the discussion of that notion regarding extract 15.

    9. The asterisks mark a croaky vocal delivery.

    10. A notorious example was coined by Mandy Rice Davies, a witness in the Profumo trial

    of 1963, and the topic of the 1989 Michael Caton film Scandal. A British government

    Defence Minister, John Profumo, was accused of liaisons with call girls including

    Davies, who were also entertaining a Russian military officer during the cold war. In

    the trial, a barrister says to Davies that Lord Astor, another government minister,

    denies having had sex with her. The court famously burst into laughter at her reply:

    Well, he would say that, wouldnt he? (see also Edwards and Potter, 1992).

    Edwards: Facts, norms and dispositions 499

    by Sorin Ciutacu on October 31, 2009http://dis.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/
  • 7/28/2019 Modal Would in Police Interrogations

    27/28

    R E F E R E N C E S

    Atkinson, J.M. and Drew, P. (1979) Order in Court: The Organization of Verbal Interaction in

    Judicial Settings. London: Macmillan.

    Benneworth, K. (2004) A Discursive Analysis of Police Interviews with Suspected

    Paedophiles: The Implications of Open and Closed Interviewing for Admission and

    Denial, unpublished doctoral thesis, Loughborough University, UK.

    Bybee, J. and Fleischman, S. (eds) (1995) Modality and Grammar in Discourse (Typological

    studies in language, 32). Amsterdam and Philadelphia, PA: John Benjamins.

    Clayman, S.E. (1988) Displaying Neutrality in Television News Interviews, Social

    Problems 35(4): 47492.

    Clayman, S.E. and Heritage, J. (2002) The News Interview: Journalists and Public Figures on

    the Air. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Drew, P. (1992) Contested Evidence in Courtroom Cross-examination: The Case of a Trial

    for Rape, in P. Drew and J. Heritage (eds)Talk at Work: Interaction in Institutional

    Settings, pp. 470520. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Edwards, D. (1994) Script Formulations: A Study of Event Descriptions in Conversation,

    Journal of Language and Social Psychology 13(3): 21147.

    Edwards, D. (1995) Two to Tango: Script Formulations, Dispositions, and Rhetorical

    Symmetry in Relationship Troubles Talk, Research on Language and Social Interaction

    28(4): 31950.

    Edwards, D. (1997) Discourse and Cognition. London: Sage.

    Edwards, D. and Potter, J. (1992) Discursive Psychology. London: Sage.

    Edwards, D. and Potter, J. (2001) Discursive Psychology, in A. McHoul and M. Rapley

    (eds) How to Analyse Talk in Institutional Settings: A Casebook of Methods, pp. 1224.

    London/New York: Continuum International.

    Goffman, E. (1979) Footing, Semiotica 25: 129.

    Heritage, J.C. and Watson, D.R. (1979) Formulations as Conversational Objects, in G.

    Psathas (ed.) Everyday Language: Studies in Ethnomethodology, pp. 12362. New York:Irvington.

    Hester, S. and Eglin, P. (eds) (1997) Culture in Action: Studies in Membership Categorization

    Analysis. Washington, DC: University Press of America.

    Heydon, G. (2005) The Language of Police Interviewing: A Critical Analysis. Basingstoke:

    Palgrave Macmillan.

    Jayyusi, L. (1984) Categories and the Moral Order. London: Routledge.

    Jefferson, G. (2004) Glossary of Transcript Symbols with an Introduction, in G.H. Lerner

    (ed.) Conversation Analysis: Studies from the First Generation, pp. 1331. Amsterdam:

    John Benjamins.

    Komter, M.L. (1995) The Distribution of Knowledge in Courtroom Interaction, in P. ten

    Have and G. Psathas (eds) Situated Order: Studies in the Social Organization of Talk and

    Embodied Activities, pp. 10728. Washington, DC: University Press of America.

    Komter, M.L. (1997) Remorse, Redress, and Reform: Blame-taking in the Courtroom, in

    M. Travers and J.F. Manzo (eds) Law in Action: Ethnomethodological and Conversation

    Analytic Approaches to Law, pp. 23964. Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Lynch, M. and Bogen, D. (2005) My Memory Has Been Shredded: A Non-cognitivist

    Investigation of Mental Phenomena, in H. Te Molder and J. Potter (eds) Conversation

    and Cognition, pp. 22640. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Matoesian, G.M. (2001) Law and the Language of Identity: Discourse in the William Kennedy

    Smith Rape Trial. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Oxford English Dictionary (2002).

    500 Discourse Studies 8(4)

    by Sorin Ciutacu on October 31, 2009http://dis.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/http://dis.sagepub.com/
  • 7/28/2019 Modal Would in Police Interrogations

    28/28

    Palmer, F.R. (2001)Mood and Modality

    , 2nd edn. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Pollner, M. (1987) Mundane Reason: Reality in Everyday and Sociological Discourse.

    Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Pomerantz, A.M. (1984) Agreeing and Disagreeing with Assessments: Some Features of

    Preferred/Dispreferred Turn Shapes, in J.M. Atkinson and J. Heritage (eds) Structures

    of Social Action: Studies in Conversation Analysis, pp. 57101. Cambridge: Cambridge

    University Press.

    Pomerantz, A. (1986) Extreme Case Formulations: A Way of Legitimizing Claims,Human Studies 9: 21929.

    Sacks, H. (1992) Lectures on Conversation, Vols I & II, ed. G. Jefferson. Oxford: Basil

    Blackwell.

    Sacks, H., Schegloff, E.A. and Jefferson, G. (1974) A Simplest Systematics for the

    Organization of Turn-taking for Conversation, Language 50(4): 696735.

    Schegloff, E.A., Jefferson, G. and Sacks, H. (1977) The Preference for Self-Correction in

    the Organization of Repair in Conversation, Language 53(2): 36182.Smith, D. (1978) K is Mentally Ill: The Anatomy of a Factual Account, Sociology 12:

    2353.

    Sneijder, P. and te Molder, H.F.M. (2005) Moral Logic and Logical Morality: Attributions

    of Responsibility and Blame in Online Discourse on Veganism, Discourse & Society

    16(5): 67596.

    Stokoe, E.H. (2003) Mothers, Single Women and Sluts: Gender, Morality and Membership

    Categorization in Neighbour Disputes, Feminism and Psychology 13(3): 31744.

    Travers, M. and Manzo, J.F. (eds) (1997) Law in Action: Ethnomethodological and

    Conversation Analytic Approaches to Law. Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Watson, R. (1997) The Presentation of Victim and Motive in Discourse: The Case of

    Police Interrogations and Interviews, in M. Travers and J.F. Manzo (eds) Law in Action:

    Ethnomethodological and Conversation Analytic Approaches to Law, pp. 7797. Aldershot:

    Ashgate.Wowk, M.T. (1984) Blame Allocation: Sex and Gender in a Murder Interrogation,

    Womens Studies International Forum 7: 7582.

    D ER EK E DWA RD S is Professor of Psychology in the Department of Social Sciences,

    Loughborough University. His interests are in the analysis of language and social

    interaction in everyday and institutional settings. He specializes in discursive psychology,

    in which relations between psychological states and the external world are studied as

    discourse categories and practices. His books include Common Knowledge, with Neil Mercer

    (Routledge, 1987), Ideological Dilemmas, with Michael Billig and others (Sage, 1988),

    Discursive Psychology, with Jonathan Potter (Sage, 1992), and Discourse and Cognition(Sage, 1997). A D D R E S S : Department of Social Sciences, Loughborough University,

    Loughborough LE11 3TU, UK. [email: [email protected]]

    Edwards: Facts, norms and dispositions 501