Top Banner

of 16

Milton's References to Plato and Socrates

Feb 17, 2018

Download

Documents

Erick Miranda
Welcome message from author
This document is posted to help you gain knowledge. Please leave a comment to let me know what you think about it! Share it to your friends and learn new things together.
Transcript
  • 7/23/2019 Milton's References to Plato and Socrates

    1/16

    University of North Carolina Press http://www.jstor.org/stable/4172643.

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    University of North Carolina Pressis collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to

    Studies in Philology.

    http://www.jstor.org

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=uncpresshttp://www.jstor.org/stable/4172643?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/4172643?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=uncpress
  • 7/23/2019 Milton's References to Plato and Socrates

    2/16

    MILTON'S REFERENCES

    TO PLATO AND

    SOCRATES

    By

    IRENE

    SAMUEL

    The importance of Platonism to Milton's

    growth

    in

    philosophi-

    cal and

    poetic power

    has needed *further

    study.

    While the

    sub-

    ject

    hitherto has not

    been

    neglected,

    a

    glance

    at

    the

    appended

    table of

    references made

    by

    Milton

    to Plato

    and

    Socrates

    will

    show how far even clear signs of his indebtedness have escaped

    scholarly

    notice. From these references

    I have ventured to draw

    some

    conclusions

    on the

    importance

    of the debt. But

    first

    I wish

    to

    thank

    Dr.

    Herbert

    Agar

    for

    permission

    to build

    upon

    the useful

    discoveries

    recorded in

    his

    book on

    Milton and

    Plato.

    My

    method

    of

    distinguishing

    new

    matter

    in

    the

    table

    is intended to acknowl.

    edge fully

    the debt that

    I

    with other scholars owe to his initial

    research. The

    Index to the Columbia edition

    of

    The

    Works

    of

    John

    Milton

    appeared

    after I had

    compiled my

    own

    list of

    references, but has proved a helpful check.

    References to Socrates and Plato

    from the

    pen

    of John

    Milton

    are,

    of course,

    hardly

    matter for

    surprise.

    An

    Englishman

    of the

    seventeenth century, trained at St.

    Paul's

    and

    Cambridge,

    at

    home

    in

    the academies of Italy, in

    correspondence with the

    learned men

    of his

    time,

    who

    had

    not

    found occasion

    to

    mention Plato

    and

    Socrates would

    astonish us. And

    yet

    time and

    place will

    not wholly

    account for these references

    by one who

    so

    constantly and reso-

    lutely as Milton transcended

    the mental

    barriers of era and local-

    ity. Again,

    the mere frequency of

    allusion might seem

    enough to

    explain why such an astute reader as Coleridge called Plato ' Mil-

    ton's

    darling.'

    But

    Coleridge's

    complaint,

    that

    commentators have

    heeded too little

    Plato's influence on Milton,'

    rightly suggests that

    these

    references

    are no

    less

    important than

    numerous. Why labor

    the

    point?

    As

    early

    as his

    student

    years

    at

    Cambridge Milton was

    calling Socrates

    the 'wisest

    of

    the Greeks

    2 and Plato

    'divine.'

    3

    As late as Paradise

    Regained Socrates

    was still for

    Milton 'the

    S.

    T.

    Coleridge,

    Letter

    to W.

    Sotheby,

    dated

    September 10,

    1802, in

    Letters, ed.

    by Ernest

    Hartley

    Coleridge

    (Boston, 1895),

    I,

    406.

    ' See

    Eleg.

    IV,

    23-4.

    a

    Prolus.

    VII.

    See the

    Coluimbia

    edition of

    The Works

    of

    John

    Milton

    (hereafter

    referred to as C.

    E.).

    XII.

    262-4.

    50

  • 7/23/2019 Milton's References to Plato and Socrates

    3/16

    Irene Samuel 51

    wisest

    of them

    [i.

    e., the

    pagans]

    all' and

    Plato 'the

    next

    '-in

    wisdom, we

    may guess,

    as

    in

    time.

    But

    since

    such

    epithets

    may

    be

    conventional,

    and were

    so in

    Milton's

    age, as often in our

    own,

    and often

    conventional

    with

    those

    who know little

    more

    of Plato than that he may,be

    called

    divine and

    of

    Socrates that he

    was

    called the

    wisest of

    men, they

    need

    suggest

    no

    unusual

    Platonism in

    Milton's

    thought. Indeed

    Milton's

    early

    references

    to both

    Socrates and

    Plato are

    of this

    kind;

    common-

    places of the schools and society, they indicate learning, but rather

    learning about

    than

    learning

    from

    Plato.

    Milton

    surely

    read in

    the

    Dialogues at

    college,

    if

    not

    earlier,

    used

    materials from

    them,

    and knew

    something

    of

    Platonic

    'theories.' But he

    read,

    and

    used,

    and

    knlew, we

    may

    surmise,

    in

    the

    way of

    a

    highly gifted

    collegian

    dealing

    with an

    ancient

    philosopher.

    Plato was as

    remote as

    high.

    The

    early

    references, both in

    the

    Cambridge

    and

    even

    early

    in

    the

    Horton

    period, might

    come from

    any one

    of similar

    training.

    They

    are

    vague;

    4

    they reveal

    no

    special

    insight into

    Plato's

    thought; they have no connection with the writer's own serious

    belief.

    The like

    may be

    said even

    of

    the verses De

    Idea

    Platonica,

    in

    which

    Aristotle's

    denials are

    tossed

    about on

    Milton's

    frolicsome

    Pegasus.5

    So

    too with 11

    Penseroso, where

    Plato is to be

    unsphered

    for

    such work

    as had

    better

    have been

    left to

    Hermes

    Trismegis-

    tus.6

    These familiar

    uses of

    Pla.to show

    interest and

    learning,

    even

    affection, but

    hardly

    deep

    understanding.

    They

    reflect

    the

    contemporary zest for

    Platonism, but reveal

    little of

    AMilton.

    The

    allusions of

    his

    middle

    years

    are

    decidedly

    different.

    Whether

    inspired

    by

    the

    Platonizing talk

    in

    the

    Italian

    academies

    he had visited or pressed by the needs of political controversy, or

    4

    Note the

    impossibility

    of

    relating

    any

    of

    them

    to a

    particular

    writing

    of

    Plato,

    or

    indeed

    with

    certainty

    to

    any

    source

    at

    all.

    E.

    H.

    Visiak

    has

    raised

    the

    question

    'how

    far

    Mi'lton

    understood

    Plato's

    conception when

    he wrote

    this

    academic

    exercise;

    whether

    he

    had

    .

    .

    .as yet

    come

    into

    the enthusiasm

    for

    Plato's

    philosophy

    which

    he

    afterwards

    expressed.'

    See

    Milton's Lament

    for

    Damon

    and

    his

    other

    Latin Poems

    (London,

    1935), p.

    66.

    And

    another

    commentator,

    Walter

    Mac

    Kellar,

    while

    accepting

    the

    poem

    as

    Platonic,

    feels

    the

    need

    to

    suggest

    for

    it

    sources

    other

    than

    Plato

    and Aristotle,

    See

    The

    Latin

    Poems

    of

    John

    Milton

    (New

    Haven,

    1930), p.

    51.

    6

    In 'A Note on Il Penseroso,' MLN., XXXIII (1918), 184-5, E. C.

    Baldwin observed

    that the

    whole

    passage

    bears far

    more

    resemblance

    to

    the

    Hermetica

    than

    to

    any

    writing

    of

    Plato.

  • 7/23/2019 Milton's References to Plato and Socrates

    4/16

    52

    Miltones

    References to Plato

    and Socrates

    whenever

    and however

    moved, Milton

    apparently was

    a

    careful

    student

    of

    the

    Dialogues during the

    years

    of

    England's

    civil war.

    In his

    various treatises,

    allusions and

    citations are

    specific

    and

    detailed, so much

    so that a scholar must still

    read

    Plato's words

    as

    carefully as

    Milton did

    in

    order to find the exact

    source.7 But

    even more

    striking

    than

    this

    exactness is the

    manifest

    wish

    to

    grasp

    Plato's thought

    and hold it

    steadily in view.

    The reference,

    while

    imbedded in

    argument,

    often

    has

    a

    bit of

    commentary

    attached;

    that is, Milton comments not merely on its relevance to the argu-

    ment,

    but on the

    reasonableness of the

    position taken

    by

    Plato.8

    Most

    important of

    all,

    these

    citations of

    Plato's

    authority show

    not

    understanding

    alone, but an

    incorporation of

    the thought

    into Mil-

    ton's own doctrine:

    they

    do not

    simply

    add

    the

    prop

    of

    a

    great

    name

    to the

    argument,

    they guide

    it.

    And because

    Milton

    was

    thus steadily

    assimilatiing

    the thoughts

    of the

    Dialogues

    and

    Epistles,

    or

    assimilating

    his own

    thoughts

    to

    them,

    with his latest

    allusions

    we once more have

    difficulty

    in

    naming the precise

    origin.9

    Here

    again,

    as in the

    early references,

    is vagueness, but with a difference. Now

    particularity is absent

    because

    absorbed

    in

    general

    understanding. Thus the

    growing

    infrequency

    of

    allusions to Plato and Socrates in

    Milton's later

    work

    means not a

    waning familiarity, but a

    fully

    accomplished

    assimilation,

    showing not

    less interest

    in Plato's

    writings,

    but a

    more

    perfect

    appropriation

    of

    their

    content.

    7

    For

    example, the

    passage

    in

    the

    letter to

    Buommattei,

    quoted

    below

    on

    p.

    -,

    is

    surely

    an

    allusion

    to

    Laws, VII,

    797-8;

    but

    Agar

    writes,

    'If

    Milton had

    any particular

    passages

    in

    mind, they

    were

    perhaps

    the eighth

    and ninth Books of

    the

    Republic.'

    See Herbert

    Agar,

    Milton

    and

    Plato

    (Princeton,

    1928),

    p.

    69.

    Again,

    Ronald

    B.

    Levinson

    has

    demonstrated

    that

    a

    reference

    in

    Chzurch-Gov.

    (C.

    E.,

    III, 264)

    is to

    Plato's

    Sophist

    230,

    not,

    as

    Agar

    says,

    to

    Gorgias

    524-5. Cf.

    Agar, p.

    61,

    with

    Levinson,

    'Milton

    and

    Plato,'

    MLN.,

    XLVI

    (1931), 85-91.

    One further

    illustration: in

    his

    first

    Defensio

    (C.

    E., VII,

    158)

    Milton

    paraphrases

    Republic, V,

    463;

    Agar

    gives

    as

    the

    source

    Laws,

    IV,

    715.

    8

    See,

    for

    example,

    the Preface to

    Church-Gov.

    (C.

    E., III,

    181-2)

    and

    the discussion below on

    pp.

    -.

    Similarly

    Milton

    comments

    on

    Plato'a

    words in a

    number

    of

    passages,

    among

    them:

    Church-Gov.

    (C. E.,

    III,

    264);

    D. D. D.

    (C.

    E.,

    III,

    458-9);

    Tetrach.

    (C.

    E., IV,

    655); Def.

    (C.

    E.,

    VII,

    348-50).

    9 In the Logic Milton had, of course, particular reasons for taking from

    Downham,

    or himself

    supplying,

    the

    name of

    the

    Dialogue

    referred

    to.

    See

    the

    table

    of

    references.

  • 7/23/2019 Milton's References to Plato and Socrates

    5/16

    Irene

    Samuel

    53

    So

    much we

    may learn

    by

    tabulating

    these

    references and

    their

    sources,

    explicitly given

    or

    implied.

    And

    Milton's

    use of

    Platon-

    ism, as we

    hope to show in

    further

    papers,

    confirms

    this view.

    Where the

    early

    poems

    are

    dotted with native

    stars

    and

    love-inspir-

    ing

    beauties and spheric

    harmonies, all

    in

    the manner

    of the

    Platonizing

    Renaissance,

    the

    later

    poems

    incorporate

    Platonic

    theories

    in their

    argument.

    And

    again,

    while the

    works

    of his

    middle

    vears

    reveal

    their debt

    to

    Plato

    in more,

    and

    more

    specific,

    passages, the latest works are more steadily and intrinsically Pla-

    tonic

    in

    their

    theoretical

    basis.

    While

    we cannot

    precisely

    date

    Milton's first

    reading

    in the

    Dialogues nor

    define

    its course

    and effect,

    something can

    be said

    about the

    reason for

    the change

    we find

    from the

    early

    references

    to those of

    his

    middle years.

    A

    letter

    to

    Diodati,

    written from

    London on

    September

    23, 1637,

    contains

    Milton's earliest

    'schol-

    arly'

    citation of

    Plato:

    Though

    I

    know

    not God's

    intent

    toward me in

    other

    respects, yet of

    this

    I

    am

    sure,

    that

    he

    has

    imbued me

    especially

    with a

    mighty

    passion for

    Beauty. [8ecv&6uot

    apwvra,

    e('rep

    71

    dXXCp

    0V

    icaXoi E'vaorae.] 10 Ceres never

    sought her

    daughter

    Prosperine (as the

    legend tells)

    with

    greater

    ardour

    than

    I

    do

    this

    Idea of

    Beauty [roV KaXOI

    8iaV]

    1L

    like

    some image

    of loveli-

    ness;

    ever

    pursuing it,

    by day

    and by night, in

    every

    shape

    and form

    (

    for

    many forms

    there are of

    thinigs

    divine ), and

    following close

    in

    its

    footprints

    as

    it

    leads. '

    And

    so,

    whensoever I find

    one who

    spurns the

    base opinions

    of common

    men,18

    and

    dares

    to be, in

    thought and

    word and

    deed, that which

    the

    wisest

    minds

    throughout the

    ages

    have

    approved;

    whensoever, I

    say,

    I

    find such a

    maii, to

    him I

    find myself

    impelled

    forthwith to

    cleave....

    14

    What am I

    thinking

    about?

    you ask.

    So help me

    God, of

    immortality.15

    What am I

    doing?

    Growing

    wings

    [7rTepoov(Z]

    and

    learning to

    fly;

    16

    but my Pegasus can only rise on tender pinions as yet, so let my new

    wisdom be

    humble.17

    'I

    Cf.

    Phaedrus

    249

    d-e.

    2'

    Plato

    does

    not

    use

    this

    termn,

    but it is

    an

    obviously

    Platonic

    substitute

    for

    those he

    does use

    in

    Phaedrus

    to

    express

    the

    concept.

    12

    Cf.

    Phaedrus 250

    a-c.

    13

    Cf.

    ibid.

    249

    c-d.

    14

    Cf.

    ibid. 251

    b- 252

    c,

    256

    d.

    5 Cf.

    ibid. 245

    ff.

    16

    Cf.

    ibid.

    249

    d-e,

    251

    b-

    252

    c,

    256 d.

    17

    Trans. by Phyllis B. Tillyard, Milton: Private Correspondence and

    Academic

    Exercises

    (Cambridge,

    1932), p.

    14.

    The

    insertions are

    from

    the

    text of Milton's

    letter,

    C.

    E.,

    XII,

    26.

  • 7/23/2019 Milton's References to Plato and Socrates

    6/16

    54 Milton's

    References

    to

    Plato and

    Socrates

    Phaedrw

    is

    not

    named;

    Diodati

    is

    expected

    to

    place

    the

    quota-

    tion.

    Evidently

    Milton

    had

    known

    an Italian

    Platonist

    before

    ever

    he

    entered

    an

    accademia.

    But this

    is

    somehow

    different

    from

    such

    use

    of

    roi

    xaAoi

    i&e'ov

    s

    Ficino

    or Pico

    della Mirandola

    or

    Bembo

    had

    popularized.

    Here

    is no

    mistress

    praised

    as the

    very

    incarnation

    of that

    glorious

    idea,

    but

    a friend

    told

    that

    he, but

    not

    he alone,

    is

    loved

    because

    this

    'Idea

    of Beauty'

    leaves

    its print

    on

    many

    shapes

    and

    forms,

    and

    especially

    on

    the spirit

    of an

    uncom-

    monly good man. The friend is even told his use: by his aid the

    soul

    grows

    its

    wings,

    and to

    its own

    end-immortality,

    that

    it

    may

    bave

    vision

    of the

    very

    'image

    of loveliness

    ' and

    fly its

    Pegasus,

    if

    it be

    a poet's

    soul,

    to the

    rim

    of

    heaven

    itself-hereafter.

    For

    the

    present

    the pinions

    are

    but

    growing;

    the

    flight

    must

    not

    yet-

    be,

    we gather,

    unaided.

    We

    have

    in

    this

    letter

    to

    Diodati

    the

    authentic

    note

    of

    ardent

    Platonism.

    But

    was it

    Milton's

    first

    sounding

    of that

    note?

    In

    Comus,

    written some

    three years

    earlier,

    there

    occurred

    a

    passage

    of similar

    quotation

    and paraphrase

    from Plato. 8

    And

    surely

    much in Comus may be traced directly or indirectly to the Dia-

    logues,

    and

    much is

    ardent.

    But

    is it exactly

    Platonic?

    We

    must

    reserve

    for

    another

    time

    a

    discussion

    of the

    Platonism of

    Comus,

    but

    may

    here suggest

    a way

    of putting

    the question:

    Is

    the

    con-

    versation of

    the

    mask

    such a

    dialogue

    as

    Plato might

    have

    written

    on

    the

    subject?

    Is the saintly

    Lady

    in her

    awesome

    self-righteous-

    ness

    a second

    Diotima

    versed

    in the deep mysteries

    of

    Love?

    No more than

    Comus

    with

    his

    bestiality

    resembles

    the Aristophanes

    of

    Plato's

    creation.

    The

    theories

    of the mask,

    like its

    men

    and

    women, are such as the Platonic Spenser loved to present, but not

    Plato.

    The

    'divine

    Philosophy'

    of

    Plato

    had

    begun

    to

    'charm'

    Milton

    long

    before;

    it had

    not

    yet

    pervaded

    his

    thought.

    Doubtless

    the

    youthful

    writer

    of Comus

    did not

    set himself

    to

    expound

    Plato's

    doctrines,

    but,

    like poets

    from

    Homer

    to

    Kipling,

    simply

    used

    what

    in

    doctrine,

    as in

    image,

    legend,

    myth,

    he

    found

    to

    his

    purpose.

    A

    great

    deal of what

    he found useful

    came

    origi-

    nally

    from

    Plato,

    some of

    it

    directly;

    but

    genuine

    Platonism

    like

    the

    words

    to Diodati

    we can

    scarcely

    call

    it. The

    Platonism

    of

    Comw

    is

    still

    largely

    conventional

    because

    the author,

    though

    I'

    Lines

    470-5

    of

    Comut

    are

    adapted

    from

    Phaedo

    81.

    There

    are,

    of

    course,

    many

    other

    reminiscences

    of

    the

    Dialogues

    in

    the

    mask.

  • 7/23/2019 Milton's References to Plato and Socrates

    7/16

    Irene Samuel

    55

    familiar

    with the

    Dialogues

    and

    even

    partially

    under their

    sway,

    was not

    immediately concerned with

    Plato. What the

    letter

    to

    Diodati

    reveals

    is

    not, then,

    in

    all

    probability,

    a

    new

    acquaintance

    with

    any dialogue,

    but a

    new

    grasp

    of the

    relevanee

    of Plato's

    thought

    to

    Milton's own

    life.

    Milton

    himself twice stated

    that his mature reading

    in

    Plato

    had greatly influenced

    him. From these two

    passages we

    learn

    explicitly what we have

    inferred from the letter to Diodati.

    Some

    time before publishing his youthful Elegies in 1645, Milton

    appended to them

    19

    a

    postscript:

    Haec

    ego meiite

    olini

    laeva, studioque supino,

    Nequitiae posui

    vana

    trophaea meae.

    Scilicet abreptum sic me

    malus impulit error,

    Indocilisque aetas prava magistra

    fuit;

    Donec

    Socraticos

    umbrosa

    Academis rivos

    Praebuit, admissum

    dedocuitque iugum.

    Protinus, extinctis ex illo

    tempore flammis

    Cincta

    rigent

    muilto

    pectora

    nostra

    gelu;

    Uiide suis

    frigus

    metuit puer ipse

    sagittis,

    Et Diomedeam vim timet ipse Venus.20

    The

    lines,

    somewhat like a

    recantation,

    have an

    evident purpose.

    At a definite time in

    Milton's

    life, we are to understand,

    Plato

    with his Socratic

    teaching

    profoundly altered the

    thoughts and

    feelings of

    the

    poet.

    Once he

    hadl been

    content to write

    in an

    amorous

    vein very like,

    we

    note, that

    of conventional

    Platonism;

    then

    upon reading,

    or rather

    rereading, Plato, he discovered

    that

    the

    doctrine

    of

    love there

    taught was

    of

    grave

    significance, not

    only

    in

    itself,

    but

    for

    him.

    If

    this

    doctrine were

    simply the arm-

    ing of the heart against Cupid's shafts, we might suppose that the

    experience

    had

    preceded

    and

    prompted

    the writing of Comus,

    where

    we

    could

    find

    fully expressed the new

    understanding.

    But the

    Apology for Smectymnuus

    records

    the event more

    completely:

    19

    Or

    to the

    last of

    them.

    20

    '

    These

    vain

    trophies

    of

    my

    idleness

    I

    once

    set

    up

    in

    foolish

    mood

    and

    with

    supine

    endeavor.

    Injurious

    error,

    forsooth,

    led

    me

    astray, and untu-

    tored youth

    was

    a

    bad

    teacher;

    until

    the

    shady

    Academy

    offered its

    Socratic

    streams, and

    freed me from

    the

    yoke

    to

    which

    I

    had

    submitted.

    At once

    these flames were

    extinguished,

    and thenceforth

    my

    breast

    has

    been

    stiff

    with en6ircling ice, whence Cupid has feared a frost for his arrows, and

    Venus fears

    my

    Diomedean

    strength.'

    The

    text

    and translation

    are

    taken

    from

    Mac

    Kellar's edition of

    Milton's

    Latin

    Poems.

  • 7/23/2019 Milton's References to Plato and Socrates

    8/16

    56 Milton's References to Plato and Socrates

    Thus,

    from

    the

    laureate

    fraternity

    of

    poets, riper years

    and the

    ceaseless

    round of study

    and

    reading led me

    to

    the shady spaces

    of

    philosophy;

    but

    chiefly

    to

    the divine

    volumites

    of Plato and

    his equal Xenophon: where,

    if I should tell you what

    I

    learnt

    of

    chastity

    and

    love,

    I mean

    that which

    is

    truly so, whose charming

    cup is only virtue,

    which

    she

    bears

    in

    her

    hand

    to those who are worthy; (the rest are cheated with

    a

    thick intoxicating

    potion,

    which a

    certain

    sorceress,

    the

    abuser of

    love's name, carries about;)

    and how the first and chiefest office of

    love

    begins and ends in the soul,

    producing those happy twins of her divine generation, knowledge and

    virtue. With such abstracted sublimities as these, it might be worth

    your listening, readers, as I may one day hope to have ye in a still time,

    when there

    shall

    be no chiding.21

    Since Milton

    wrote

    this

    passage years

    after Comm

    had

    been per-

    formed, clearly he himself did not feel that his mask told what he

    had learned about chastity and love from the Dialogues. Far from

    it. Those 'divine volumes' have supplied him with matter for

    work yet unborn. And now, be it noted, the epithet 'divine' is

    no longer merely conventional, but granted by a disciple to the

    'abstracted

    sublimities' into

    which

    he has himself

    been

    initiated.

    For this is the language of an initiate, of one for whom the heart

    of

    an

    ethical doctrine has come alive. Knowing that Milton had

    never

    since

    his

    student days been unacquainted with Platonism,

    we

    recognize this experience of

    his

    'riper years'

    as the

    winning of

    a

    new

    insight. The letter to Diodati,

    the

    postscript

    to

    the Elegies,

    the

    words in

    the Apology,

    all bear

    the

    mark

    of emotion,

    the

    two

    in

    prose, a strong emotion as

    well

    as clear understanding; they

    suggest,

    as it

    were,

    a

    philosophical

    conversion.

    But we

    need

    not dwell

    on

    the

    emotional

    phase

    of

    Milton's

    Pla-

    tonism.

    The

    bare references

    of

    his

    middle

    years

    alone warrant

    our

    finding in the Dialogues a major source of his theories on all the

    many problems

    of

    human

    life

    witlh

    which

    he then

    was

    dealing.

    Thenceforth,

    at

    any rate,

    the

    authority

    of

    Plato

    assumed

    ever-

    increasing importance.

    In the

    letter

    to

    Diodati,

    Milton had

    quoted

    from Phaedrus

    without

    giving

    his

    source;

    a

    year

    later

    he

    was

    more

    explicit.

    He

    wrote

    to

    Buommattei:

    It is

    Plato's

    opinion

    that

    an

    alteration in

    the

    style

    and

    fashion

    of

    dress

    portends grave

    disorders and

    changes

    in the State.22

    That

    is Plato's

    opinion

    in the Laws; 23 the illustration of clothes

    21

    C.

    E.,

    III,

    305.

    22

    Trans.

    by

    Tillyard,

    p.

    16.

    23 See

    Laws,

    VII,

    797.

  • 7/23/2019 Milton's References to Plato and Socrates

    9/16

    Irene

    Samuel

    57

    is

    given

    only

    once,

    but

    in

    connection

    with

    a doctrine basic

    to

    the

    Laws as

    a

    whole,

    that

    unnecessary

    and

    careless

    change,

    like

    all

    instability,

    is at

    once

    cause

    and

    sign

    of

    decadence.

    Milton,

    though

    it may

    seem

    strange

    for one

    who

    was

    to advocate divorce

    and

    regi-

    cide,

    accepted the

    principle,

    reapplying

    it here

    to

    language

    as

    earn-

    estly as Plato

    had

    applied

    it to dress. Indeed it became

    for

    Milton

    a constant

    principle,

    too little observed

    by

    readers of

    his

    tracts

    on

    religion,

    politics, and

    marriage, who

    naturally

    are

    more

    struck

    by

    its more striking corollary, that needed and deliberate corrections

    of

    evil

    signify

    and

    produce

    vitality.

    Milton's

    political

    writings

    make

    frequent

    use

    of

    various

    Pla-

    tonic

    theories. For

    example,

    The Reason

    of

    Church-Government

    opens

    with the

    words:

    In the

    publishing

    of

    human

    laws,

    which for the

    most

    part

    aim

    not

    beyond

    the good

    of civil

    society, to

    set them

    barely

    forth

    to

    the

    people

    without

    reason

    or

    preface, like

    a

    physical

    prescript,

    or

    only

    with

    threaten-

    ings,

    as

    it

    were a

    lordly

    command,

    in

    the

    judgment of

    Plato

    was thought

    to

    be

    doneneither

    generously

    or wisely.24

    The advice of Plato is then explained in detail and moreover con-

    firmed

    by

    the

    practice of

    Moses.

    A little

    later

    in the

    Preface,

    Plato

    is

    called

    'the wisest

    of the

    heathen;

    '

    25

    and

    throughout the

    tract

    Milton

    consistently

    applies to

    the

    problems of

    church-governtment

    the wise

    doctrine

    he

    had

    found

    repeatedly

    expressed and

    applied

    in

    Plato's Laws:

    persuasion

    educates;

    coercion

    merely

    restrains.

    Milton's

    interest

    at

    the time

    in

    political theory

    would naturally

    lead

    him

    to

    careful

    study of

    the two

    great

    political

    theorists

    of

    antiquity.

    Plato,

    however,

    unlike

    Aristotle,

    had

    presented

    his

    politics

    as

    an

    integrated

    part not

    only

    of his

    ethical, but of his

    entire

    body of

    thought.

    Inevitably

    Milton

    would

    consider

    works

    other

    than

    the

    Republic

    and

    Laws in

    order to

    grasp the

    full

    mean-

    ing

    of

    Plato's

    doctrines on

    the

    state.

    Thus we

    find in

    the

    Reason

    of

    Church-Government

    allusions

    to other

    Platonic

    dialogues,

    not

    primarily

    political.

    'I read,'

    says

    Milton,

    of

    no

    sophister

    among the

    Greeks that

    was so

    dear,

    neither

    Hippias nor

    Protagoras, nor

    any whom

    the

    Socratic

    school

    famously

    refuted

    without

    hire.26

    24

    Preface

    to

    Church-Gov.,C.

    E.,

    III,

    181.

    25

    C. E., III, 182.

    E6

    C.

    .,

    III,

    202;

    and

    see

    the

    table

    for

    other

    references

    in

    The

    Reason

    of

    Church-Government.

  • 7/23/2019 Milton's References to Plato and Socrates

    10/16

    58 Milton's References to Plato and Socrates

    Milton's very use of the term 'Sophist'-and he uses it with

    growing frequency and scorn in his controversial

    writings-appar-

    ently comes from his reading in the Dialogues, though the word

    was surely in his time, as now, a commonplace. At any rate, in his

    Apology for Smectymnuus, he again associates refutation of sophis-

    try with the Socratic method,27 and elsewhere repeats Plato's

    objection that those who deal in truth for hire cannot be true

    teachers.2

    From the Apology for Smectymnuus we further learn that Mil-

    ton did not

    always feel the aversion to 'Atlantic and Utopian poli-

    ties

    '

    that he later expressed in Areopagitica. Here he praises

    that grave and noble

    invention which the

    greatest

    and

    sublimest

    wits in

    sundry ages,

    Plato in

    Critias,

    and our own two

    famous

    countrymen,

    the

    one

    in his

    Utopia,

    the

    other

    in

    his

    New

    Atlantis

    chose,

    I

    may

    not

    say

    as

    a

    field, but as

    a

    mighty

    Continent

    wherein

    to

    display

    the

    largeness

    of

    their

    spirits by teaching

    this

    our world better

    and exacter

    things

    than

    were yet known, or

    used.'6

    Areopagitica

    is

    the

    one

    work

    in which

    Milton ever

    disparaged any

    writing of Plato; and even there Plato remains ' a man of high

    authority indeed,' though

    'least of all

    in

    his

    Commonwealth,

    n the

    book of his

    laws.'

    'I

    Since Milton

    often used the

    authority

    of

    that

    very book to support

    his

    own arguments,

    we

    may suppose

    that not

    the Laws

    in its entirety,

    but

    only its

    advocation of

    censorship

    roused

    his

    dissent;

    and

    surely many another

    Platonist has found it as

    hard

    to reconcile

    himself

    to

    some of the

    legal

    constraints Plato

    seemingly urged.

    But

    Milton,

    be

    it

    noted,

    ends his

    discussion

    of

    the

    censorship

    in the

    Laws

    by commending

    in its

    place

    another

    principle from the same work:

    Nor is

    it Plato's licensing of books will do this [i. e., mend our

    condi-

    tion],

    which

    necessarily pulls along with it

    so

    many other kinds

    of

    licensing; .

    .

    . but those unwritten, or at least unconstraining laws of

    virtuous education, religious and civil nurture, which Plato there men-

    tions, as

    the

    bonds

    and

    ligaments

    of

    the commonwealth, the pillars

    and the

    sustainers

    of

    every

    written

    statute;

    these

    they be,

    which

    will bear

    chief

    sway

    in

    such

    matters as

    these.31

    Plato

    naturally

    has a

    large part

    in

    the treatise Of Education,

    not

    only among

    the books to be

    given

    to

    students,

    but

    in

    the

    theory

    27

    C.

    E.)

    III,

    293-4.

    2R

    See,

    for

    example,

    Pro

    Se

    Defensio,

    C.

    E., IX,

    284-6.

    24

    C.

    E., III,

    294.

    '0

    C.

    E., IV, 316.

    a1

    C.

    E.,

    IV,

    318.

  • 7/23/2019 Milton's References to Plato and Socrates

    11/16

    Irene Samuel 59

    and plan

    of instruction

    there set

    forth.

    And later

    works show

    how

    large a part

    the

    Dialogues

    had

    in

    Milton's own

    self-education.

    Tetrachordon

    cites Plato

    three

    times;

    the first

    D'efensio

    repeatedly

    turns to the

    Laws

    and

    Eighth Fpistle

    for confirmation of its

    politi-

    cal

    theorv;

    and

    in

    the

    Defensio,

    nine

    years

    after the

    Apology for

    Smectymnuus,

    Mlilton reasserts

    his

    old

    judgment by

    naming

    Plato

    among the 'best and wisest men of old' and

    calling

    him

    once

    more

    'divine.'32

    The Dialogues, once carefully studied, kept their hold upon

    Milton.

    Others have

    noted

    with what relative

    lightness

    Plato

    escapes

    Jesus' attack

    on classical

    learning

    in

    Paradise

    Regained.

    We need only add that Milton's

    words

    are

    not

    a

    very serious

    accu-

    sation for

    a

    poet

    to make

    of

    a

    philosopher:

    if

    Plato 'fell' to 'fab-

    ling

    and

    smooth conceits,' his fall

    was

    from

    philosophy to poetry.

    And

    Milton

    did

    indeed think Plato poetical,

    recognizing

    in

    him

    the

    'grave

    and noble'

    facultv

    of

    invention.

    He

    thought

    Plato

    a

    master

    of comic invention

    too,33

    a

    master of educational theory,34

    a

    model

    of

    literary

    decorum,35

    an

    expert in law;

    38

    in

    short he did

    most

    seriously

    accord

    to

    Plato a position

    far above

    any other

    author,

    pagan or Christian, save the authors

    of Holy Scripture. Never to

    Augustine,

    his

    favorite amolng Church-Fathers, to

    Spenser, his

    favorite among English

    poets, to

    Cicero, Erasmus, or Bacon, did

    he

    apply the epithet

    he granted to Plato. And far

    from merely

    adopting a

    conventional term of praise,37 Milton

    showed that he

    independently approved the common

    judgment,

    explaining that

    Plato 'for those his writings hath

    obtain'd the surname of Divine.'

    38

    We

    see that

    Milton

    was

    well

    equipped by study to confirm

    and

    explain the ancient judgment. Note in the table of references how

    often he

    alludes

    to

    a

    specific passage in Plato; note from

    how wide

    a

    range

    in

    the

    Dialogues

    and

    Epistles his allusions are

    drawn, and

    with

    what precision

    he refers to the

    Laws and Epistles, the least

    generally read of

    Plato's works. If the references he

    took from

    sa

    C.

    E.,

    VII,

    350.

    See

    Ap.

    Smect.,

    C.

    E.,

    III,

    293-4;

    Tetrach.,

    C.

    E.,

    IVy

    76.

    O4

    f

    Ed.,

    C. E.,

    IV,

    287.

    36

    See

    Pro

    Se

    Def.,

    C.

    E.,

    IX,

    176.

    I

    See

    D.

    D.

    D.,

    C.

    E.,

    III,

    458.

    37

    At

    least

    as

    early as

    Athenaeus

    he

    was

    6

    OEcoLraros

    lXarwv.

    See

    Deipnosophists,

    x, 440b.

    38

    Ap.

    Smect.,

    C.

    E.,

    III,

    293-4.

  • 7/23/2019 Milton's References to Plato and Socrates

    12/16

    60

    Milton's

    References to Plato

    anrd Socrates

    Downham's

    commentary on

    Rlamus should not be counted as

    Mil-

    ton's own, the

    choice at

    least

    is his,

    since he omitted innumerable

    others

    in

    condensing

    Downham's work.

    And two

    changes

    he made

    in

    Downham's

    citations are

    clear proof

    that

    what he took

    unchanged,

    he

    took with full

    knowledge

    of the

    works

    alluded to.

    Once, where

    Downham

    had

    omitted the

    specific

    source, Milton

    supplied

    Phae-

    drus;

    '

    and

    again,

    to

    Downham's

    illustrative

    phrase, 'philosophus

    pro

    Aristotle,' Milton

    significantly

    added 'aut

    Platone.' 40

    From the two amendments we may learn, first, Milton's ability

    independently to

    supply the

    precise

    dialogue of

    Plato when his

    source failed

    to name

    it,

    and

    further

    his

    unwillingness

    to

    have

    the

    term

    'the

    philosopher'

    stand, even

    in

    one short

    phrase,

    for

    any

    other

    alone

    without

    mention of Plato.

    Briefly,

    both amendments

    confirm

    Milton's

    thorough

    knowledge of and enthusiastic admira-

    tion for

    Plato's work.

    What

    that

    knowledge

    and enthusiasm meant

    in his own

    thought and

    writing we have

    as

    yet hardly

    begun

    to

    probe. For

    put

    Paradise

    Lost and Paradise

    Regained

    to the same

    test

    as

    we

    put Comus

    earlier,

    and

    we

    get

    a

    startlingly

    different

    result. Suppose Plato dealing with the loss of human happiness,

    would he

    give the same

    explanation as

    Milton in

    the

    tale of man's

    fall?

    On the

    whole,

    we may

    say yes.

    True,

    he would

    conceive

    of

    no

    such perfect

    providence

    watching-and

    waiting to relieve-

    mankind's errors.

    And

    Plato, to be

    sure,

    never tarried

    so

    long

    in

    Hell

    as Milton.

    Doubtless the

    Hebraic view

    of life

    brings to

    its

    disciples greater

    struggles as

    well

    as greater

    aspirations

    than

    Hlel-

    lenism

    at its best.

    But

    if

    we

    look

    aside from

    Hell and

    Heaven to

    Earth,

    where

    Milton after all

    wished

    us to

    fix

    our

    gaze

    most

    steadily,

    and discern in the struggle there ensuing the meaning as Milton

    discerned it, we

    can

    see

    that, however

    little the

    words and

    acts

    resemble

    those of

    a Platonic

    dialogue,

    the

    underlying

    argument is

    largely

    Plato's. And

    when we

    turn to

    Paradise

    Regained,

    where a

    bolder

    Sophist than any

    opponent

    of

    Socrates defies

    a more

    glorious

    seeker

    after

    truth,

    even if the

    very

    dialectical

    method of

    Jesus'

    victory did

    not

    point to the

    Dialogues as a

    model, the

    themes and

    arguments

    are, we

    conceive,

    very

    nearly what

    Plato would

    have

    written

    had

    he-as in

    the

    nature of

    things he

    could not

    have-

    treated

    a

    like

    subject.

    ao

    See

    in the

    appended

    table

    the note

    to the

    reference

    Logic, C.

    E.,

    XI,

    *22.

    4

    See

    the

    note to

    Logic,

    C.

    E., XI,

    **334.

  • 7/23/2019 Milton's References to Plato and Socrates

    13/16

    Irene

    Samuel

    61

    We

    can see

    and

    we

    conceive-but

    only

    after careful

    comparison

    of Milton's

    thought

    with

    Plato's;

    and while the

    reader awaits

    that

    comparison,

    he may grant

    the

    need of

    it from the

    number

    and

    variety

    of

    Milton's references.

    A

    TABLE

    OF MILTON'S

    REFERENCES

    TO

    SOCRATES

    AND

    PLATO

    Passage

    Date

    Source Quoted

    S

    Eleg.

    4.

    23-4

    1627 ?t

    Aloib., 103 ff.,

    135

    Agar 15

    P

    Idea Plat. 1628

    passim; esp.

    ?Phaedo, Agar

    16

    or

    later ?Phaedr.,

    ?Sym.,

    ?Rep.

    P

    Prolus.

    2, C.

    E.

    12. 150

    1625-9 ?Rep. 10. 616-7

    Agar

    76

    Prolus.

    6, C. E. 12

    1625-9

    S

    *218

    ?Apol. 20-3

    S

    *238

    passim

    Prolus. 7, C. E. 12

    1625-9

    P

    262-4

    Agar 77

    S

    *280

    passim

    P

    II Pen. 87-96

    1631-4

    ?Tim.

    41-2

    Agar

    5

    1

    The

    symbols

    used

    in

    the table

    are as

    follows:

    S

    and

    P

    indicate references

    to

    Socrates

    and

    Plato. Parentheses

    are

    used

    to

    distinguish

    implicit

    references,

    as

    in

    the

    letter to

    Diodati,

    where

    Milton

    quotes

    Phaedrus, but

    does not

    name

    his

    source.

    The

    single

    asterisk marks

    a

    reference

    not

    given

    in

    Agar's

    Milton

    and

    Plato.

    The

    double

    asterisk

    marks a

    reference given

    neither

    in

    the Columbia

    Index nor

    by

    Agar.

    .0.

    B.

    with

    Arabic

    numbers

    following

    refers to the

    Columbia

    edition

    of

    The Works

    of

    John

    Milton,

    volume

    and

    page. The

    numbers

    in

    parentheses

    correspond to

    Milton's own

    divisions.

    A question nmark before a title indicates uncertainty in assigning the

    allusion

    to

    any specific

    work

    of

    Plato.

    The

    number after

    Agar

    refers

    to

    the

    passage in the

    Appendix

    of Agar's

    volume where

    the selection is

    quoted.

    The

    page-number

    after Downham

    marks

    the

    place in

    the

    work of

    George

    Downham,

    Rami

    Dialecticae Libri

    D1uo

    cum Comm

    entariis

    (London,

    1669),

    which

    is the

    source of

    Milton's

    reference.

    Milton,

    of

    course,

    used an

    earlier

    edition

    of

    Downham's

    commentary.

    The list

    does

    not

    include those

    passages in

    the

    Logic where

    Socrates is

    named

    merely

    as

    a

    convenient

    Everyman

    of

    argument.

    2

    The most

    likely

    source is

    Diogenes

    Laertius,

    Life of

    Socrates,

    36-8.

    See

    also

    Xenophon's

    Banquet

    2.

    10.

    Diogenes

    Laertius seems

    to take

    the

    statement of the oracle

    from

    Plato's

    Apology

    and

    the

    character

    of

    Xanthippe

    from

    Xenophon.

  • 7/23/2019 Milton's References to Plato and Socrates

    14/16

    62

    Milton's

    References

    to Plato

    and

    Socrates

    Passage

    Date Source

    Quoted

    [P]

    To

    Dio.,

    C. E. 12. 26 1637 Phaedr.

    Agar

    72

    P To Buom.,

    C. E.

    12. 32 1638 Laws 7. 797-8 Agar 73

    P

    Of Ref., C.

    E. 3. 39 1641

    ?Rep., esp.

    4.

    420; Agar

    53

    ?Laws, esp.

    5. 739

    S

    *Animad.,

    C. E. 3. 161 1641

    (Xenophon)3

    Church-Gov.,

    C.

    E. 3 1642

    P *181-2 (Preface)

    Laws 4. 718 ff.

    S

    *202

    (1. 5) passim; esp. Protag., ?Hipp.

    Jfin.

    P 264 (2. 3) Soph. 230; '?Gorg.476ff. Agar 54

    Ap. Smect.,

    C. E. 3 1642

    PS 293-4

    passim

    Agar

    55

    P

    *294 Critias

    P

    305

    passim;

    esp.

    Phaedr., Sym.

    Agar 57

    D. D.

    D., C. E.

    3. 1643

    PS 398 (1.4)

    Sym. 203

    Agar 58

    P

    441 (2.3)

    passim; esp. Thaws 1. 644-5;

    WMenro

    9-100

    Agar

    60

    P

    *458-9 (2.9)

    Laws

    4. 719

    P

    464 (2.11)

    Protag. 354 e, 355-8; et al. Agar 61

    Cf.

    Memo 77-8,

    Tim. 86

    SP 500-1 (2.21) Gorg. 482-4, 488-510 Agar 62

    Judg. Bucer,

    C. E. 4 1644

    P

    *24 (17 on Matth. v. 19)

    (Bucer)

    5

    ?Rep.,

    ?Laws

    Areop., C. E. 4. 1644

    P

    299

    Agar

    44

    P 316

    Rep., Laws

    Agar 46

    p

    317

    Rep. 3; Laws 2, 7 Agar

    47

    P 318

    Rep. 4; Laws 1, 7 Agar

    48

    Of Ed., C. E. 4 1644

    S

    281

    Agar 66

    P

    284

    passim

    Agar 67

    P 286 passim; esp. Phaedr., Gorg. Agar 68

    P

    287

    passim and Laws 1. 634-5 Agar 69

    [PIS

    Eleg. 7, Postscript before

    passim; esp. Phaedr.,

    Sym.

    1645

    Tetrach., C. E. 4 1645

    s This is the sole reference to Socrates in which Milton uses

    Xenophon

    alone as the authority. See Xenophon, Apology, 26; Memorabilia I.

    2.

    1-8; I. 6.

    11-3.

    '

    The first part of the reference comes from Diogenes Laertius, Life

    of

    Plato, 18; the second from Milton's own reading of the Dialogues.

    'That

    detractor in Athenaeus ' is probably Pontianus in Deipnosophists II. 504 b-

    509

    e.

    IApparently taken from Martin Bucer, Of the Kingdom of

    Christ,

    Chap. 17.

  • 7/23/2019 Milton's References to Plato and Socrates

    15/16

    Irene Samuel

    63

    Passage

    Date

    Source

    Quoted

    S *70

    (To Parl.)

    ?Apol.

    19

    P

    *76

    (on

    Gen. i.

    27)

    Sym.

    189-93

    P

    81

    (on

    Gen.

    i.

    28)

    Laws

    6.

    773-6,

    783-5

    Agar

    63

    P

    *157-8 (on

    Matth.

    xix.

    7-8) Rep.

    Def.,

    C.

    E. 7.

    1651

    P 158 (3)

    Rep.

    5. 463.

    Cf. Laws

    4.

    715

    P

    166-8 (3)

    Laws

    4.715; VIIIEpist.354

    Agar

    40

    P 304-6 (5)

    VIII Epist.

    355

    Agar

    41

    P

    *348-50 (6)

    VIII

    Epist.

    354-5

    S Def. Sec., C. E. 8.192 1654 ?A.pol. 20-3

    Pro Se Def.,

    C. E. 9.

    1655

    S

    *52

    ?Apol.

    S[P]

    *112

    passim

    PS *176

    passim

    p

    *180-2

    P P. L. 3. 471-3

    before

    Agar

    18

    1667

    Grammar,C.

    E. 6

    1669

    P

    **329 (2. Of the

    Con-

    cords)

    SP *1349 (2. of the Con-

    junctions)

    Logic, C. E.

    11.

    1670

    Downham.

    P

    *10 (Preface)

    Theaet.

    202 e Proleg., p. 19

    P

    **12 (Preface)

    Gorg.

    448

    Proleg.,

    p. 22

    P

    *18-20 (1.1)

    Crat., IAlcib.

    129

    c pp.

    3-4

    P

    *22 (1. 2)

    Phaedr.

    235-6, 264

    p. 15

    5

    PS *58

    (1.

    7)

    passim

    (and Diogenes

    p. 79

    Laertius)

    P

    *66

    (1. 8)

    Phil.

    54

    p.88

    P

    *96

    (1.11)

    Rep. 3. 405

    7

    p.122

    S

    [PI

    *140-2

    (1. 16)

    Crito

    44

    p. 164

    P *150 (1. 18) p. 177

    Milton

    gives

    the source

    as Phaedrus

    where

    Downham

    had

    simply said,

    'Atque

    hanc

    distributionem

    ]Plato

    videtur

    primus

    attigisse.'

    7

    Milton's

    translator

    in the

    Columbia

    edition, Allan H.

    Gilbert, makes

    a

    serious

    mistake

    here. Quoting

    Downham,

    Milton

    writes:

    'Hoc

    argu-

    mento

    Plato

    miseras

    civitates

    auguratur,

    quae

    medicorum et

    judicum

    multitudine

    indigeant,

    quia

    multum

    quoque et

    intemperantiam

    et injusti-

    tiam

    in ea

    civitate versari

    necesse

    est.' The

    translation

    given

    is:

    '

    By

    means of this

    argument

    Plato

    conjectures that

    those

    states are

    wretched

    which lack a

    multitude

    of

    physicians

    and

    judges, since

    necessarily

    much

    intemperance and injustice will be practised in such a state. ' Clearly

    Plato

    says the

    very opposite

    in

    the Republic

    3. 405,

    and

    Milton's

    '

    multi-

    tudine

    indigeant' must mean

    'are

    poor

    with their

    multitude.'

  • 7/23/2019 Milton's References to Plato and Socrates

    16/16

    64

    Milton's

    References to

    Plato

    and Socrates

    Passage Date

    Source

    Quoted

    S

    *166 (1.18)

    P *200 (1. 21) Laws

    3,

    Phaedo 92

    p.209

    S

    204

    (1.21)

    p. 212

    S *228

    (1. 25)

    (Aristotle) p. 242

    P

    *228-30 (1. 25)

    ?Phil.

    16-8, pp.

    243-4

    ?Statesm. 287

    S

    238 (1. 27)

    passim

    and Meno 72-7 pp.

    249-50

    P

    *240

    (1.27)

    Statesm.

    p.251

    P

    #286 (1.33)

    Rep. 5. 473 p.290

    P *308 (2.3) Crat. ?431 p.324

    P ?*334 (2.4)

    p.365

    P

    *470 (2.17)

    Phil.

    16 p.472

    P 474 (2.17) ?Phaedr.,

    ?Statesm.

    p.428

    P **494 (Praxis)

    ?Tim.

    p. 47

    P.R.

    1671

    S

    3.

    96-9

    passim; esp. ?Apol.

    29-

    Agar

    35

    31,

    36-42; ?Crito,

    ?Phaedo

    P 4. 244-7

    Agar

    37

    S

    [P]

    *4. 272-8 ?Apol.

    20-3

    BP 4. 293-5 passim Agar 38

    ?On Worthy Master t

    Shakespeare, C.

    E. 18. 361

    P **15-8

    Tim.

    39

    @

    Downham

    had

    written,

    'ut Poeta

    pro Homero aut Virgilio:

    philoso-

    phus pro Aristotele: orator pro Demosthene aut Cicerone.' Milton inserts

    Plato as

    one

    for whom philosophus

    may stand:

    'ut

    poets pro

    Homero

    aut Virgilio,

    Philosophus

    pro Aristotele

    aut Platone et similia.'